Skip to main content
Log in

Heterophenomenology: A Limited Critique

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Dennett (Synthese, 53(2), 159–180, 1982, 1991, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(9–10), 19–30, 2003, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, 247–270, 2007) proposes and defends a method called heterophenomenology. Heterophenomenology is a method to study consciousness from a third-person objective point of view as opposed to a first-person subjective point of view or (auto)-phenomenology. The method of heterophenomenology serves a necessary role in Dennett’s schema of bridging the gap between the manifest and the scientific image of the world. In this paper, I attempt to present a limited critique of the method of heterophenomenology. The objection raised in this paper is limited to one of the steps involved in the method, i.e., the interpretation of the heterophenomenological text as analogous to novelist fiction. I attempt to show that the assumptions made by Dennett about the interpretation of fiction are contradictory in nature and therefore the same cannot be applied to the interpretation of a heterophenomenological text. The assumptions fail in justifying the interpretation of fiction itself and hence exporting them by analogy to interpret a heterophenomenological text is a mistake.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Following Kuhn’s (1962) famous remark about all observations being theory-laden, one can raise a general criticism against Dennett’s overall project of reconciling the manifest with the scientific image of the world. It is often overlooked in such endeavours that the scientific image of the world does not consist of just independent-out-in-the-world facts but it is a joint product of these facts and the value judgments of a scientist. (Norton, 2003).

  2. Philosophical zombies are proposed as beings who are behaviourally indistinguishable from a conscious human being but they themselves are not conscious and do not have any inner subjective experience whatsoever. The term zombie in this sense was first used by Kirk (1974). Chalmers (1996) is credited to having popularised this idea. Dennett (1995) is one of the earlier works where Dennett has criticized the possibility of such beings. Dennett (1982) while proposing the method of heterophenomenology argues that maintaining the metaphysical minimalism would save heterophenomenology from the objection arising out of the possibility of philosophical zombies.

References

  • Beenfeldt, C. (2008). A philosophical critique of heterophenomenology. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 15(8), 5–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carman, T. (2007). Dennett on seeming. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(1–2), 99–106.

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory (2nd ed.). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2004). How can we construct a science of consciousness? In M. S. Gazzaniga (Ed.), The Cognitive Neurosciences III (pp. 1111–1119). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1982). How to study human consciousness empirically or nothing comes to mind. Synthese, 53(2), 159–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1993). Caveat emptor. Consciousness and Cognition, 2(1), 48–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1995). The unimagined preposterousness of zombies. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(4), 322–326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2003). Who’s on First? Heterophenomenology explained. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(9–10), 19–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2007). Heterophenomenology reconsidered. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, 247–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dokic, J., & Pacherie, E. (2007). Too much ado about belief. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(1–2), 185–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gertler, B. (2009). Introspection. In T. Bayne, A. Cleeremans, & P. Wilken (Eds.), The Oxford Companion to Consciousness. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1997). Science, publicity, and consciousness. Philosophy of Science, 64(4), 525–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirk, R. (1974). Sentience and behavior. Mind, 83(January), 43–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). University of Chicago Press.

  • Levine, J. (1994). Out of the closet: A Qualophile Confronts Qualophobia. Philosophical Topics, 22, 107–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. D. (2003). A material theory of induction. Philosophy of Science, 70(4), 647–670.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (2003a). Data from introspective reports: Upgrading from commonsense to science. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10, 9–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (2003b). Epistemic divergence and the publicity of scientific methods. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 34, 597–612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (2010). How to improve on heterophenomenology: The self-measurement methodology of First-Person Data. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 17, 84–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2007). No unchangeable epistemic authority, of any sort, regarding our own conscious experience - contra Dennett? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, 1–2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. S. (1962). Philosophy and the scientific image of man. In R. Colodny (Ed.), Science, Perception, and reality (pp. 35–78). Humanities Press/Ridgeview.

  • Smith, D. W. (2007). Husserl. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F., & Shear, J. (1999). First-person methodologies: What, why, how? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6(2–3), 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2007). Killing the straw man: Dennett and phenomenology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(1–2), 21–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Prof. Ranjan Kumar Panda for his suggestions and feedback on my work. I would also like to thank the anonymous reviewers for their suggestions. I am also thankful to Ramakrishna Mission Institute of Culture, Gol Park Kolkata as the first version of this paper was presented in a conference organized by the institute in March 2023.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Abhishek Yadav.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

I, Abhishek Yadav, the author of this paper, declare that I have no conflict of interests.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Yadav, A. Heterophenomenology: A Limited Critique. Philosophia 52, 87–99 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-024-00711-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-024-00711-x

Keywords

Navigation