Skip to main content
Log in

Intuitionism and Nihilism

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Intuitionism and nihilism, according to nihilists, have key features in common: the same semantics and the same phenomenology. Intuitionism is the object of nihilism’s attack. The central charge nihilism lodges against intuitionism is that its nonnatural moral properties are queer. Here I’ll examine what ‘queer’ might mean in relation to the doctrines nihilism uses to support this charge. My investigation reveals that nihilism’s queerness charge lacks substance and resembles a tautology served with a frown. There’s really nothing to it. After I show that, I’ll offer an explanation for why nihilism has gotten intuitionism wrong. It makes a central mistaken methodological assumption and doesn’t target any identifiable intuitionism in the last hundred or so years.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Huemer 2005: 110 and my 2012: Ch.4.

  2. In my 2017 I show how my intuitionism explains a wide range of moral phenomena.

  3. Thomas Hurka distinguishes inherent, or internal, moral explanations from external ones (Hurka 2011)

  4. See my 2012: Ch. 2.

  5. Much confusion has resulted from the fact that after G.E. Moore defines naturalism in this way (Moore 1903: 41), he then quickly moves to characterize the nonnatural more narrowly as, in our contemporary terminology, consisting of abstract entities (Moore 1903: 42). My definition of nonnatural fits Moore’s broader initial definition.

  6. This understanding is in line with Shafer-Landau’s claim that the non-reductive naturalist and the nonnaturalist ‘can have identical ontological inventories’, but differ epistemically (2003: 64).

  7. I say ‘direct’ here for indirect evidence for why someone believes a moral claim p can undermine it. For example, if someone was brainwashed to believe that p, and they are thereby psychologically unable to doubt that p, that would indicate a psychological explanation for their belief. See Huemer 2008.

  8. Recently, intuitionists have devised theories of reasons. See Shafer-Landau 2003: Chs. 7–8 and Huemer 2005: Ch. 7.

  9. See my 2012: Ch. 5.

  10. Compare these explicit possible meanings of ‘queer’ with the corresponding standard nihilist elliptical meanings at the beginning of section 6.

References

  • Audi, R. (2004). The good in the right: A theory of intuition and intrinsic value. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedke, M. S. (2014). A menagerie of duties? Normative judgments are not beliefs about non-natural properties. American Philosophical Quarterly, 51(3), 189–201.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copi, I. M., & Cohen, C. (1994). Introduction to logic (9th ed.). Englewood Cliffs: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cuneo, T. (2007). The normative web: An argument for moral realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frankena, W. K. (1963). Ethics. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garner, R. T. (1990). On the genuine queerness of moral properties and facts. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 68, 137–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hudson, W. D. (1983). Modern moral philosophy (2nd ed.). New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2005). Ethical intuitionism. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2008). Revisionary intuitionism. Social Philosophy & Policy, 25, 368–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, T. (2011). Common themes from Sidgwick to Ewing. In T. Hurka (Ed.), Underivative duty: British moral philosophers from Sidgwick to Ewing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, P. J. (2012). A concise Introduction to logic (11th ed.). Boston: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. (2001). The myth of morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. (2009). Is moral Projectivism empirically tractable? Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 12, 53–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaspar, D. (2012). Intuitionism. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaspar, D. (2015). How we decide in moral situations. Philosophy, 90, 59–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaspar, D. (2017). Moral explanation through moral kinds. In L. Taddio (Ed.), New perspectives on realism (pp. 217–238). Mimesis International: Milan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, A. (2003). An Introduction to contemporary Metaethics. Oxford: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nowell-Smith, P. H. (1954). Ethics. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, J. (2014). Moral error theory: History, critique, Defence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Platts, M. (1980). Moral reality and the end of desire. In M. Platts. (Ed.), Reference, truth, and reality: essays on the philosophy of language (pp. 69–82). London: Routledge and Kegan Pau.

  • Prichard, H. A. (1912). Does moral philosophy rest on a mistake? Mind, 21, 21–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, R. (1948). The emotive theory of ethics. Proceedings of the Aristotelean Society, Supplementary Volumes, 22, 79–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. (1930). The right and the good. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. (1939). Foundations of ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. (2003). Moral realism: A Defence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Timmons, M. (1999). Morality without foundations: A defense of ethical Contextualism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the audience members of the 9th Annual Felician Ethics Conference at Felician College, Rutherford, NJ: April 25, 2015 for their helpful comments on an earlier version of this article. I would also like to thank an anonymous reviewer for helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Kaspar.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The author states that there is no conflict of interest.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kaspar, D. Intuitionism and Nihilism. Philosophia 46, 319–336 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9930-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9930-0

Keywords

Navigation