Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Abolishing the Death Penalty: An Untested Legal Argument

  • Published:
American Journal of Criminal Justice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper supplies the logical and substantive framework for an untested challenge to the legality of the death penalty in the United States. As such, it yields a novel strategy for appellants and supporting amici seeking review of capital cases in the United States Supreme Court. With twin reliance on the right of the people to reparation for harm wrongly inflicted by others and their constitutional right to Due Process of Law under the Fourteenth Amendment, this paper advances the argument that the mere possibility of a wrongful execution yields an imperative for abolishment of capital punishment by the Court.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For an earlier presentation of the initial phase of the argument, together with an account of its theoretical moorings in Locke’s Second Treatise, see Sarver (2012) (which contrasts Locke’s familiar argument for the death penalty in the Second Treatise and urges a Lockean argument against the death penalty better reflects the prevailing tenor of his treatise and appears to be on more secure footing within the general framework of his theory of the social contract). For a preliminary draft of all three phases of the argument with annotations, see Sarver (2013).

  2. Writing for the Court, Chief Justice Rehnquist held that petitioner failed to make a showing of “actual innocence” linked to “an independent constitutional violation occurring in the underlying state criminal proceeding,” a requirement for federal habeas relief; and that, “for the sake of argument in this case, . . . [if] in a capital case a truly persuasive demonstration of ‘actual innocence’ [were to be] made after trial[,] [that] would render the execution of a defendant unconstitutional, and warrant federal habeas relief if there were no state avenue open to process such a claim,” (at 417). While Rehnquist left the door open here for a demonstration of “actual innocence” in future cases, he made it clear that “[t]he showing made by petitioner in this case falls far short of any such threshold” (ibid.) Agreeing with the decision of the Court, but for different reasons, Justice O’Conner held that “the proper disposition of this case is neither difficult nor troubling” because of the “fundamental fact” that “[p]etitioner is not innocent, in any sense of the word,” (at 419). In effect, she held that, not only had the record at trial established the guilt of petitioner under the law, it also warranted the conclusion that he could not possibly have been factually innocent of the crimes for which he was sentenced to die. Another point of difference with Rehnquist’s opinion is the weight O’Connor would assign to the execution of a legally and factually innocent person, were this ever to occur. While Rehnquist does not elaborate on the aftermath of a wrongful execution, O’Connor observed an “event” of this kind would be “constitutionally intolerable,” (supra); yet enigmatically, she fails to explain why. Against this backdrop, the argument of this paper seeks to explain why O’Connor was right in her observation, but wrong to exclude the possibility of factual innocence for the petitioner in Herrera. In contrast with the petitioner’s failed strategy, this new and untested argument does not turn on a showing of “actual innocence” at all, but instead relies on the mere assertion of possible innocence, which, as will be elaborated in the second phase of the argument, is a possibility that may not be discounted, even when the chance of error appears infinitesimally small in a particular case, as, e.g., it probably does for most observers of Herrera. Moreover, under the impress of this constraint, the final phase of the argument then seeks to open a constitutional pathway to abolition of the death penalty by linking this assertion to the constitutional right of Due Process of Law under the Fourteenth Amendment and the right of the people to reparation for harm wrongly inflicted by others. In fairness to O’Connor and even the petitioner, for that matter, this is not a strategy that could have been attempted in 1993. This is because the argument relies on empirical assumptions drawn from an emergent literature of the social sciences that has only in more recent times become sufficiently robust to have probative weight before the Court; and for the further reason that the strategy itself did not fully emerge until late in 2012 (See n. 1, supra).

  3. Other developments included the emergence of innocence projects at several prominent American law schools, among them Duke University School of Law, Northwestern University School of Law, University of North Carolina School of Law, University of Washington School of Law, and University of Wisconsin School of Law; and a gubernatorial moratorium on the death penalty in Illinois. For a brief overview of then Governor George Ryan’s decision and a discussion of related issues, see White (2001).

  4. These analyses appear also in Sarver (2012), at 186–187.

  5. At times the Court has employed other less often cited language in qualifying a fundamental right of the people under the Due Process Clause; see, e.g., Rochin, at 172 (“shocks the conscience”), which also would have merit as a standard for the present argument.

  6. Locke’s impact on the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment has been extensive, formative in its early development and substantive in its contemporary application. See D. G. Smith (2002) (characterizing section one of the Fourteenth Amendment as a remedy for “defects” or “imperfections” in the Lockean state of nature, with the Due Process Clause serving the purpose of rectifying “the lack of a known and indifferent judge” p. 1147). See also Koehlinger (1990) (“The Lockean liberal tradition. . . offers a . . . principled and organized method for determining the substantive content of an individual’s ‘life, liberty, and property’ rights under the due process clauses . . .,” p. 725).

  7. In this final phase of the argument, the language of the Fourteenth Amendment is preferred over that of the Fifth because the former expressly affirms what the states may not do, while the latter asserts more generally what may not be done to a person. See U. S. Const. amend. XIV, § 1 (“. . . nor shall any State deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law”); cf. U. S. Const. amend. V (“nor shall any person . . . be deprived of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law”). While this distinction is subtle, it is one worth making , as the states are the primary instrument of the death penalty in the United States.

  8. The need for a constitutional remedy may be implied, though not addressed, by the Takings Clause of the Fifth Amendment. See U. S. Const. amend. V (“. . . nor shall private property be taken for public use without just compensation”). For a recent discussion of takings logic applied to the plight of those who have been wrongfully convicted and imprisoned, see especially Master (2004) (analyses intended to show “that eminent domain principles may compel governments to compensate individuals who have been wrongfully convicted and imprisoned,” p. 97). An instructive limitation of this line of reasoning, if accepted by the Court, would be that it affords no relief to the victim of a wrongful execution. While this underscores the need for a categorical exclusion of the death penalty, the clause itself fails to supply any ground for relief.

  9. Between January 1, 2007, and August 5, 2013, six states abolished the death penalty (New Jersey, New York, New Mexico, Illinois, Connecticut, and Maryland), while over this same time period, 258 executions were carried out, with 219 (76.6 %) of these occurring in just six states (Texas, Ohio, Oklahoma, Alabama, Mississippi, and Florida). See Death Penalty Information Center. States With and Without the Death Penalty; Executions in the United States [2007–2013]. Data files available at http://www.deathpenaltyinfo.org (last visited September 4, 2013).

  10. This is not a far-fetched possibility. Among plausible candidates, see, e.g., Liebman, Crowley, Markquart, Rosenberg, White and Zharkovsky (2012) (documenting Carlos DeLuna’s claim of factual innocence and concluding with reference to Justice Scalia’s rooftop allusion, “We believe that the story of Carlos DeLuna represents such a case,” p. 1118); Ryan (2012) (featuring the case of Cameron Todd Willingham and describing it as what may eventually become “the first . . . in the United States in which an executed individual has been exonerated” p. 273).

References

  • Aristotle (350 BCE). (1941). Nicomachean ethics, Book V. In R. McKeon (Ed.), The basic works of Aristotle. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bush, G.W. (2005). State of the union address. The New York Times, p. A22.

  • Death Penalty Information Center (2013). States with and without the death penalty; Executions in the United States [2007–2013]. Data files available at http://www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/ (last visited September 4).

  • Doernberg, D. L. (1985). We the people: John Locke, collective constitutional rights, and standing to challenge government action. California Law Review, 73, 52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gross, S. R. (1996). The risks of death: Why erroneous convictions are common in capital cases. Buffalo Law Review, 44, 469.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, S. R., Jacoby, K., Matheson, D. J., Montgomery, N., & Patil, S. (2005). Exonerations in the United States 1989 through 2003. Texas Tech Law Review, 95, 523.

    Google Scholar 

  • Justice for All Act of 2004, Pub. L. No. 108–405, 118 Stat. 2260 (2004).

  • Koehlinger, J. S. (1990). Substantive due process analysis and the Lockean liberal tradition: Rethinking the modern privacy cases. Indiana Law Journal, 65, 723.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krotoszynski, R. J., Jr. (1997). On the danger of wearing two hats: Mistretta and Morrison revisited. William & Mary Law Review, 38, 417.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liebman, J. S., Crowley, S., Markquart, A., Rosenberg, L., White, L. G., & Zharkovsky, D. (2012). Los Tocayos Carlos. Columbia Human Rights Law Review, 43, 711.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1690). Second treatise on civil government. In E. Barker (Ed.), Social contract (1962). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Master, H. S. (2004). Revisiting the takings-based argument for compensating the wrongfully convicted. New York University Annual Survey of American Law, 60, 97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radelet, M. L. (2008). The role of the innocence argument in contemporary death penalty debates. Texas Tech Law Review, 41, 199.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radelet, M. L., Bedau, H. A., & Putnam, C. E. (1992). In spite of innocence: Erroneous convictions in capital cases. Boston: Northeastern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Risinger, D. M. (2007). Innocents convicted: An empirically justified wrongful conviction rate. Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 97, 761.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryan, M. J. (2012). Remedying wrongful execution. University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform, 45, 261.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarver, V. T., Jr. (2012). A Lockean argument against the death penalty. British Journal of American Legal Studies, 1, 173.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarver, V. T., Jr. (2013). A due process challenge to the constitutionality of the death penalty in the United States. Amicus Journal, 30, 18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, D. G. (2002). A Lockean analysis of section one of the fourteenth amendment. Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy, 25, 1094.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B. P. (2005). The history of wrongful execution. Hastings Law Journal, 56, 1185.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, L. S. (2005). “Religion-neutral” jurisprudence: An examination of its meaning and end. William & Mary Bill of Rights Journal, 13, 841.

    Google Scholar 

  • van den Haag, E. (1986). The ultimate punishment: A defense. Harvard Law Review, 99, 1662.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warden, R. (2009). Reflections on capital punishment. Northwestern Journal of Law & Social Policy, 4, 329.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, P. J. (2001). Errors and ethics: Dilemmas in death. Hofstra Law Review, 29, 1265.

    Google Scholar 

Cases Cited

  • Herrera v. Collins, 506 U. S. 390 (1993)

  • Schlup v. Delo, 513 U. S. 298 (1995)

  • Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137 (1803)

  • Furman v. Georgia, 408 U. S. 238 (1972)

  • Spaziano v. Florida, 468 U. S. 447 (1984)

  • Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U. S. 153 (1976)

  • Kansas v. Marsh, 548 U. S. 163 (2006)

  • Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U. S. 479 (1965)

  • Snyder v. Massachusetts, 291 U. S. 97 (1934)

  • Palco v. Connecticut, 302 U. S. 319 (1937)

  • Rochin v. California, 352 U. S. 165 (1952)

  • Skinner v. Oklahoma ex rel. Williamson, 316 U. S. 535 (1942)

  • Loving v. Virginia, 388 U. S. 1 (1967)

  • Ford v. Wainwright, 477 U. S. 399 (1986)

  • Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U.S. 304 (2002)

  • Roper v. Simmons, 543 U. S. 551 (2005)

  • Trop v. Dulles, 356 U. S. 86, 101 (1958)

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Vernon Thomas Sarver Jr..

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sarver, V.T. Abolishing the Death Penalty: An Untested Legal Argument. Am J Crim Just 39, 808–817 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12103-014-9264-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12103-014-9264-4

Keywords

Navigation