Skip to main content
Log in

Accounting for Experiences as of Passage: Why Topology Isn’t Enough

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Time appears to us to pass. Some philosophers think that we should account for these experiences by appeal to change in what there unrestrictedly is (i.e. ontological change). I argue that such an appeal can only be the beginning of an account of passage. To show this, I consider a minimal type of view—a purely topological view—that attempts to account for experiences as of passage by an appeal to ontological change and topological features of the present. I argue that, if ontological change is needed to account for our experiences as of passage, then there are other features of our experiences as of passage that a purely topological view does not have the resources to explain. These features include the implacability of time’s passage, the orderliness of time’s passage, and the impossibility of a having a past that was never present.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. E.g. Broad 1927; Bourne 2006; McCall 1994; Bigelow 1996; Mackie 1974 and many others.

  2. I shall not consider the question of whether a dynamic view is needed to account for our experiences as of passage at all, though such questions are raised by been raised by Paul (2010) and Callendar (2012).

  3. I shall be restricting my attention to views which set things up in terms of change in what there is, where ‘what there is’ is neutral, and unrestricted, with respect to whether the event in question is present. Some views that might like the epithet ‘dynamic’ do not require ontological change, but change in what is predicated. Since I’m considering the role of topological features here, discussion of such views is beyond the scope of this paper.

  4. Ersatz times might be made out of maximally consistent sets of propositions ordered to create sequences, for example.

  5. Cf. Bourne (2006), pp. 12–13; Callendar (2012), p. 75; Dainton (2012), p. 124.

  6. See footnote 5, above.

  7. Or rather, the earth’s spinning will slow despite my interventions. See http://what-if.xkcd.com/26/.

  8. Ignoring the fact that one cannot provide an account for anything without time in which to do so.

  9. I phrase it in this way to forestall the objection that I am raising a question that the semantics doesn’t allow, discussed in Sect. 5.

  10. There may be some exceptions to this general rule. Such exceptions will be very unusual, however, so even if we allow such cases, the difference between those cases and the case where we must first train in order to have trained becomes even more striking.

  11. This is a purely topological version of Craig Bourne (2006) Ersatzer Presentism.

  12. Cf. Russell (1921).

  13. Cf. Briggs and Forbes (2012).

References

  • Bigelow J (1996) Presentism and possibilities. Philos Perspect 10:35–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourne C (2006) A future for presentism. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Briggs R, Forbes GA (2012) The real truth about the unreal future. In: Bennett K, Zimmerman D (eds) Oxford studies in metaphysics, vol 7, Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Broad CD (1927) Scientific thought. Keagan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Callendar C (2012) Time’s ontic voltage. In: Bardon A (ed) The future of the philosophy of time. Routledge, London, pp 73–98

    Google Scholar 

  • Dainton B (2012) Time and temporal experience. In: Bardon A (ed) The future of the philosophy of time. Routledge, London, pp 123–148

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie JL (1974) The cement of the universe. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • McCall S (1994) A model of the universe. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Oaklander LN (2012) A-, B-, and R-theories of time: a debate. In: Bardon A (ed) The future of the philosophy of time. Routledge, London, pp 1–24

    Google Scholar 

  • Paul LA (2010) Temporal experience. J Philos 107:333–359

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell B (1921) The analysis of mind. George and Allen Unwin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Skow B (2011) On the meaning of the question ‘How fast does time pass?’. Philos Stud 155:325–344

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to audiences at Southwestern College Kansas, Exeter, Sheffield and Kent for their feedback on presentations of this paper, and thanks also to Eric Olson, Stephen Wright, and Melissa Ebbers for incredibly useful comments and advice on drafts of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Graeme A. Forbes.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Forbes, G.A. Accounting for Experiences as of Passage: Why Topology Isn’t Enough. Topoi 34, 187–194 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-014-9254-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-014-9254-7

Keywords

Navigation