Skip to main content
Log in

The Diversity of Rational Choice Theory: A Review Note

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I review the literature on rational choice theory (RCT) to scrutinize a number of criticisms that philosophers have voiced against its usefulness in economics. The paper has three goals: first, I argue that the debates about RCT have been characterized by disunity and confusion about the object under scrutiny, which calls into question the effectiveness of those criticisms. Second, I argue that RCT is not a single and unified choice theory—let alone an empirical theory of human behavior—as some critics seem to suppose. Rather, there are several variants of RCT used in economics. Third, I propose that we think of RCT as a set of distinct research strategies to appreciate its diversity. This account implies that the effectiveness of any criticism depends on the variant of RCT we are considering.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This idea is inspired by Philip Kitcher’s discussion of Richard Lewontin’s positions in the debate about genetic determinism (Kitcher 2000).

  2. For an overview of respective debates of ACTs, see Anand et al. (2009).

  3. There are various books on the different variants of ACTs in economics and philosophy. For comprehensive expositions, see Anand et al. 2009) and Gilboa (2010).

  4. Presumably nobody would deny that RCT cannot be literally true in all respects. As any theoretical approach, it is grounded in specific abstractions and idealizations. However, criticism often rests upon the idea that RCT offers a literally true description of the psychological mechanism behind behavior and what is either abstracted away or has been idealized as not causally relevant are the environmental factors.

  5. There are other and more fundamental difficulties hiding behind these problems discussed in the philosophy of action, philosophy of mind, and epistemology that cannot concern us here.

  6. Pettit (1991) takes the relation between various versions of RCT and folk psychology to be an explication relation, whereby the explicandum is the folk psychological concepts and the explicatum is the various mathematical formulations of those concepts in RCT, a view he takes from David Lewis.

  7. Hausman (1995, p. 96) argues against Satz and Ferejohn by claiming that “Rational-choice explanations are psychological explanations”.

  8. On the relationship between decision theory and folk psychology, see Pettit (1991).

  9. For a detailed discussion of the transitivity assumption, its role and implications as a common property of ordering relations, and its connection to weak orders as one class of binary relations, see Fishburn (1979).

  10. Note that various labels, such as comparability, connectedness, and connectivity, which all denote the same axiom and are here called completeness, can be found in the literature (see Hausman 1992, p. 15).

  11. Note that this is the description of a strict, not a weak preference relation.

  12. It is not important for our purposes to present different kinds of possible interpretations that a binary relation in mathematics can have. What matters is that the use of a relation does not commit one to any specific interpretation and that the economist’s interpretation of a relation as a type of preference relation or preference-or–indifference relation (Fishburn 1979, 164) is only one among many possible interpretations that a formal–mathematical structure can have.

  13. For a discussion of different accounts of preferences in economics, see Hausman (2011).

  14. Hargreaves-Heap et al. (1992, p. 3) and Elster (1989) are examples of equating the notion of desire from philosophy of action with the concept of a preference in RCT.

  15. The interpretation and conceptualization of ‘utility’ is one of the most important and most forcefully debated issues in the history of the discipline of economics. The concept has gone through various fundamental transitions since Bentham and the Marginalists (see, e.g., Ross 1999).

  16. For some recent contributions to the debate, see, e.g., Angner (2018), Dietrich and List (2016b) Hands (2013), Hausman (2012), and Okasha (2016).

  17. Debates about the way in which economists have conceptualized human behavior have been plagued by confusion and disagreement at least since the work of J.S. Mill. Mill’s homo oeconomicus was accused of striving only for pecuniary self-interest.Mill himself was very clear that his account did not explain human behavior but instead would help economists understand a highly complex subject, the clear that his account did not explain human behavior but instead would help economists understand a highly complex subject, the market. For him, “Not that any political economist was ever so absurd as to suppose that mankind are really thus constituted, but because [it allows for reasoning from first principles about highly complex social phenomena, this] is the mode in which science must necessarily proceed” (Mill 1874 [1844], V. 38). Mill’s position is exemplary for many economists defending RCT. In the first half of the twentieth century, Fritz Machlup remarked that, while some criticisms of economic man had to be addressed carefully, it was remarkable that “some of the strictures and denunciations […] can probably be best explained as the result of misunderstandings—due to ignorance or incompetence” (1978, p. 286). Lionel Robbins saw, ironically, a virtue therein, as economic man would probably not have become such a “universal bogey” if critics had known what they were talking about (1935 [1932], p. 97).

  18. Morgan (2006) offers an introduction into the diversity of what she calls the ‘economic man’ throughout the history of economics, which is revealed by looking at instances of economic modelling and how those modelling contexts reveal how economists thought about their conceptualizations of the human agent and the role it played in those contexts.

  19. See the editors’ introduction in Frisch (2009 [1933], p. xxv).

  20. This section draws upon Herfeld (2019).

  21. As I take methodological rationalism to encompass also the earlier traditions of political economy, this doctrine should not be confused with a rationalist approach in the traditional sense of the term. It is committed to approaching human behaviour most broadly through reference to human reason, which was understood much broader in early traditions, such as the Scottish Enlightenment (e.g., Dow et al. 1997).

  22. The doctrine of methodological rationalism has not been extensively addressed in the literature. For exceptions see Anderson (2000) and Lee (2009).

References

  • Akerlof GA (1984 [1970]) The market for ‘lemons’: quality uncertainty and the market mechanism. In: Akerlof GA (ed) An economic theorist’s book of tales. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 7–22

  • Allais M (1953) Le comportement de l’homme rationnel devant le risque: critique des postulats et axiomes de l’école Américaine. Econometrica 21(4):503–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anand P, Pattanaik P, Puppe C (eds) (2009) The handbook of rational and social choice: an overview of new foundations and applications. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson E (2000) Beyond homo oeconomicus: new developments in theories of social norms. Philos Public Aff 29(2):170–200

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Angner E (2018) What preferences really are. Philos Sci 85(4):660–681

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ (1951) Social choice and individual values. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ (1958) Utilities, attitudes, choices: a review note. Econometrica 26(1):1–23

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ (1959) Rational choice functions and orderings. Economica 26(102):121–127

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ (1994) Methodological individualism and social knowledge. Am Econ Rev 84(2):1–9

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker GS (1962) Irrational behavior and economic theory. J Polit Econ 70(1):1–13

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker GS (1976a) Altruism, egoism, genetic fitness: and sociobiology economics. J Econ Lit 14(3):817–826

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker GS (1976b) The economic approach to human behavior. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Becker GS (1993) Nobel lecture: the economic way of looking at behavior. J Polit Econ 101(3):385–409

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker GS (2009) Interview—Gary Becker. In: Horn KI (ed) Roads to wisdom, conversations with ten nobel laureates in economics. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, pp 132–152

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim D, Rangel A (2008) Choice-theoretic foundations for behavioral welfare economics. In: Caplin A, Schotter A (eds) The foundations of positive and normative economics: a handbook. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 155–192

    Google Scholar 

  • Binmore K (2011) Rational decisions. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Blume LE, Easley D (2008) Rationality. In: Durlauf SN, Blume LE (eds) The new Palgrave dictionary of economics, 2nd edn. Palgrave Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Boumans M, John BD (2010) Economic methodology: understanding economics as a science. Palgrave Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge MA (1996) Finding philosophy in social science. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Colander D (2007) Retrospectives: Edgeworth’s hedonimeter and the quest to measure utility. J Econ Perspect 21(2):215–225

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Debreu G (1959) Theory of value: an axiomatic analysis of economic equilibrium. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Debreu G (1986) Theoretic models: mathematical form and economic content. Econometrica 54(6):1259–1270

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich F, List C (2013) A reason-based theory of rational choice. Noûs 47(1):104–134

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich F, List C (2016a) Reason-based choice and context-dependence: an explanatory framework. Econ Philos 32(2):175–229

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich F, List C (2016b) Mentalism versus behaviourism in economics: a philosophy-of-science perspective. Econ Philos 32:249–281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dow A, Dow S, Hutton A (1997) The Scottish political economy tradition and modern economics. Scott J Polit Econ 44(4):368–384

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J (2001) Human nature and the limits of science. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ellsberg D (1961) Risk, ambiguity and the Savage axioms. Q J Econ 75(4):643–669

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster J (1989) Social norms and economic theory. J Econ Perspect 3(4):99–117

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster J (1994) Rationality, emotions, and social norms. Synthese 98:21–49

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher I (2007 [1892]) Mathematical investigations in the theory of value and prices. Cosimo, Inc., New York

  • Fishburn PC (1968) Utility theory. Manag Sci 14(5):335–378

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn PC (1979) Transitivity. Rev Econ Stud 46(1):163–173

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frisch R (2009 [1933]) Problems and methods of econometrics: the Poincaré lectures of Ragnar Frisch 1933. In: Bjerkholt O, Dupont-Kieffer A (eds) Routledge studies in the history of economics. Routledge, London

  • Frisch R (2010 [1930]) A dynamic approach to economic theory: the Yale lectures of Ragnar Frisch, 1930. In: Bjerkholt O, Qin D (eds) Routledge studies in the history of economics. Routledge, London

  • Frisch R (1971 [1926]) On a problem in pure economics. In: Chipman JS et al (eds) Preferences, utility, and demand: a Minnesota symposium. Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, New York, pp 386–423

  • Gauthier D (1974) Rational cooperation. Noûs 8(1):53–65

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa I (2010) Rational choice. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Giocoli N (2003) Modeling rational agents: from interwar economics to early modern game theory. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham

    Google Scholar 

  • Giocoli N (2009) Do prudent agents play lotteries? Von Neumann’s Contribution to the theory of rational behavior. J Hist Econ Thought 28(1):95–109

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green DP, Shapiro I (1994) Pathologies of rational choice theory: the critique of applications in political science. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff T (2007) Bounded rationality. Philos Compass 2(3):534–563

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guala F (2017) Preferences: neither behavioural nor mental, Working Paper No. 5/17. http://wp.demm.unimi.it/files/wp/2017/DEMM-2017_05wp.pdf. Accessed 7 Oct 2018

  • Gul F, Pesendorfer W (2008) The case for mindless economics. In: Caplin A, Schotter A (eds) The foundations of positive and normative economics: a handbook. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 3–42

    Google Scholar 

  • Hands DW (2006) Integrability, rationalizability, and path-dependency in the history of demand theory. Hist Polit Econ 38:153–185

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hands DW (2013) Foundations of contemporary revealed preference theory. Erkenntnis 78(5):1081–1108

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman DM (1992) The inexact and separate science of economics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman DM (1995) Rational choice and social theory: a comment. J Philos 92(2):96–102

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman DM (2011) Mistakes about preferences in the social sciences. Philos Soc Sci 41(3):3–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman DM (2012) Preference, value, choice, and welfare. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Heap SH et al (1992) The theory of choice: a critical guide. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Herfeld C (2013) The many faces of rational choice theory. Witten/Herdecke University, Witten

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Herfeld C (2018) Explaining patterns, not details: reevaluating rational choice models in light of their explananda. J Econ Methodol 25(2):179–209

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herfeld C (2019) Imagination rather than observation in econometrics: Ragnar Frisch’s hypothetical experiments as thought experiments. HOPOS: J Int Soc Hist Philos Sci 9 (1)

  • Herne K, Setälä M (2004) A response to the critique of rational choice theory: Lakatos’ and Laudan’s conceptions applied. Inquiry 47(1):67–85

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hollis M, Sugden R (1993) Rationality in action. Mind 102(405):1–35

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoover K (2015) Reductionism in economics: intentionality and eschatological justification in the microfoundations of macroeconomics. Philos Sci 82(4):689–711

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D, Slovic P, Tversky A (eds) (1982) Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (2000) Battling the undead; how (and how not) to resist genetic determinism. In: Singh RS, Krimbas CB, Paul DB, Beattie J (eds) Thinking about evolution: historical philosophical and political perspectives. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 396–414

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagueux M (2004) The forgotten role of the rationality principle in economics. J Econ Methodol 11(1):31–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee CJ (2009) Reclaiming Davidson’s methodological rationalism as Galilean idealization in psychology. Philos Soc Sci 40(1):84–106

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehtinen A, Kuorikoski J (2007) Unrealistic assumptions in rational choice theory. Philos Soc Sci 37(2):115–138

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes G, Starmer C, Sugden R (1991) Observing violations of transitivity by experimental methods. Econometrica 59(2):425–439

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luce D, Raiffa H (1985) Games and decisions: introduction and critical survey. Dover Publications, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Maas H (2005) Jevons, Mill and the private laboratory of the mind. Manchester Sch 73(5):620–649

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machlup F (1978) Methodology of economics and other social sciences. Academic Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (2009) MISSing the world: models as isolations and credible surrogate systems. Erkenntnis 70(1):29–43

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mantzavinos C (2009) A note on methodological individualism. In: Mohamed C, Peter H (eds) Raymond Boudon: a life in sociology. Bardwell Press, Oxford, pp 211–215

    Google Scholar 

  • Mas-Colell A et al (1995) Microeconomic theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill JS (1874 [1844]) Essays on some unsettled questions of political economy, 2nd edn. Longmans, Greens, Reader, and Dyer, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan M (2006) Economic man as model man: ideal types, idealization and caricatures. J Hist Econ Thought 28(1):1–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S (2016) On the interpretation of decision theory. Econ Philos 32:409–433

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsen RA, Troughton GH (2000) Are risk premium anomalies caused by ambiguity? Financ Anal J 56(2):24–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paternotte C (2011) Rational choice theory. In: Jarvie I, Zamorra-Bonilla J (eds) The sage handbook of philosophy of social science, Chap. 14. Sage, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Peter F (2003) Gender and the foundations of social choice: the role of situated agency. Feminist Econ 9(2–3):13–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit P (1991) Decision theory and folk psychology. In: Bacharach M, Hurley S (eds) Foundations of decision theory: issues and advances. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 147–175

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit P (1996) The common mind: an essay on psychology, society and politics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit P (2000) Rational choice, functional selection and empty black boxes. J Econ Methodol 7(1):33–57

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reutlinger A, Hangleiter D, Hartmann S (2017) Understanding (with) toy models. Br J Philos Sci. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axx005

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robbins L (1935 [1932]) An essay on the nature and significance of economic science, 2nd edn. Macmillan, London

  • Rosenberg A (1986) What Rosenberg’s philosophy of economics is not. Philos Sci 53:127–132

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg A (2015) Philosophy of social science, 5th edn. Westview Press, Boulder

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross D (1999) What people want: the concept of utility from Bentham to game theory. University of Cape Town Press, Cape Town

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross D (2008) Ontic structural realism. Philos Sci 75:732–743

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross D (2014) Philosophy of economics. Palgrave Macmillan, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson PA (1938a) A note on the pure theory of consumer’s behavior. Economica 5(17):61–71

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson PA (1938b) A note on the pure theory of consumer’s behaviour: an addendum. Economica 5(19):353–354

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Satz D, Ferejohn J (1994) Rational choice and social theory. J Philos 91(2):71–87

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage LJ (1972 [1954]) The foundations of statistics. Wiley, New York

  • Schulz A (2011) Gigerenzer’s evolutionary arguments against rational choice theory: an assessment. Philos Sci 78(5):1272–1282

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (2002) Rationality and freedom. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1955) A behavioral model of rational choice. Q J Econ 69(1):99–118

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steele K (2014) Choice models. In: Cartwright N, Montushi E (eds) Philosophy of social science: a new introduction. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 185–207

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (1985) Why be consistent? A critical analysis of consistency requirements in choice theory. Economica 52(206):167–183

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (1991) Rational choice: a survey of contributions from economics and philosophy. Econ J 101(407):751–785

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (2000) Credible worlds: the status of theoretical models in economics. J Econ Methodol 7(1):1–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (2005) Why rationality is not a consequence of Hume’s theory of choice. Eur J Hist Econ Thought 12(1):113–119

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P (1961) The philosophical relevance of decision theory. J Philos 58(21):605–614

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Udehn L (2001) Methodological individualism: background, history and meaning. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Udehn L (2002) The methodology of rational choice. In: Turner SP, Roth PA (eds) The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of the social sciences. Blackwell Publishers, Oxford, pp 1–18

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg VJ (2004) The rationality postulate in economics: its ambiguity, its deficiency and its evolutionary alternative. J Econ Methodol 11(1):1–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varian HR (2010) Intermediate microeconomics: a modern approach, 8th edn. Norton Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Neumann J, Morgenstern O (1953 [1994]) Theory of games and economic behavior, 3rd edn. Princeton University Press, Princeton

  • Vriend NJ (1996) Rational behavior and economic theory. J Econ Behav Organ 29(2):263–285

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weintraub ER (2002) How economics became a mathematical science. Duke University Press, Durham

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Paul Dudenhefer for his edits and three anonymous referees for providing very helpful feedback on the paper.

Funding

This project was not financially supported by any funding agency or third party. I am fully responsible for the content of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Catherine Herfeld.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

I hereby declare that I do not have any conflict of interests that could arise.

Research Involving Human and Animal Participants

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Herfeld, C. The Diversity of Rational Choice Theory: A Review Note. Topoi 39, 329–347 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-018-9588-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-018-9588-7

Keywords

Navigation