Skip to main content
Log in

Second-Guessing Scientists and Engineers: Post Hoc Criticism and the Reform of Practice in Green Chemistry and Engineering

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Science and Engineering Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The article examines and extends work bringing together engineering ethics and Science and Technology Studies, which had built upon Diane Vaughan’s analysis of the Challenger shuttle accident as a test case. Reconsidering the use of her term “normalization of deviance,” the article argues for a middle path between moralizing against and excusing away engineering practices contributing to engineering disaster. To explore an illustrative pedagogical case and to suggest avenues for constructive research developing this middle path, it examines the emergence of green chemistry and green engineering. Green chemistry began when Paul Anastas and John Warner developed a set of new rules for chemical synthesis that sought to learn from missed opportunities to avoid environmental damage in the twentieth century, an approach that was soon extended to engineering as well. Examination of tacit assumptions about historical counterfactuals in recent, interdisciplinary discussions of green chemistry illuminate competing views about the field’s prospects. An integrated perspective is sought, addressing how both technical practice within chemistry and engineering and the influence of a wider “social movement” can play a role in remedying environmental problems.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. But see Pinkus et al. (1997), pp. 318–319, on the possibility of having found a correlation of O-ring damage with temperature across all flights, not just those with field joint problems.

  2. On the tendency for students reading Vaughan to excuse engineers from responsibility, as well as pedagogical techniques for overcoming this tendency, see Kline (2001/2002).

  3. Jasanoff (1991) observes that the British regulatory regime incorporates engineering judgment, while the U.S. approach excludes it for quantitative proof.

  4. More generally, citation of Perrow (1984) has functioned within STS to reinforce skepticism that anything can be done to prevent disaster in complex systems.

  5. Some work has already been done, particularly on the way national cultures have shaped engineering practice, with Americans oriented to industry and the French to government, for instance, or the ways in which educational requirements served to bolster the low status of engineers in Britain (Downey 2007; Brown et al. 2009). The impact of warfare on engineering generally and the role of Cold War politics on directing military innovation in particular have received much attention (Walton 2005; Mitcham 2009). Finally, it is a truism within engineering ethics that engineering is a “captive profession” in that engineers working in corporations will be much more susceptible to corporate concern with maximizing profit than with professional obligations to protect public welfare (Davis 1998, p. 22).

  6. For arguments identifying branching points in political history, see Lebow (2010).

  7. A special section of New Scientist (2005), 187 (2513): 34–46, was dedicated to counterfactuals in the history of science.

  8. For a similar critique of green engineering and green business initiatives, see Jamison (2013).

  9. See the link for green chemistry at www.acs.org. Numerous links can also be found at the Michigan Green Chemistry Clearinghouse at migreenchemistry.org, including reference to state initiatives in California, Michigan, Minnesota, New York, Oregon, and Washington. Michigan offers a Green Chemistry Governor’s Award, announced at an annual conference.

  10. See Collins (1988) on premature consensus achieved as the result of a restriction of the core set.

  11. On the limitations of green chemistry as a social movement to fundamentally alter how chemistry is done, see Roberts (2005, Ch. 4) and Woodhouse and Breyman (2005).

  12. Linthorst (2010) argues that green chemistry “is not a scientific specialty with a coherent conducted paradigm.” In contrast to Linthorst, Roberts (2005, p. 79) argues that Green Chemistry’s first editor, James Clark, “drew heavily from the mission established in [Anastas and Warner’s Green Chemistry: Theory and Practice]” and credited U.S. colleagues for why the journal was entitled Green Chemistry despite intense debate on the question.

  13. The Presidential Green Chemistry Challenge Awards have recognized numerous innovations by chemical companies. The Michigan Green Chemistry Governor’s Awards are split between academic and business categories. The 2012 business award went to Dow Chemical, based in Midland, Michigan, for a flame retardant less persistent in the environment. The Michigan Green Chemistry and Engineering Conference is supported by state, corporate, and university funding.

  14. For an endorsement of embracing risk over caution, see Fuller (2012). Most reports of the social and ethical implications of emerging technologies call for after-the-fact regulation, but reject consideration of stopping or altering developments. See, for example, Roco and Bainbridge (2003), pp. 4–7, 16–21.

References

  • Allen, D. T., & Shonnard, D. R. (2001). Environmentally conscious design of chemical processes. New York: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anastas, P. T., & Warner, J. C. (1998). Green chemistry: Theory and practice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anastas, P. T., & Zimmerman, J. B. (2003). Design through the 12 principles of green engineering. Environmental Science and Engineering, 37(5), 94A–101A.

    Google Scholar 

  • Azapagic, A. (2002). Life-cycle assessment: A tool for identification of more sustainable products and processes. In J. H. Clark & D. Macquarrie (Eds.), Handbook of green chemistry and technology (pp. 62–85). Oxford: Blackwell Science.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, B. (1977). Interests and the growth of knowledge. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Basart, J. M., & Serra, M. (2013). Engineering ethics beyond engineers’ ethics. Science and Engineering Ethics, 19(1), 179–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. H., Downey, G., & Doigo, M. P. (Eds.) (2009). Engineering Education, special issue, Technology and Culture, 50(4), 737–838.

  • Carson, R. (1962). Silent spring. New York: Fawcett Crest.

  • Castleman, B. I., & Zeim, G. E. (1989). Toxic pollutants, science, and corporate influence. Archives of Environmental Health, 44(2), 68–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colburn, T., Dumanoski, D., & Myers, J. P. (1997). Our stolen future: Are we threatening our fertility, intelligence, and survival? A scientific detective story. New York: Plume.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H. M. (1981). Stages in the empirical programme of relativism. Social Studies of Science, 11(1), 3–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H. M. (1988). Public experiments and displays of virtuosity: The core-set revisited. Social Studies of Science, 18, 725–748.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conlon, E., & Zandvoort, H. (2011). Broadening ethics teaching in engineering: Beyond the individualistic approach. Science and Engineering Ethics, 17, 217–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daemmrich, A., & Greene, J. (2010). From visible harm to relative risk: Centralization and fragmentation of pharmacovigilance. In E. Elhauge (Ed.), The fragmentation of U.S. healthcare: Causes and solutions (pp. 301–322). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, M. (1998). Thinking like an engineer: Studies in the ethics of a profession. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, M. (2006). Engineering ethics, individuals, and organizations. Science and Engineering Ethics, 12(2), 223–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doing, P. A. (2012). Applying ethnographic insight to engineering ethics: Epistemography and accountability in the space shuttle Challenger failure and the Macondo well blowout. Engineering Studies, 4(3), 233–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doorn, N. (2012). Responsibility ascriptions in technology development and engineering: Three perspectives. Science and Engineering Ethics, 18, 69–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downey, G. (2007). Distance from Manual Labor: British Improvement, English Character, and Engineering Formation, 1760–1914. Society for Social Studies of Science, October 13, 2007.

  • Edwards, P. N. (1996). The closed world: Computers and the politics of discourse in cold war America. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1979). Logic and society: Contradictions and possible worlds. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, E. (2011). Editorial overview: Public science and technology scholars? Engaging whom? Science and Engineering Ethics, 17(4), 607–620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frickel, S., Gibbon, S., Howard, J., Kempner, J., Ottinger, G., & Hess, D. J. (2010). Undone science: Charting social movement and civil society challenges to research agenda setting. Science, Technology and Human Values, 35(4), 444–473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frickel, S., & Moore, K. (Eds.). (2006). The new political sociology of science: Institutions, networks, and power. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, S. (2012). Precautionary and proactionary as the New Right and the New Left of the twenty-first century ideological spectrum. International Journal of Politics, Culture, and Society, 25(4), 157–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, S., & Collier, J. H. (2004). Philosophy, rhetoric and the end of knowledge: A new beginning for science and technology studies (2nd ed.). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graedel, T. E. (2002). Green chemistry and sustainable development. In J. H. Clark & D. Macquarrie (Eds.), Handbook of green chemistry and technology (pp. 56–61). Oxford: Blackwell Science.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, D. J. (1989). Primate visions: Gender, race, and nature in the world of modern science. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, C. E., Pritchard, M. S., & Rabins, M. (1995). Engineering ethics: Concepts and cases. Belmont: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, F. P. (2012). Explaining the Iraq war: Counterfactual theory, logic, and evidence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herkert, J. R. (2001). Future directions in engineering ethics research: Microethics, macroethics and the role of professional societies. Science and Engineering Ethics, 7(3), 403–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herkert, J. R. (2003). Professional societies, microethics, and macroethics: Product liability as an ethical issue in engineering design. International Journal of Engineering Education, 19(1), 163–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herkert, J. R. (2005). Ways of thinking about and teaching ethical problem solving: Microethics and macroethics in engineering. Science and Engineering Ethics, 11(3), 373–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jablokow, K. W. (2007). Engineers as problem-solving leaders: Embracing the humanities. IEEE Technology and Society Magazine, Winter: 29–35.

  • Jamison, Dale. (2013). The making of green engineers: Sustainable development and the hybrid imagination. San Rafael: Morgan and Claypool.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jasanoff, S. (1991). Acceptable evidence in a pluralistic society. In D. Mayo & R. D. Hollander (Eds.), Acceptable evidence: Science and values in risk management (pp. 29–47). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Jolly, J. C. (2003). Thresholds of uncertainty: Radiation and responsibility in the fallout controversy. PhD dissertation, Oregon State University.

  • Kathren, R. L. (1996). Pathway to a paradigm: The linear nonthreshold dose-response model in historical context. Health Physics, 70, 376–90.

  • Kirsch, D. (2000). The electric vehicle and the burden of history. East Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kline, R. R. (2001/2002). Using history and sociology to teach engineering ethics. IEEE Technology and Society Magazine, Winter: 13–20.

  • Kumar, A. (2013). Historical development of green chemistry. The Chemical Educator, 18, 50–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1996). Aramis, or the love of technology. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lebow, N. L. (2010). Forbidden fruit: Counterfactuals and international relations. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Li, J., & Fu, S. (2012). A systematic approach to engineering ethics education. Science and Engineering Ethics, 18, 339–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Linthorst, J. A. (2010). An overview: Origins and development of green chemistry. Foundations of Chemistry, 12, 55–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, W. T., & Kline, R. (2000). Engineering practice and engineering ethics. Science, Technology and Human Values, 25(2), 195–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, D. (1990). Inventing accuracy: A historical sociology of nuclear missile guidance. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marteel-Parrish, A. E., & Abraham, Martin A. (2013). Green chemistry and engineering: A pathway to sustainability. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, K. (2002). Green catalysts for industry. In J. H. Clark & D. Macquarrie (Eds.), Handbook of green chemistry and technology (pp. 321–377). Oxford: Blackwell Science.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mitcham, C. (2009). A historico-ethical perspective on engineering education: From use and convenience to policy engagement. Engineering Studies, 1(1), 35–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ozaktas, H. M. (2013). Teaching Science, Technology, and Society to engineering students: A sixteen year journey. Science and Engineering Ethics, 19(4), 1439–1450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perrow, C. (1984). Normal accidents: Living with high risk technologies. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinkus, L. B., Shuman, L. J., Hummon, N. P., & Wolfe, H. (1997). Engineering ethics: Balancing cost, schedule, and risk—lessons learned from the space shuttle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, J. (2005). Creating green chemistry: Discursive strategies of a scientific movement. Ph.D. thesis, Virginia Tech.

  • Roco, M. C., & Bainbridge, W. S. (Eds.) (2003). Nanotechnology: Societal implicationsmaximizing benefit for humanity. Report of the National Nanotechnology Initiative Workshop, December 3–5, 2003. National Science Foundation.

  • Ross, B., & Amter, S. (2010). The polluters: The making of our chemically altered environment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schon, D. A. (1983). The reflective practitioner: How professionals think in action. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrader-Frechette, K. (1985). Technological risk and small probabilities. Journal of Business Ethics, 4(6), 431–445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schuurbiers, D. (2011). What happens in the lab does not stay in the lab: Applying midstream modulation to enhance critical reflection in the laboratory. Science and Engineering Ethics, 17(4), 769–788.

  • Semendeferi, I. (2008). Legitimating a nuclear critic: John Gofman, radiation safety, and cancer risks. Historical Studies in the Natural Sciences, 38(2), 259–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swierstra, T., & Jelsma, J. (2006). Responsibility without moralism in technoscientific design practice. Science, Technology and Human Values, 31(3), 309–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • The Royal Society and the Royal Academy of Engineering (2004). Nanoscience and nanotechnologies: Opportunities and uncertainties. http://www.nanotec.org.uk/finalReport.htm.

  • Trost, B. M. (1991). The atom economy—a search for synthetic efficiency. Science, 254(5037), 1471–1477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vaughan, D. (1996). The Challenger launch decision: Risky technology, culture, and deviance at NASA. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, S. (2008). From ‘the dose makes the poison’ to ‘the timing makes the poison’: Conceptualizing risk in the synthetic age. Environmental History, 13(4), 667–673.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voutchkova, A. M., Kostal, J., Steinfeld, J. B., Emerson, J. W., Brooks, B. W., Anastas, P., et al. (2011). Towards rational molecular design: derivation of property guidelines for reduced acute aquatic toxicity. Green Chemistry, 13, 2373–2379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, S. A. (2005). Instrumental in war: Science, research, and instruments between knowledge and the world. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodhouse, E. J. (2003). Change of state? The greening of chemistry. In M. J. Caspar (Ed.), Synthetic planet: Chemical politics and the hazards of modern life (pp. 177–193). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodhouse, E. J., & Breyman, S. (2005). Green chemistry as social movement? Science, Technology and Human Values, 30(2), 199–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woolgar, S. (1981). Interests and explanation in the social study of science. Social Studies of Science, 11(3), 365–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wynne, Brian. (2011). Lab work goes social, and vice versa: Strategising public engagement processes. Science and Engineering Ethics, 17(4), 791–800.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zandvoort, H., Børsen, T., Deneke, M., & Bird, S. (2013). Editors’ overview: Perspectives on teaching social responsibility to students in science and engineering. Science and Engineering Ethics, 19(4), 1413–1438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful for research support provided by the History Department at Wayne State University. I would like to thank anonymous reviewers and audience members at Cornell University and the 2011 Society for Social Studies of Science annual meeting for helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to William T. Lynch.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lynch, W.T. Second-Guessing Scientists and Engineers: Post Hoc Criticism and the Reform of Practice in Green Chemistry and Engineering. Sci Eng Ethics 21, 1217–1240 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-014-9585-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-014-9585-1

Keywords

Navigation