Skip to main content
Log in

“There’s Life in the Old Dog Yet”: The Homo economicus model and its value for behavioral ethics

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Journal of Business Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The Homo economicus model (HEM) is widely used in the social sciences in general and in business ethics in particular. Despite its success, the model is frequently criticized for being empirically flawed and normatively dangerous, and its critics argue that it should be abandoned and replaced by more realistic models of human behavior. In response to the HEM’s critics, this paper develops a precise methodological approach that makes it possible to integrate within the HEM seemingly contradictory empirical evidence. Using the methodology we develop, we will integrate recent findings in behavioral economics and show how a rational-choice approach to behavioral ethics can illuminate the emergence, salience and persistence of morality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Kant famously illustrates his position with an example from business: if a merchant who could easily cheat charges a fair price to everybody because he is worried that, if he did not, his reputation would suffer, there is no moral worth in his honesty, as his behavior is just a matter of prudence (Kant 1785/2013: 487). Another prominent critic of economic acts is Karl Marx who denies the possibility of morality, solidarity and humanity in capitalist market systems (Marx 1959/2007). On egoist motives in Marxism, see Churchich (1994: 145–169).

  2. Some researchers describe a similar “indoctrination effect” to explain why in laboratory experiments economics students tend to behave less cooperatively than students of other social sciences (Bauman and Rose 2011; Frank et al. 1993; Ostrom 1998).

  3. Popper himself did not think of his methodology as ‘contingent,’ but understood it as the only way of guaranteeing progress in science. In this respect, we do not follow Popper. His position is prescriptive and hence not falsifiable in itself (see e.g., Küpper 2011). Methodological choices are normative stipulations and therefore cannot be true in an objective sense.

  4. For the sake of expositional clarity, we summarize our results in the form of a proposition. In a recent Academy of Management Review editorial, Cornelissen (2017) referred to this style of theorizing as the “proposition-based style.” In contrast to that, our propositions do not introduce “cause–effect relationships” but outline the cornerstones of our proposed methodology.

  5. We should note that Becker’s concept of ‘preferences’ does not refer to mere tastes, but to fundamental preferences, as reflected in the following quote: “The preferences that are assumed to be stable do not refer to market goods and services, like oranges, automobiles, or medical care, but to underlying objects of choice that are produced by each household using market goods and services, their own time, and other inputs. These underlying preferences are defined over fundamental aspects of life, such as health, prestige, sensual pleasure, benevolence, or envy, that do not always bear a stable relation to market goods and services” (Becker 1976: 5).

  6. Note that this methodological choice does not deny that evolutionary cooperation may have developed first (Tomasello 2009).

  7. In Elements of Law Hobbes (1650/1994: 50) states: “GLORY […] is that passion which proceedeth from the imagination or conception of our own power, above the power of him that contendeth with us.”

  8. We are grateful to Alicia Melis for drawing our attention to this distinction.

  9. Similarly, economics draws a difference between an explanatory model of behavior and the agent’s perception of that same behavior (his Lebenswelt): “The critics of rational choice invariably—and I mean invariably—misrepresent the theory. In particular, it does not imply that rational actors are egoists, or that they maximize pleasure, or in fact, that they maximize anything. It is useful to keep in mind at all times that the rational choice model is a key tool of animal behavior theory (…). It is difficult to consider a creature lacking nociceptors (e.g., most insects) as a happiness maximizer, and yet the rational actor model is very illuminating even for such creatures. They maximize fitness” (Gintis 2016: vii).

References

  • Anderson E (2000) Beyond H. economicus: new developments in theories of social norms. Philos Public Aff 29(2):170–200

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreoni J, Gee LK (2012) Gun for hire: delegated enforcement and peer punishment in public goods provision. J Public Econ 96(11):1036–1046

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreoni J, Miller JH (1993) Rational cooperation in the finitely repeated prisoner’s dilemma: experimental evidence. Econ J 103(418):570–585

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreoni J, Samuelson L (2006) Building rational cooperation. J Econ Theory 127(1):117–154

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreoni J, Harbaugh W, Vesterlund L (2003) The carrot or the stick: rewards, punishments, and cooperation. Am Econ Rev 93(3):893–902

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ariely D (2011) The (Honest) truth about dishonesty. How we lie to everyone—especially ourselves. HarperCollins, New York, p 2011

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle (1925/1998) The nicomachean ethics. translated by ross. Oxford University Press, New York

  • Axelrod R (1980) Effective choice in the prisoner’s dilemma. J Confl Resolut 24(1):3–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod R (1984) The evolution of cooperation. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauman Y, Rose E (2011) Selection or indoctrination: Why do economics students donate less than the rest? J Econ Behav Organ 79(3):318–327

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker GS (1976) The economic approach to human behavior. Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Becker GS (1993) Nobel lecture: the economic way of looking at behavior. J Polit Econ 101(3):385–409

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blaug M (1992) The methodology of economics: or, how economists explain. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boehm C (2012) Moral origins. The evolution of virtue, altruism, and shame. New York (Basic)

  • Boland LA (1981) On the futility of criticizing the neoclassical maximization hypothesis. Am Econ Rev 71(5):1031–1036

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan G, Buchanan JM (1985) The reasons of rules. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan JM (1995) Individual rights, emergent social states, and behavioral feasibility. Ration Soc 7(2):141–150

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer C, Weigelt K (1988) Experimental tests of a sequential equilibrium reputation model. Econometrica 56(1):1–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casari M, Luini L (2009) Cooperation under alternative punishment institutions: an experiment. J Econ Behav Organ 71(2):273–282

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chaudhuri A (2011) Sustaining cooperation in laboratory public goods experiments: a selective survey of the literature. Exp Econ 14(1):47–83

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchich N (1994) Marxism and morality: a critical examination of marxist ethics. James Clarke & Co., Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Combs JG, Jr K, David J (1999) Can capital scarcity help agency theory explain franchising? Revisiting the capital scarcity hypothesis. Acad Manag J 42(2):196–207

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper DJ, Kagel JH (2016) Other-regarding preferences: a selective survey of experimental results. In: Kagel JH, Roth AE (eds) Handbook of experimental economics, vol 2. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp 217–289

    Google Scholar 

  • Cornelissen J (2017) Editor’s comments: developing propositions, a process model, or a typology? Addressing the challenges of writing theory without a boilerplate. Acad Manag Rev 42(1):1–9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Waal Frans (1996) Good natured. Harvard University Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Stefano G, King AA, Verona G (2015) Sanctioning in the wild: rational calculus and retributive instincts in gourmet cuisine. Acad Manag J 58(3):906–931

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dierksmeier C (2011) The freedom-responsibility nexus in management philosophy and business ethics. J Bus Ethics 101(2):263–283

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson L (1990) The ethereal hand: organizational economics and management theory. Acad Manag Rev 15(3):369–381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson T, Dunfee TW (1999) Ties that bind. A social contracts approach to business ethics. Harvard Business School Press, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Dow SC (1997) Mainstream economic methodology. Camb J Econ 21(1):73–93

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Etzioni A (2010) Behavioral economics: a methodological note. J Econ Psychol 31(1):51–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr E, Fischbacher U (2002) Why Social preferences matter—the impact of non-selfish motives on competition, cooperation and incentives. Econ J 112(478):C1–C33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr E, Gächter S (2000) Cooperation and punishment in public goods experiments. Am Econ Rev 90(4):980–994

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr E, Schmidt KM (1999) A theory of fairness, competition, and cooperation. Q J Econ 114(3):817–868

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr E, Schmidt KM (2003) Theories of fairness and reciprocity: evidence and economic applications. In: Dewatripont M, Hansen LP, Turnovsky SJ (eds) Advances in economics and econometrics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 208–257

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Frank RH, Gilovich T, Regan DT (1993) Does studying economics inhibit cooperation? J Econ Perspect 7(2):159–171

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedland J, Cole BM (2017) From homo-economicus to homo-virtus: a system-theoretic model for raising moral self-awareness. J Bus Ethics (online first). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-017-3494-6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (1953) The methodology of positive economics. In: Friedman M (ed) Essays in positive economics. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 3–43

    Google Scholar 

  • Gächter S, Renner E, Sefton M (2008) The long-run benefits of punishment. Science 322(5907):1510

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier D (1986) Morals by agreement. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghoshal S (2005) Bad management theories are destroying good management practices. Acad Manag Learn Edu 4(1):75–91

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gintis H (2016) Individuality and entanglement: the moral and material bases of social life. Princeton University Press, Princeton, p 2016

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gintis H, Bowles S, Boyd R et al (eds) (2005) Moral sentiments and material interests—the foundations of cooperation in economic life. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Glass JC, Johnson W (1988) Metaphysics, MSRP and economics. Br J Philos Sci 39(3):313–329

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene J (2013) Moral tribes. Emotion, reason, and the gap between us and them. Penguin Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene JD, Nystrom LE, Engell AD et al (2004) The neural bases of cognitive conflict and control in moral judgment. Neuron 44(2):389–400

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greif A (2000) The fundamental problem of exchange: a research agenda in historical institutional analysis. Eur Rev Econ Hist 4(3):251–284

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guala F (2012) Reciprocity: weak or strong? What punishment experiments do (and do not) demonstrate. Behav Brain Sci 35(1):1–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gürerk Ö, Irlenbusch B, Rockenbach B (2006) The competitive advantage of sanctioning institutions. Science 312(5770):108–111

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gürerk Ö, Irlenbusch B, Rockenbach B (2014) On cooperation in open communities. J Public Econ 120:220–230

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Güth W, Kocher MG (2014) More than thirty years of ultimatum bargaining experiments: motives, variations, and a survey of the recent literature. J Econ Behav Organ 108:396–409

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn FH, Hollis M (1979) Philosophy and economic theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J (2001) The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychol Rev 108(4):814–834

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J (2008) Morality. Perspect Psychol Sci 3(1):65–72

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt J (2012) The righteous mind: Why Good People are divided by politics and religion. New York (Pantheon)

  • Harsanyi JC (1977) Rational behavior and bargaining equilibrium in games and social situations. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hauser MD (2006) Moral minds: How nature designed our universal sense of right and wrong. New York (HarperCollins)

  • Heath J (2014) Morality, competition, and the firm: the market failures approach to business ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hirschman AO (1985) Against parsimony: three easy ways of complicating some categories of economic discourse. Econ Philos 1(1):7–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes T (1650/1994) The elements of law, natural and politic. In: Gaskin JCA (ed) Edited with an introduction. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Hobbes T (1651/2005) Leviathan. Continuum, New York

  • Homann K (1994) Homo oeconomicus und dilemmastrukturen. In: Sautter H (ed) Wirtschaftspolitik in offenen Volkswirtschaften - Festschrift zum 60. Geburtstag von Helmut Hesse. Göttingen, Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht, pp 387–412

    Google Scholar 

  • Homann K (2014) Sollen und Können. Grenzen und bedingungen der individualmoral. Ibera/European University Press, Wien

    Google Scholar 

  • Homann K, Suchanek A (2005) Ökonomik—Eine Einführung, 2nd edn. Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck

    Google Scholar 

  • Hosmer LT, Chen F (2001) Ethics and economics. growing opportunities for joint research. Bus Ethics Q 11(4):599–622

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hühn MP (2014) You reap what you sow: How MBA programs undermine ethics. J Bus Ethics 121(4):527–541

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce R (2007) The evolution of morality. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D, Tversky A (1979) Prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica 47(2):263–292

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1785/2013) Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals. In: Shafer-Landau R (ed) Ethical theory, an anthology. Wiley, Chichester (Reprinted)

  • Keynes JN (1917) The scope and method of political economy, 4th edn. Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchgässner G (2008) Homo oeconomicus. The economic model of behavior and its applications in economics and other social sciences. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kluver J, Frazier R, Haidt J (2014) Behavioral ethics for Homo economicus, Homo heuristicus, and Homo duplex. Organ Behav Hum Decis Process 123(2):150–158

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korth C (2009) Game theory and fairness preferences. In: Korth C (ed) Fairness in bargaining and markets. Springer, Berlin, pp 19–34

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kosfeld M, Okada A, Riedl A (2009) Institution formation in public goods games. Am Econ Rev 99(4):1335–1355

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langlois RN, Hodgson GM (1992) Orders and organizations: toward an austrian theory of social institutions. In: Caldwell B, Boehm S (eds) Austrian economics: tensions and new directions. Springer, Heidelberg, pp 165–192

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Laville F (2000) Should we abandon optimization theory? The need for bounded rationality. J Econ Methodol 7(3):395–426

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lazear EP (2000) Economic imperialism. Quart J Econ 115(1):99–146

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levitt SD, List JA (2007) What do laboratory experiments measuring social preferences reveal about the real world? J Econ Perspect 21(2):153–174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levitt S, List JA (2008) Economics: Homo economicus evolves. Science 319(5865):909–910

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindenberg S (1990) Homo socio-oeconomicus: the emergence of a general model of man in the social sciences. J Inst Theor Econ (JITE) 146:727–748

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein G, Thaler RH (1989) Anomalies: intertemporal choice. J Econ Perspect 3(4):181–193

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie KD, House R (1978) Paradigm development in the social sciences: a proposed research strategy. Acad Manag Rev 3(1):7–23

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marx K (1959) Economic & Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, transl. and edited by Martin Milligan, Moscow (Foreign Languages Publishing House)

  • McKenzie RB (2009) Predictably rational? In search of defenses for rational behavior in economics. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • McWilliams A, Siegel D (2001) Corporate social responsibility: a theory of the firm perspective. Acad Manag Rev 26(1):117–127

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meckling WH (1976) Values and the choice of the model of the individual in the social sciences. Schweizerische Zeitschrift für Volkswirtschaft und Statistik 112(4):545–560

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill JS (1836/1967) On the definition of political economy. In: Robson JM (ed) Collected works, vol IV. University of Toronto Press, Toronto, pp 309–339

  • Mueller F (1995) Organizational governance and employee cooperation: can we learn from economists? Hum Relat 48(10):1217–1235

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Néron P-Y (2015) Rethinking the very idea of egalitarian markets and corporations: Why relationships might matter more than distribution. Bus Ethics Q 25(1):93–124

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • North DC (1991) Institutions. The Journal of Economic Perspectives 5(1):97–112

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nowak MA, Page KM, Sigmund K (2000) Fairness versus reason in the ultimatum game. Science 289(5485):1773–1775

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom E (1998) A behavioral approach to the rational choice theory of collective action: presidential address, 1997. Am Polit Sci Rev 92(1):1–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom E (2000) Collective action and the evolution of social norms. J Econ Perspect 92(1):137–158

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pareto V (1907/1971) Manual of political economy (transl. by A. Schwier). London, MacMillan

  • Pies I, Hielscher S (2014) Verhaltensökonomik versus Ordnungsethik? Zum moralischen Stellenwert von Dispositionen und Institutionen. Zeitschrift für Wirtschafts- und Unternehmensethik 15(3):398–420

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pies I, Hielscher S, Beckmann M (2009) Moral commitments and the societal role of business: an ordonomic approach to corporate citizenship. Bus Ethics Q 19(3):375–401

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popper KR (1945/2011) The open society and its enemies. Routledge, London

  • Popper KR (1959/2005) The logic of scientific discovery. Routledge, London

  • Popper KR (1963/1985) The rationality principle. In: Miller DW (ed) Popper selections. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp 357–365

  • Popper KR (1964/1994) Models, instruments, and truth. The status of the rationality principle in the social sciences. In: Popper KR, Mark AN (eds) The myth of the framework: in defense of science and rationality. Routledge, London, pp 154–184

  • Poundstone W (1992) Prisoner’s dilemma: john von neuman, game theory, and the puzzle of the bomb. Doubleday, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Putterman L, Tyran J-R, Kamei K (2011) Public goods and voting on formal sanction schemes. J Public Econ 95(9):1213–1222

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schreck P, van Aaken D, Donaldson T (2013) Positive economics and the normativistic fallacy: bridging the two sides of CSR. Bus Ethics Q 23(2):297–329

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scott-Phillips TC, Dickins TE, West SA (2011) Evolutionary theory and the ultimate-proximate distinction in the human behavioral sciences. Perspect Psychol Sci 6(1):38–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1977) Rational fools: a critique of the behavioral foundations of economics. Philos Public Aff 6(4):317–344

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1957) Models of man: social and rational. Mathematical essays on rational human behavior in a social setting. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Slomp G (1990) The significance of glory in the political theory of thomas hobbes. UMI, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E, Wilson DS (1999) Unto others: the evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K, Joyce R, Calcott B et al (eds) (2013) Cooperation and its evolution. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (1991) Rational choice: a survey of contributions from economics and philosophy. Econ J 101(407):751–785

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutter M, Haigner S, Kocher MG (2010) Choosing the carrot or the stick? Endogenous institutional choice in social dilemma situations. Rev Econ Stud 77(4):1540–1566

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler RH, Sunstein CR (2008) Nudge: improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Tinbergen N (1963) On aims and methods of ethology. Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie 20(4):410–433

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M (2009) Why we cooperate. MIT Press, Boston, p 2009

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M (2014) A natural history of human thinking. Harvard University Press, Boston, p 2014

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M (2016) A natural history of human morality. Harvard University Press, Boston, p 2016

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M, Melis AP, Tennie C et al (2012) Two key steps in the evolution of human cooperation: the interdependence hypothesis. Curr Anthropol 53(6):673–692

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Traulsen A, Röhl T, Milinski M (2012) An economic experiment reveals that humans prefer pool punishment to maintain the commons. Proc R Soc B 279(1743):3716–3721

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg VJ (2002) Rational choice vs. program-based behavior: alternative theoretical approaches and their relevance for the study of institutions. Ration Soc 14(1):7–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg VJ (2004) The rationality postulate in economics: its ambiguity, its deficiency and its evolutionary alternative. J Econ Methodol 11(1):1–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weizsäcker CF (1964) The relevance of science. Creation and cosmogony. Gifford lectures 1959–60. Collins, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhang B, Li C, De Silva H et al (2014) The evolution of sanctioning institutions: an experimental approach to the social contract. Exp Econ 17(2):285–303

    Google Scholar 

  • Zintl R (1989) Der Homo Oeconomicus: ausnahmeerscheinung in jeder Situation oder Jedermann in Ausnahmesituation? Analyse Kritik 11:52–69

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Philipp Schreck.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schreck, P., van Aaken, D. & Homann, K. “There’s Life in the Old Dog Yet”: The Homo economicus model and its value for behavioral ethics. J Bus Econ 90, 401–425 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11573-019-00964-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11573-019-00964-z

Keywords

JEL Classifications

Navigation