Skip to main content
Log in

Epistemic Logics with Quantification Over Epistemic Operators: Decidability and Expressiveness

  • Published:
Logica Universalis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The optimal balance between decidability and expressiveness is a big problem of logical systems, in particular, of quantified epistemic logics (QELs). On the one hand, decidability is a very significant characteristic of logics that allows us to use such logics in the framework of artificial intelligence. On the other hand, QELs have important expressive capabilities that should not be lost when we construct decidable fragments of these logics. QELs are known to be much more expressive than first-order logics. One important example of their extra expressive power is that they allow us to distinguish between de dicto and de re readings of epistemic sentences. It is clear that such capabilities should be preserved as much as possible in decidable fragments. In this paper, we consider extensions of QELs that include quantification over modalities. Denote this extensions by \(\hbox {Q}_{\Box }\)Ls. \(\hbox {Q}_{\Box }\)Ls allows us to make more subtle distinctions between de dicto and de re readings of epistemic sentences, and we also should keep these new features as much as possible in decidable fragments. It is known that there are not much interesting decidable QELs. The situation with \(\hbox {Q}_{\Box }\)Ls is the same. But in recent years (after 2018), we have obtained a variety of decidable \(\hbox {Q}_{\Box }\)Ls constructed in different ways. We distinguish between (1) the approach in which for every undecidable \(\hbox {Q}_{\Box }\)L and for every variant of its decidable fragment, a specific proof is constructed, and (2) the approach in which a class of decidable \(\hbox {Q}_{\Box }\)Ls is obtained using general tools and a uniform method for all \(\hbox {Q}_{\Box }\)Ls of this class. In this paper, we compare the results of these approaches.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It is known that transitive relations and, in particular, equivalence relations are not expressible in FO\(^2\).

  2. We will look at these fragments in detail in Sects. 5.1 and 5.2.

  3. Note that the paper [32] has been accepted, but the paper [33] is only submitted.

  4. Quine’s original sentence is ‘Ralph believes that someone is a spy’. But the difference between ‘know’ and ‘believe’ is inessential for this paper.

  5. Propositional atoms are viewed as nullary predicates.

  6. Since Ralph saw Ortcutt in a brown hat and at the beach in different circumstances and at different times, we can always choose sets of worlds (situations) \(W_1\) and \(W_2\) such that \(W_1\cap W_2 = \emptyset \).

  7. See the reading (S\(\forall \)1) and also its formalization (S\(\forall \)1)\(^{TML^2}\) in Sect. 6.1.

  8. Recall that the monodic fragment of a modal logic is a restriction allowing at most one free variable within the scope of a modality.

  9. Note that in the monodic fragment of PTML, we can express only unary predicates.

  10. In contrast, the monodic fragment of PTML can be extended with constants (as indices of modalities) and equality without loss of decidability (see [23, Sect. 3]).

  11. The notion ‘first-order correspondence language’ is defined in [3, pp. 83, 127].

  12. Super predicate symbols; are predicate symbols that take as arguments both individual variables and predicate variables (see [6, Sect. 4]).

  13. In (f1), the superscript \(^{(w)}\) indicates that name \(P^{(w)}\) is associated with some world (in this case with the current world).

  14. The paper [15] establishes the 2-Nexptime upper complexity bound for satisfiability of FO\(^2\)+2E. But in [31], we use a fragment of FO\(^2\)+2E the satisfiability problem of which is Nexptime-complete (see [31, Sect. 3]).

  15. U corresponds to the relation R of Definition 3.1.

  16. Such a quantifier \(\forall \overline{Y}\) exists in \(\varphi \), since formulas of HO-LGF\(^{\Box }\) do not contain second-order predicate variables free (see Definition 5.4).

  17. Obviously, this formula belongs to HO-LGF\(^{\Box }\).

References

  1. Aloni, M.: Individual concepts in modal predicate logic. J. Philos. Log. 34(1), 1–64 (2005)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. Aloni, M.: Knowing-who in quantified epistemic logic. In: van Ditmarsch, H., Sandu, G. (eds.) Jaakko Hintikka on Knowledge and Game-Theoretical Semantics, pp. 109–129. Springer, Berlin (2018)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  3. Blackburn, P., de Rijke, M., Venema, Y.: Modal logic. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2001)

  4. Carlson, L.: Quantified Hintikka-style epistemic logic. Synthese 74, 223–262 (1988)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  5. Corsi, G., Orlandelli, E.: Free quantified epistemic logics. Stud. Log. 101(6), 1159–1183 (2013)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. Enderton, H.B.: Second-order and higher-order logic. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2009). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/logic-higher-order/

  7. Fagin, R., Halpern, J.Y., Moses, Y., Vardi, M.Y.: Reasoning About Knowledge. The MIT Press, Cambridge (1995)

  8. Fitting, M., Thalmann, L., Voronkov, A.: Term-modal logics. Stud. Log. 69(1), 133–169 (2001)

  9. Gabbay, D.M., Kurucz, A., Wolter, F., Zakharyaschev, M.: Many-dimensional modal logic: theory and applications. Studies in Logic 148, Elsevier (2003)

  10. Grädel, E.: On the restraining power of guards. J. Symb. Log. 64(4), 1719–1742 (1999)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. Grove, A.J., Halpern, J.Y.: Naming and identity in epistemic logics. Part I: the propositional case. J. Log. Comput. 3(4), 345–378 (1993)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. Grove, A.J.: Naming and identity in epistemic logic. Part II: a first-order logic for naming. Artif. Intell. 74(2), 311–350 (1995)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. Hodkinson, I.: Loosely guarded fragment of first-order logic has the finite model property. Stud. Log. 70(2), 205–240 (2002)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  14. Kieroński, E.: Results on the guarded fragment with equivalence or transitive relations. Proceedings of CSL 2005. Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 3634, pp. 309–324 (2005)

  15. Kieroński, E., Michaliszyn, J., Pratt-Hartmann, I., Tendera, L.: Two-variable first-order logic with equivalence closure. SIAM J. Comput. 43(3), 1012–1063 (2014)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. Kieroński, E., Otto, M.: Small substructures and decidability issues for first-order logic with two variables. J. Symb. Log. 77(3), 729–765 (2012)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  17. Kooi, B.: Dynamic term-modal logic. In: Proceedings of LORI, pp. 173–185 (2007)

  18. Liberman, A.O., Achen, A., Rendsvig, R.K.: Dynamic term-modal logics for first-order epistemic planning. Artif. Intell. 286, 103305 (2020)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  19. Lomuscio, A., Colombetti, M.: QLB: a quantified logic for belief. In: Proceedings of ATAL. Lecture Notes in Computer Science 1193, pp. 71–85 (1996)

  20. Naumov, P., Tao, J.: Everyone knows that someone knows: quantifiers over epistemic agents. Rev. Symb. Log. 12(2), 255–270 (2019)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  21. Orlandelli, E., Corsi, G.: Decidable term-modal logics. In: Proceedings of EUMAS 2017. Lecture Notes in Computer Science 10767, pp. 147–162 (2018)

  22. Padmanabha, A., Ramanujam, R.: Propositional modal logic with implicit modal quantification. In: Proceedings of ICLA: Logic and Its Applications. Lecture Notes in Computer Science 11600, pp. 6–17 (2019)

  23. Padmanabha, A., Ramanujam, R.: The monodic fragment of propositional term modal logic. Stud. Log. 107(3), 533–557 (2019)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  24. Padmanabha, A., Ramanujam, R.: Two variable fragment of term modal logic. In: Proceeding of MFCS: Mathematical Foundations of Computer Science, pp. 30:1–30:14 (2019). https://doi.org/10.4230/LIPIcs.MFCS.2019.30

  25. Padmanabha, A., Ramanujam, R.: A decidable fragment of first order modal logic: two variable term modal logic. ACM Trans. Comput. Log. (2023). Published: 19 April. https://doi.org/10.1145/3593584

  26. Quine, W.V.O.: Quantifiers and propositional attitudes. J. Philos. 53(5), 177–187 (1956)

  27. Sawasaki, T., Sano, K., Yamada, T.: Term-sequence-modal logics. In: Proceedings of LORI. Lecture Notes in Computer Science 11813, pp. 244–258 (2019)

  28. Seligman, J., Wang, Y.: Call me by your name: epistemic logic with assignments and non-rigid names. Computing Research Repository (CoRR) (2018). arXiv:1805.03852v1

  29. Shapiro, S.: Foundations Without Foundationalism. A Case for Second-order Logic. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1991)

  30. Shtakser, G.: Propositional epistemic logics with quantification over agents of knowledge. Stud. Log. 106(2), 311–344 (2018)

  31. Shtakser, G.: Propositional epistemic logics with quantification over agents of knowledge (an alternative approach). Stud. Log. 107(4), 753–780 (2019)

  32. Shtakser, G.: A modal loosely guarded fragment of second-order propositional modal logic. J. Log. Lang. Inf. 32(3), 511–538 (2023)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  33. Shtakser, G.: A modal two-variable fragment of second-order propositional modal logic (Submitted manuscript)

  34. Wang, Y., Wei, Y., Seligman, J.: Quantifier-free epistemic term-modal logic with assignment operator. Ann. Pure Appl. Log. 173(3), 103071 (2022)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  35. Wolter, F., Zakharyaschev, M.: Decidable fragments of first-order modal logics. J. Symb. Log. 66(3), 1415–1438 (2001)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gennady Shtakser.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Shtakser, G. Epistemic Logics with Quantification Over Epistemic Operators: Decidability and Expressiveness. Log. Univers. 17, 297–330 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11787-023-00330-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11787-023-00330-2

Keywords

Mathematics Subject Classification

Navigation