1 Introduction

Many institutions, companies, governments, and so on are organized in hierarchical structures. Typically, there is one unit at the top. In the following levels, each unit of the parent level is divided into two or more subordinate units, which usually have a lower rank than the higher ones. We can see a similar organizational structure in supply chains in some respects, and queuing problems or electricity and other networks often have hierarchical structures as well. Effectiveness increases by sharing or pooling physical objects, resources, and information. A central characteristic of all these forms of organization is that a cooperating unit can itself be an actor to gain advantages of cooperation for the members of the unit. The question arises: how should we share the benefits and allocate the costs?

To distribute the profits of cooperating coalitions, the application of a cooperative game seems to be a natural approach. Winter (1989) defined a model for cooperative games with a level structure (LS-games). A level structure comprises a sequence of coalition structures (the levels). At each level, the player set is partitioned into components where each higher level is coarser than the previous one (see also Fig. 1). Winter’s value (Winter, 1989) for LS-games, we call it Shapley levels value, extends the Owen value (Owen, 1977), which is itself an extension of the Shapley value (Shapley, 1953b). This value satisfies adaptations of the symmetry axioms, satisfied by the Owen value, for values for LS-games.

To treat symmetric players differently when there are exogenous weights for the players, Shapley (1953a) introduced the weighted Shapley values. Vidal-Puga (2012) established a value for games with a coalition structure with weights given by the size of the coalitions. With a step by step top–down algorithm, Gómez-Rúa and Vidal-Puga (2011) extended it for games with a level structure. Besner (2019) generalized this value to the class of the weighted Shapley hierarchy levels values for arbitrary, exogenously given, weights. These values satisfy an extension of the consistency property of the weighted Shapley values in Hart and Mas-Colell (1989). Interestingly, the class of the weighted Shapley hierarchy levels values contains the Shapley levels value but the values from this class do not satisfy the null player axiom in general.

The weighted values for games with a coalition structure in Levy and Mclean (1989) and McLean (1991) behave the other way round; they satisfy the null player property but do not correspond to a consistency property in the above sense. Levy and Mclean (1989) examine several classes of weighted values for games with a coalition structure which use the same weight system as the weighted Shapley values: either for the players within a component or the components themselves if the components act as players. The combined use of such a weight system, both for players and components, is only mentioned. This latter class of extensions of the weighted Shapley values and an extension of the class of random order values (Weber, 1988) for games with a coalition structure is discussed in McLean (1991). Dragan (1992) called McLean’s extensions of the weighted Shapley values McLean weighted coalition structure values. He presented a formula for them related to that of the Owen value. For a fixed coalition structure, these values coincide with a multiweighted Shapley value (Dragan, 1992).

Harsanyi (1959) introduced a new perspective on coalition functions. He used so-called (Harsanyi) dividends, assigned to all feasible coalitions of a player set according to the coalition function. Singletons receive the singleton worth as their dividend and the dividend of each larger coalition S amounts to the worth of S minus the sum of all dividends of the proper subcoalitions of S. The weighted Shapley values give the players as payoffs a share of the dividends from the coalitions in which they are members. Two players’ shares of dividends from coalitions containing both players are always in the same ratio. In comparison, the Harsanyi solutions (Hammer et al., 1977; Vasil’ev, 1978) are more flexible. By these values, two players can receive dividend shares from coalitions, containing both, in various ratios for each coalition.

In this article, we introduce the class of Harsanyi support levels solutions. To the best of our knowledge, the values of this class are the first values for games with level structure (LS-values) that extend the Harsanyi solutions. We represent each Harsanyi support levels solution by a formula with dividends. The coefficients in the formulas constitute a dividend sharing system, i. e., all coefficients are non-negative and amount to one for each coalition. According to the definition of a Harsanyi solution, each LS-value from this class corresponds to a Harsanyi solution for a fixed level structure. Therefore, Harsanyi solutions inherit all properties (adapted for LS-values) of these values for a fixed level structure.

Within the framework of LS-games, we can also consider the components of a level as players in so-called induced LS-games. Winter (1989) has shown that the Shapley levels value satisfies the level game property. This property means that the payoff to a component in an induced LS-game is equal to the sum of the payoffs to all players included in the component. We show that if an LS-value satisfies the level game property and coincides for a fixed level structure with a Harsanyi solution, the value is a member of the class of the Harsanyi support levels solutions. As a corollary, our main result extends an axiomatization of the class of the Harsanyi solutions by Vasil’ev (1981) and Derks et al. (2000) to a characterization of the class of the Harsanyi support levels solutions.

Since the Harsanyi solutions are no random order values in general, we cannot adopt the proof procedures for characterizations, e.g., in Winter (1989) or McLean (1991). We base our proofs on dividends where two new lemmas are a significant help.

As a further result, we present the class of the weighted Shapley support levels values as a proper subset of the class of the Harsanyi support levels solutions. The LS-values from this class coincide with the McLean weighted coalition structure values on a level structure with only three levels if we count the partition containing all singletons and the partition containing only the grand coalition as levels. To offer a characterization for this class, we adapt an axiomatization of the class of the weighted Shapley values in Nowak and Radzik (1995).

In the concluding section, it is briefly explained that the values presented in this article can have an interesting solidarity characteristic: players who have formed a group support the other group members even in situations where they are not active and do not expect any direct reward for their support, as with the weighted Shapley Hierarchy levels values. In this way, they differ fundamentally from solidarity-based solution concepts such as the equal division value, the equal surplus division value (Driessen and Funaki, 1991), the egalitarian Shapley values (Joosten, 1996) or the solidarity value (Nowak and Radzik, 1994) and the Shapley-solidarity value (Calvo and Gutiérrez, 2013).

The outline of the paper is structured as follows. Section 2 contains preliminaries. As the main part, we introduce in Sect. 3 the Harsanyi support levels solutions with an appropriate class axiomatization. In Sect. 4, we offer the weighted Shapley support levels values as a further result. A numerical example in Sect.  5 compares different values. Section  6 discusses the results and concludes with a fundamental principle of group solidarity which is satisfied by our new values. The Appendix (Sect.  7) provides all the proofs, related properties and lemmas, and shows the logical independence of the axioms in our axiomatizations.

2 Preliminaries

2.1 TU-games

Let \({\mathbb {R}}\) be the set of real numbers and \({\mathbb {R}}_{++}\) the set of all positive real numbers. We fix a countably infinite set \({\mathfrak {U}}^A\), the universe of atomic players. The set \({\mathfrak {U}}\), the universe of all playersFootnote 1, is defined recursively:

  1. (a)

    \(i \in {\mathfrak {U}}\) for all \(i \in {\mathfrak {U}}^A\).

  2. (b)

    For all non-empty and finite subsets \(N \subseteq {\mathfrak {U}}\), we have also \(N \in {\mathfrak {U}}\).

  3. (c)

    Nothing is in \({\mathfrak {U}}\) unless it can be shown to be there using (a) and (b).

We denote by \({\mathcal{N}}\) the set of all non-empty and finite subsets of \({\mathfrak {U}}\). A cooperative game with transferable utility (TU-game) is a pair (Nv) such that \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}\) is a set of players and \(v\!: 2^N\!\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}},\,v(\emptyset ) = 0,\) a coalition function where \(2^N\) is the power set of N. The subsets \(S\subseteq N\) are called coalitions, v(S) is the worth of coalition S, the set of all non-empty subsets of S is denoted by \(\Omega ^S\), and the set of all TU-games with player set N is denoted by \({\mathbb {V}}^N\).

Let \(N\in {\mathcal{N}},\,(N,v)\in {\mathbb {V}}^N\) and \(S\subseteq N\). The dividends \(\Delta _v(S)\) (Harsanyi, 1959) are defined inductively by

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta _v(S):={\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} & v(S)- \sum _{R\subsetneq S}\Delta _v(R), \text{ if } S \in \Omega ^N\!, \text { and}\\ & 0, \text { if }S = \emptyset . \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$
(1)

A TU-game \((N,u_T)\in {\mathbb {V}}^N\!,\,T \in \Omega ^N\), with \(u_T(S):=1\) if \(T\subseteq S\) and \(u_T(S):=0\) otherwise for all \(S\subseteq N\) is called a unanimity game. It is well known that any coalition function v on N has a unique representation

$$\begin{aligned} v=\sum _{T \in \Omega ^N}\Delta _v(T)u_T. \end{aligned}$$
(2)

(Nv) is called totally positive (Vasil’ev, 1975) if \(\Delta _v(T)\ge 0\) for all \(T\subseteq N\). Player \(i \in N\) is called a null player in (Nv) if \(v(S\cup \{i\})=v(S)\) for all \(S\subseteq N\backslash \{i\};\) players \(i,j \in N,\,i\ne j,\) are called (mutually) dependent (Nowak and Radzik, 1995) in (Nv) if \(v(S\cup \{i\})= v(S)=v(S\cup \{j\})\) for all \(S\subseteq N\backslash \{i,j\}\), which is equivalent to

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta _v(S \cup \{k\})=0, \,k \in \{i,j\}, \text { for all }S \subseteq N\backslash \{i,j\}. \end{aligned}$$
(3)

For all \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}\), a TU-value or solution \(\phi\) is an operator that assigns to any \((N,v) \in {\mathbb {V}}^N\) a payoff vector \(\phi (N,v) \in {\mathbb {R}}^{N}\).

By \(W :=\{f\!:{\mathfrak {U}}\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}_{++}\}\), \(w_i:=w(i)\) for all \(w \in W,\,i \in {\mathfrak {U}}\), we define the collection of all positive weight systems on \({\mathfrak {U}}\).

The following TU-values distribute the dividends of the coalitions proportionally to the weights of the players included in these coalitions. For all \(N\in {\mathcal{N}},\,(N,v)\in {\mathbb {V}}^N\!,\) and each \(w \in W\), the (positively) weighted Shapley value \({\textit {Sh}}^w\) (Shapley, 1953a) assigns to any (Nv) a vector in \({\mathbb {R}}^{N}\) defined as

$$\begin{aligned} {\textit {Sh}}_i^w(N,v) := \sum _{S \subseteq N,\, S \ni i}\frac{w_i}{\sum _{j \in S}w_j}\Delta _v(S) \;\text { for all } \,i \in N. \end{aligned}$$
(4)

As a special case of a weighted Shapley value, all weights are equal, the Shapley value Sh (Shapley, 1953b) assigns to any \((N,v)\in {\mathbb {V}}^N\) a vector in \({\mathbb {R}}^{N}\) defined as

$$\begin{aligned} {\textit {Sh}}_i(N,v) := \sum _{S\subseteq N,\, {S\ni i}} \frac{\Delta _v(S)}{|S|}\;\text { for all } \,i \in N. \end{aligned}$$

For all coalitions that include the same two players, for the weighted Shapley values, the dividend shares for these players are always in the same ratio. This need not be the case for the following TU-values, using sharing systems, where the ratio of the dividend shares of two players may also be different for two different coalitions containing both players. The collection \(\Lambda\) of all sharing systems \(\lambda \in \Lambda\) on \({\mathcal{N}}\) is defined by

$$\begin{aligned} \Lambda :=\Big \{\lambda =(\lambda _{S,i})_{S \in {\mathcal{N}},\, i \in S}\Big |\, \sum _{i \in S}\lambda _{S,i}=1 \text { and } \lambda _{S,i}\ge 0\text { for each }S \in {\mathcal{N}}\text { and all } i \in S \Big \}. \end{aligned}$$

Hammer et al. (1977) and Vasil’ev (1978), independently of each other, defined a class of TU-values. While Hammer et al. (1977) and, e. g., Derks et al. (2000) this class call selectopeFootnote 2, Vasil’ev (1978), Vasil’ev and van der Laan (2002), and, e. g., del Pozo et  al. (2011) refer to this class as Harsanyi set, abbreviated to \({\mathcal{H}}\). For all \(N \in {\mathcal{N}},\,(N,v)\in {\mathbb {V}}^N\), and each sharing system \(\lambda \in \Lambda\), the Harsanyi solution \(H^\lambda \in {\mathcal{H}}\) assigns to any (Nv) a vector in \({\mathbb {R}}^{N}\) defined as

$$\begin{aligned} H^\lambda _i(N,v):=\sum _{T \subseteq N,\, T \ni i}\lambda _{T,i}\Delta _v(T) \text { for all } i \in N. \end{aligned}$$

By (4), it is immediate that the class of the weighted Shapley values is a proper subset of the Harsanyi set.

2.2 LS-games

In the following, we have to restrict the amount of available player sets. We give some (a few times recursive) definitions where the underlying atomic players of players representing coalitions of players play an important role:

An atomic player \(i \in {\mathfrak {U}}^A\) is called a sub-member of a player \(j\in {\mathfrak {U}}\) if \(i=j\) or i is a sub-member of a player \(k \in {\mathfrak {U}}, \,k \in j\). A player \(i\in {\mathfrak {U}}\) is called a sub-player-coalition of a player \(j\in {\mathfrak {U}}\) if \(i=j\) or \(i \in k,\,k\) is a sub-player-coalition of j. A player set \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}\) is called sub-member-disjoint if no atomic player \(i \in {\mathfrak {U}}^A\) is a sub-member of any two sub-player-coalitions \(j,k,\,j\ne k,\) such that \(j,k \in \ell,\,\ell\) is a sub-player-coalition of N.Footnote 3 The set of all sub-member-disjoint player sets \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}\) is denoted by \({\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\).Footnote 4

For any \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\), a coalition structure \({\mathcal{B}}\) on N is a partition of the player set N, i.e., a collection of non-empty, pairwise disjoint, and mutually exhaustive subsets of N. Each \(B \in {\mathcal{B}}\) is called a component and \({\mathcal{B}}(i)\) denotes the component that contains a player \(i \in N\). A level structure (Winter, 1989) on N is a finite sequence \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}:=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!, \ldots ,{\mathcal{B}}^{h+1}\}\) of coalition structures \({\mathcal{B}}^r\!,\,0 \le r \le h+1,\) on N such that (see also Fig. 1):

  • \({\mathcal{B}}^0=\big \{\{i\}\!\!: i \in N\big \}\),

  • \({\mathcal{B}}^{h+1} =\{N\}\), and

  • for each \(r,\, 0\le r\le h,\) \({\mathcal{B}}^r\) is a refinement of \({\mathcal{B}}^{r+1}\), i. e., \({\mathcal{B}}^r\!\!\,(i) \subseteq {\mathcal{B}}^{r+1}\!\!\,(i)\) for all \(i \in N\).

\({\mathcal{B}}^r\) is called the rth level of \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}\), \(\underline{\overline{{\mathcal{B}}}}:=\{B| B \in {\mathcal{B}}^r \text { for all }{\mathcal{B}}^r \in \underline{{\mathcal{B}}},\, 0\le r\le h\}\) is the set of all components \(B \in {\mathcal{B}}^r\) of all levels \({\mathcal{B}}^r \in \underline{{\mathcal{B}}},\, 0\le r\le h\), and \({\mathbb {L}}^{N}\) denotes the set of all level structures on the player set N.

For each \(B \in {\mathcal{B}}^\ell \!,\,0\le \ell \le r\le h+1,\) we denote by \({\mathcal{B}}^{r}\!(B)\) the component of the rth level containing B as a (not necessary proper) subset; \({\mathcal{B}}^{r}\!(B)\) is called an ancestor of B; if \(r=\ell +1\), \({\mathcal{B}}^{r}\!(B)\) is also called parent of B. We call all components with the same parent \(B\in {\mathcal{B}}^r\!,\,1\le r\le h+1,\) children of B and two different children of B are called siblings in \({\mathcal{B}}^{r-1}\). We explicitly point out that a component, for different levels, can be its own child or parent at the same time.

If we regard the components of the rth level, \(0\le r\le h,\) as players and cancel all levels below the rth level, we get the induced \({\varvec{r}}\)th level structure \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}^r}:=\big \{{\mathcal{B}}^{r^{\scriptstyle 0}}\!,\ldots ,{\mathcal{B}}^{r^{\scriptstyle h+1-r}}\big \}\in {\mathbb {L}}^{{{\mathcal{B}}}^{r}}\) from \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!, \ldots ,{\mathcal{B}}^{h+1}\}\). We give an illustrating example.

Example 2.1

Let \(N=\{1,2,3\}\) and \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!,{\mathcal{B}}^1\!, {\mathcal{B}}^2\}\) be given by \({\mathcal{B}}^0\!=\{\{1\},\{2\},\{3\}\},\, {\mathcal{B}}^1\!=\{\{1,2\},\{3\}\},\) and \({\mathcal{B}}^2\!=\{N\}\). We regard, e.g., the components of the first level as players. Then, the induced first level structure \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}^1}=\{{\mathcal{B}}^{1^{\scriptstyle 0}}\!,{\mathcal{B}}^{1^{\scriptstyle 1}}\!\}\) from \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}\) is given by \({\mathcal{B}}^{1^{\scriptstyle 0}}\!=\big \{\big \{\{1,2\}\big \},\big \{\{3\}\big \}\big \},\) and \({\mathcal{B}}^{1^{\scriptstyle 1}}\!=\big \{\big \{\{1,2\},\{3\}\big \}\big \}.\)

For each \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\), a TU-game \((N,v)\in {\mathbb {V}}^N\) together with a level structure \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}} \in {\mathbb {L}}^N\) is an LS-game which is denoted by (NvB). We denote the set of all LS-games on N by \(\mathbb {VL}^N\).

If we want to stress the property that a coalition \(T\in \Omega ^N\!,\,T=\bigcup _{B\subseteq T,\,B\in {\mathcal{B}}^r}\!B,\) is the union of components of the rth level from \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}\), we denote T by \(T^r\). Each such \(T^r\) is an associated coalition to a coalition of all players \(B \!\in {\mathcal{B}}^{r}\!,\,B \subseteq T^r\!,\) in the induced rth level structure, denoted by \({\mathcal{T}}^r\!:=\{B\in {\mathcal{B}}^r\!: B \subseteq T^r\}\) and vice versa. This means that a coalition and its associated coalition have the same sub-members. Thus, for each \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\), each LS-game \((N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\), and each induced rth level structure \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}^r},\,0\le r\le h,\) we have an associated LS-game \(({\mathcal{B}}^r\!,v^r\!,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}^r})\in \mathbb {VL}^{{\mathcal{B}}^r}\), called induced \({\varvec{r}}\)th LS-gameFootnote 5, with a coalition function \(v^r\) which is given by

$$\begin{aligned} v^r\!\!\,({\mathcal{T}}^r):=v(T^r) \text { for all }{\mathcal{T}}^r\! \in \Omega ^{{\mathcal{B}}^r}\!. \end{aligned}$$
(5)

This means that a coalition in an induced LS-game that has the same sub-members as a coalition from the original game also has the same worth as this associated coalition. E.g., for the TU-game \((N,v)\in \mathbb {VL}^N\) and \({\underline{B}}\in {\mathbb {L}}^N\) in example 2.1, we have \(v^1\big (\big \{\{1,2\}\big \}\big )=v(\{1,2\})\).

Also induced LS-games for induced LS-games and so on are possible. We will not go into this in detail. Note that, for all \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\), each TU-game \((N,v)\in {\mathbb {V}}^N\) corresponds to an LS-game \((N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}_0})\in \mathbb {VL}^N\) with a trivial level structure \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}_0}:=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!,{\mathcal{B}}^1\}\) and we would like to point out that each LS-game \((N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})\in \mathbb {VL}^N\) corresponds to a game with coalition structure (Aumann and Drèze, 1974; Owen, 1977) if \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}:=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!,{\mathcal{B}}^1\!,{\mathcal{B}}^2\}\).

For all \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}},\) an LS-value \(\varphi\) is an operator on \(\mathbb {VL}^N\) that assigns to any LS-game \((N,v,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\) a payoff vector \(\varphi (N,v,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})\in \mathbb {R}^{N}\).

By \(W^{\text {dis}} \subseteq W\), we define the collection of all positive weight systems on \({\mathfrak {U}}\) where, for each \(w\in W^{\text {dis}}\), we have \(w_i= w_j\) for all \(i,j \in {\mathfrak {U}}\) if i and j have the same sub-members. This means that, e.g., for an LS-game \((N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})\in \mathbb {VL}^N\!,\,N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\!,\) we have that the weight \(w_i\) of a player \(i \in N\) is equal to the weight \(w_{\{i\}}\) of the singleton \(\{i\}\in {\mathcal{B}}^0\) in the zeroth LS-game.

We also want a corresponding relationship for sharing systems. The collection \(\Lambda ^{\text {dis}}\subseteq \Lambda\) of all sharing systems \(\lambda \in \Lambda ^{\text {dis}}\) on \({\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\) is defined by

$$\begin{aligned}&\Lambda ^{\text {dis}}:=\Big \{\lambda =(\lambda _{S,i})_{S \in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}},\, i \in S}\Big |\, \sum _{i \in S}\lambda _{S,i}=1 \text { and } \lambda _{S,i}\ge 0\text { for each }S \in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\text { and all }i \in S \\&\text { such that for all }S'\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}} \text { with } |S|=|S'| \text { and for each }i\in S \text { we have a } j\in S' \\&\text { which has the same sub-members as }i, \text { we have } \lambda _{S,i}=\lambda _{S'\!,j} \Big \} . \end{aligned}$$

This means that if we have two coalitions with the same number of players, and for every player in the first coalition we have a player in the second coalition with the same sub-members, then the related players should also have the same weight for their respective coalitions.

2.3 Axioms

We refer to the following axioms for LS-values \(\varphi\) which are mostly simple adaptations of standard axioms for TU-values. All axioms below apply for all \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\!\). We do not repeat this phrase at the beginning of each axiom.

Efficiency, E. For all \((N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\), we have \(\sum _{i \in N} \varphi _i(N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) = v(N).\)

Efficiency requires that the sum of the payoffs should result in the total worth of the game. The next property means that a player who contributes nothing to any coalition should obtain no payoff.

Null player, N. For all \((N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\) and \(i \in N\) such that i is a null player in (Nv), we have \(\varphi _i(N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) = 0\).

Additivity, A. For all \((N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}),(N,v'\!,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\), we have \(\varphi (N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})+\varphi (N,v'\!,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) =\varphi (N,v+v'\!,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})\).

Additivity states that a player’s payoff from the sum of two games is the sum of the player’s payoff for the two games. By the following axiom, all players receive a non-negative payoff if all coalitions have non-negative dividends.

Positivity, Pos (Vasil’ev, 1975). For all \((N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\) such that (Nv) is totally positive, we have \(\varphi _i(N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \ge 0\) for all \(i \in N\).

Strict monotonicity, SMon (Megiddo, 1974). For all \((N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\) and \(\alpha \in {\mathbb {R}}_{++},\) we have \(\varphi _i(N,v+\alpha \cdot u_N,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) > \varphi _i(N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})\) for all \(i \in N\).

This property means that if the grand coalition improves its worth and the worth of all other coalitions remains the same, all players should receive a higher payoff. In our investigations, the next axiom plays an important role. It claims that the sum of all players’ payoffs of a component coincides with this component’s payoff in an induced LS-game where the component is regarded as a player.

Level game property, LG (Winter, 1989). For all \((N,v,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\!,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!, \ldots ,{\mathcal{B}}^{h+1}\},\) \(B \!\in {\mathcal{B}}^r\!,\,0\le r\le h,\) we have

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{i \in B} \varphi _i(N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) =\varphi _{B}({\mathcal{B}}^r\!,v^{r}\!,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}^{r}}). \end{aligned}$$
(6)

The following axiom says that if two siblings are symmetric in the induced rth LS-game, the total payoff to all players of the first sibling is equal to the total payoff to all players of the second sibling.

Symmetry between components, SymFootnote 6  Winter (1989). For all \((N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\!,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!, \ldots ,{\mathcal{B}}^{h+1}\},\) two siblings \(B_k,B_{\ell } \in {\mathcal{B}}^r\!,\,0\le r\le h,\) such that \(B_k,B_{\ell }\) are symmetric in \(({\mathcal{B}}^r\!,v^r)\in {\mathbb {V}}^{{\mathcal{B}}^r}\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{i \in B_k} \varphi _i(N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) =\sum _{i \in B_{\ell }} \varphi _i(N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}). \end{aligned}$$

2.4 The Shapley levels value

The following formula is presented in Calvo et al. (1996, Eq. (1)).

For all \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\!,\,(N,v,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\!,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!,\ldots ,{\mathcal{B}}^{h+1}\},\) and \(T\in \Omega ^N\!,\,T \ni i,\) define

$$\begin{aligned} K_{\underline{{\mathcal{B}}},T}(i):=\prod _{r=0}^{h}K_{\underline{{\mathcal{B}}},T}^r(i),\;\text { where } K_{\underline{{\mathcal{B}}},T}^{r}(i):=\frac{1}{|\{B \in {\mathcal{B}}^{r}\!:B\!\subseteq {\mathcal{B}}^{r+1}\!\!\,(i), \, B\cap T\ne \emptyset \}|} \end{aligned}$$
(7)

be the reciprocal cardinality of the set that contains all children of the component of the \((r+1)\)th level containing player i, which contain at least one player from coalition T. Then, the Shapley levels valueFootnote 7 (Winter, 1989) \({\textit {Sh}}^L\) assigns to any \((N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})\) a vector in \({\mathbb {R}}^{N}\) defined as

$$\begin{aligned} {\textit {Sh}}^{L}_i(N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}):= \sum _{T\subseteq N, \, T \ni i}K_{\underline{{\mathcal{B}}},T}(i)\Delta _v(T) \text { for all } i \in N. \end{aligned}$$
(8)

It is easy to see that \({\textit {Sh}}^L\) coincides with Sh if \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}=\underline{{\mathcal{B}}_0}\). Winter (1989) used the Owen value (Owen, 1977) as a starting point for his LS-value. Therefore, Winter has extended the efficiency, null player, symmetry and additivity axioms to axioms for LS-values. He splits symmetry into symmetry between components and an individual symmetry axiom. If we define a level structure as above, i. e., the singletons are the elements of the lowest level, Winter (1989, remark 1.6) pointed out that we can omit the individual symmetry axiom. In this sense, we present Winter’s first axiomatization of the Shapley levels valueFootnote 8.

Theorem 2.2

(Winter, 1989) \({\textit {Sh}}^{L}\) is the unique LS-value that satisfies  E, N, Sym, and A.

It should be noted that there exist some further axiomatizations of the Shapley levels value by Calvo et al. (1996), Khmelnitskaya and Yanovskaya (2007), Casajus (2010), Álvarez-Mozos and Tejada (2011), and Besner (2019).

3 Harsanyi support levels solutions

For TU-games, there are sometimes compelling reasons, not included in the coalition function itself, to treat symmetric players differently. We can have fixed, but for each coalition possibly different, metrics for each player, representing, e. g., the effort, commitment, qualification, or power of a player. Sometimes a player’s influence on other players is stronger when another player is not on the team. Or a player can only exert its influence if specific other players have joined the coalition to support this player. The same reasoning can be applied to LS-games, where at different levels the components can be considered as players. With the Shapley levels value, the members of symmetric siblings always get the same payoff in total (Sym). The following LS-values provide the opportunity to take into account the previously mentioned external influences that are not reflected in the coalition function.

Before we give a formal definition, we describe the payoff algorithm: Let \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\!,\,(N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\!,\) \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!, \ldots ,{\mathcal{B}}^{h+1}\},\) and \(\lambda \in \Lambda ^{\text {dis}}\). By (2), v can be expressed as a linear combination of unanimity games. Thus, we have a game \(v_T:=\Delta _v(T)u_T\) for each coalition \(T\in \Omega ^N\) which means that we have \(\Delta _{v_T}(T)=\Delta _{v}(T)\), \(\Delta _{v_T}(S)=0\) for all \(S\subseteq N,\,S\ne T,\) and \(v=\sum _{T \in \Omega ^N}v_T\).

In the game \(v_T\), each component \(B^h\) of the hth level that contains at least one player \(i\in T\) receives a share of \(\Delta _{v}(T)\), proportional to its sharing weight \(\lambda _{{\mathcal{C}}_T^{h},\,B^h}\), where \({\mathcal{C}}_T^{h}\) is the coalition that contains all such components \(B^h\) as elements. Then the share of each component \(B^h\) involved is distributed among all its children \(B^{h-1}\subseteq B^h\) of the (\(h-1\))th level, containing at least one player \(i\in T\), proportional to their sharing weights \(\lambda _{{\mathcal{C}}_T^{h-1},\,B^{h-1}}\), where \({\mathcal{C}}_T^{h-1}\) is the coalition that contains all such siblings \(B_{h-1}\) as elements, and so on for all levels. In the end, each player \(i \in T\) gets its share, “supported" by the sharing weights of all its ancestors. To receive the total payoff of a player, these payoffs are finally added up over all games \(v_T\) where the player is not a null player.

Definition 3.1

For all \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\!,\, (N,v,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\!,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!, \ldots ,{\mathcal{B}}^{h+1}\},\,\lambda \in \Lambda ^{\text {dis}}\), and \(T \in \Omega ^N\!,\,T\ni i,\,0 \le r\le h,\) let

$$\begin{aligned} {\mathcal{C}}^{r}_{T}(i):=\big \{B: B\in {\mathcal{B}}^{r}\!,\,B\subseteq {\mathcal{B}}^{r+1}\!\!\,(i),\,B\cap T\ne \emptyset \big \} \end{aligned}$$
(9)

be the set that contains all children of the component of the \((r+1)\)th level containing player i, which contain at least one player from coalition T. Define

$$\begin{aligned} K_{\underline{{\mathcal{B}}},T}^\lambda (i):=\prod _{r=0}^{h}\lambda _{{\mathcal{C}}^{r}_{T}(i),\,{\mathcal{B}}^{r}\!\!\,(i)}. \end{aligned}$$
(10)

Then, for each \(\lambda \in \Lambda ^{\text {dis}}\), the Harsanyi support levels solution \(H^{\lambda \textit{SL}}\) assigns to any \((N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})\) a vector in \(\mathbb {R}^{N}\) defined as

$$\begin{aligned} H^{\lambda \textit{SL}}_i(N,v,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})= \sum _{T\subseteq N, \,T\ni i}K_{\underline{{\mathcal{B}}},T}^\lambda (i)\Delta _{v}(T) \text { for all } i \in N. \end{aligned}$$
(11)

The class of all Harsanyi support levels solutions is called Harsanyi support levels set and is denoted by \({\mathcal{H}}^{SL}\).

Remark 3.2

We see that the Shapley levels value is a Harsanyi support levels solution with a \(\lambda \in \Lambda ^{\text {dis}}\) such that we have for each \(\lambda _{{\mathcal{C}}^{r}_{T}(i),\,{\mathcal{B}}^{r}\!\!\,(i)}\) in (10) a \(K_{\underline{{\mathcal{B}}},T}^{r}(i)\) in (7) with \(\lambda _{{\mathcal{C}}^{r}_{T}(i),\,{\mathcal{B}}^{r}\!\!\,(i)}=K_{\underline{{\mathcal{B}}},T}^{r}(i)\).

Remark 3.3

For each \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\!,\,(N,v,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\!,\,\lambda \in \Lambda ^{\text {dis}},\) and for all \(T \in \Omega ^N\!,\) \(T \ni i\), we have \(\sum _{i \in T}K_{\underline{{\mathcal{B}}},T}^\lambda (i)=1\) and \(K_{\underline{{\mathcal{B}}},T}^\lambda (i)\ge 0\). Therefore, for fixed N and \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}\in {\mathbb {L}}^N\), each \(H^{\lambda \textit{SL}}\!\in {\mathcal{H}}^{SL}\) on \((N,v,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})\) coincides with a \(H^{\lambda '}\!\in {\mathcal{H}},\,\lambda '\in \Lambda ,\) on \((N,v)\in {\mathbb {V}}^N\!\), where \(\lambda '_{T,i}=K_{\underline{{\mathcal{B}}},T}^\lambda (i)\) for each \(T\in \Omega ^N\) and all \(i \in T\) and the level structure is disregarded.

To prepare our main result, we first assume that a sharing system \(\lambda \in \Lambda ^{\text {dis}}\) is exogenously given. We use a technical property for unanimity games with some factor.

Let \(\lambda \in \Lambda ^{\text {dis}}\). Then an LS-value \(\varphi\) satisfies \(\lambda\)-balanced sharing between components in unanimity games (with some factor), SCUλ, if for each \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\!,\,(N,v,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\!,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!, \ldots ,{\mathcal{B}}^{h+1}\},\) and for all \(\alpha \in {\mathbb {R}}\) and \(T\!\in \Omega ^N\!,\) two siblings \(B_k,B_{\ell } \in {\mathcal{B}}^r\!,\,0\le r\le h,\,B_k,B_{\ell }\cap T\ne \emptyset ,\) and \({\mathcal{C}}^{r}_{T}(B_k):=\big \{B: B\in {\mathcal{B}}^{r}\!,\,B\subseteq {\mathcal{B}}^{r+1}\!\!\,(B_k),\,B\cap T\ne \emptyset \big \}\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} \lambda _{{\mathcal{C}}^{r}_{T}(B_k),\,B_\ell }\sum _{i \in B_k}\!\varphi _i(N,\alpha \cdot u_{T},\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) = \lambda _{{\mathcal{C}}^{r}_{T}(B_k),\,B_k}\sum _{i \in B_\ell }\!\varphi _i(N,\alpha \cdot u_{T},\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}). \end{aligned}$$
(12)

This property says that for two siblings which contain both at least one player from T the ratio of the payoff totals to all players of the two siblings in the unanimity game is equal to the ratio of the sharing weights of both siblings. The sharing weights refer to the partition that has as elements all siblings containing players from T.

The following proposition lists some axioms that are satisfied by a Harsanyi support levels solution.

Proposition 3.4

Let \(\lambda \in \Lambda ^{\text {dis}}\). \(H^{\lambda \textit{SL}}\) satisfies E, N, A, Pos, SCUλ, and LG.

We present a first axiomatization that replaces Sym in Theorem 2.2 by SCUλ.

Proposition 3.5

Let \(\lambda \in \Lambda ^{\text {dis}}\). \(H^{\lambda \textit{SL}}\) is the unique LS-value that satisfies E, N, SCUλ, and A.

It follows that the Harsanyi support levels solutions have an exceptional status among extensions of Harsanyi solutions for LS-games.

Theorem 3.6

An LS-value \(\varphi\) coincides for any fixed \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\) and \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}\in {\mathbb {L}}^N\) with a Harsanyi solution and satisfies LG if and only if \(\varphi \in {\mathcal{H}}^{SL}\).

By Theorem 3.6 and the famous characterizationFootnote 9 of the Harsanyi set in Derks et al. (2000) by E, N, Pos, and A, the following corollary is immediate.

Corollary 3.7

An LS-value \(\varphi\) satisfies E, N, Pos, A, and LG if and only if \(\varphi \in {\mathcal{H}}^{SL}\).

4 Weighted Shapley support levels values

For applications, the class of weighted Shapley values is an important subset of the Harsanyi set. Therefore, we would like to highlight the following subset of the Harsanyi support levels set that extends the class of weighted Shapley values for LS-games. Each possible coalition is assigned a positive weight. In contrary to the weighted Shapley hierarchy levels values (with the exception of the Shapley levels value), these values satisfy the null player property.

Again, we briefly describe how the dividends are distributed by the following LS-values. Let \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\!,\, (N,v,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\!,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!, \ldots ,{\mathcal{B}}^{h+1}\},\) and \(w \in W^{\text {dis}}.\) The dividends of each coalition \(T\in \Omega ^N\) are divided as follows: Each component \(B^h\) of the hth level that contains at least one player \(i\in T\) receives a share of \(\Delta _{v}(T)\), proportional to its weight \(w_{B^h}\). Then the share of each component \(B^h\) involved is distributed among all its children \(B^{h-1}\subseteq B^h\) containing at least one player \(i\in T\), proportional to their weights \(w_{B^{h-1}}\), and so on for all levels. In the end, each player \(i \in T\) gets its share, “supported" by the weights of all its ancestors.

Definition 4.1

For all \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\!,\, (N,v,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\!,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!, \ldots ,{\mathcal{B}}^{h+1}\},\,w \in W^{\text {dis}},\) and for all \(T\in \Omega ^N\!,\) \(T \ni i,\) define

$$\begin{aligned} K_{\underline{{\mathcal{B}}},T}^w(i):=\prod _{r=0}^{h}\frac{w_{{\mathcal{B}}^{r}\!\!\,(i)}}{\sum _{\begin{subarray}{c} B \in {\mathcal{B}}^{r}:\,B\subseteq {\mathcal{B}}^{r+1}\!\!\,(i),\\ \quad \,\, {B\cap T\ne \emptyset} \end{subarray}}w_{B}}. \end{aligned}$$
(13)

Then, for each \(w \in W^{\text {dis}},\) the weighted Shapley support levels value \({\textit {Sh}}^\textit{wSL}\) assigns to any \((N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})\) a vector in \({\mathbb {R}}^{N}\) defined as

$$\begin{aligned} {\textit {Sh}}^\textit{wSL}_i(N,v,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})= \sum _{T\subseteq N, \,T\ni i}K_{\underline{{\mathcal{B}}},T}^w(i)\Delta _{v}(T) \text { for all } i \in N. \end{aligned}$$
(14)

The class of all weighted Shapley support levels values is denoted by \(\mathcal{WS}^{SL}\).

Remark 4.2

If the weights for all coalitions are equal, (13) coincides with (7). Therefore, the Shapley levels value is also a member of the class of the weighted Shapley support levels values.

Remark 4.3

For all \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\) and level structures \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}\in {\mathbb {L}}^N\!,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!, \ldots ,{\mathcal{B}}^{h+1}\}\), a weighted Shapley levels value \({\textit {Sh}}^\textit{wSL}\) coincides with a Harsanyi support levels solution \(H^{\lambda \textit{SL}}\) where we have

$$\begin{aligned} \lambda _{{\mathcal{C}}^{r}_{T}(i),\,{\mathcal{B}}^{r}\!\!\,(i)}=\frac{w_{{\mathcal{B}}^{r}\!\!\,(i)}}{\sum _{\begin{subarray}{c} B \in {\mathcal{B}}^{r}:\,B\subseteq {\mathcal{B}}^{r+1}\!\!\,(i),\\ \quad \,\, {B\cap T\ne \emptyset} \end{subarray}}w_{B}} \text { for all }T\in \Omega ^N\!. \end{aligned}$$

\({\textit {Sh}}^\textit{wSL}\) coincides with \({\textit {Sh}}^w\) if \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}=\underline{{\mathcal{B}}_0}\) and, if \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!, {\mathcal{B}}^{1}\!, {\mathcal{B}}^{2}\}\), the \(K_{\underline{{\mathcal{B}}},T}^w(i)\) coincide with the “\(\lambda ^S_i\)” given in Dragan (1992, Sec. 2(e)). Therefore, in this case, the \({\textit {Sh}}^\textit{wSL}\) coincide with the McLean weighted coalition structure values (Levy and Mclean, 1989; McLean, 1991; Dragan, 1992).

Dependent players are always symmetric but not vice versa. Therefore, our next axiom can be seen as a weighted weakening of Sym. The version for TU-values of this axiom comes from Nowak and Radzik (1995, Axiom A4 (w-Mutual Dependence)).

Let \(w \in W^{\text {dis}}\). Then an LS-value \(\varphi\) satisfies w-weighted dependence between components, Depw, if for all \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\!,\, (N,v,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})\) \(\in \mathbb {VL}^N\!,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!, \ldots ,{\mathcal{B}}^{h+1}\},\) two siblings \(B_k,B_{\ell } \in {\mathcal{B}}^r\!,\,0\le r\le h,\) such that \(B_k,B_{\ell }\) are dependent in \(({\mathcal{B}}^r\!,v^r)\in {\mathbb {V}}^{{\mathcal{B}}^r}\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{i \in B_k} \frac{\varphi _i(N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})}{w_{B_k}} =\sum _{i \in B_{\ell }} \frac{\varphi _i(N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})}{w_{B_{\ell }}}. \end{aligned}$$

The meaning of this axiom is that if two siblings are dependent in the rth LS-game the ratio of the sum of all players’ payoffs from the two siblings is equal to the ratio of the weights of both siblings. It follows an extension of the mutual dependence axiom in Nowak and Radzik (1995, Axiom 7).

Mutual dependence between components, MDep : For all \(N\in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}}\!,\,(N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})\), \((N,v',\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\!,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!, \ldots ,{\mathcal{B}}^{h+1}\},\) two siblings \(B_k,B_{\ell } \in {\mathcal{B}}^r\!,\,0\le r\le h,\) such that \(B_k,B_{\ell }\) are dependent in \(({\mathcal{B}}^r\!,v^r)\in {\mathbb {V}}^{{\mathcal{B}}^r}\) and \(({\mathcal{B}}^r\!,{v'}^r)\in {\mathbb {V}}^{{\mathcal{B}}^r}\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} \bigg (\sum _{i \in B_k}\varphi _i(N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})\bigg )\sum _{i \in B_\ell }\varphi _i(N,v',\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) = \bigg (\sum _{i \in B_\ell }\varphi _i(N,v,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}})\bigg )\sum _{i \in B_k}\varphi _i(N,v',\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}). \end{aligned}$$

This axiom considers games where two siblings are dependent in two induced rth LS-games. Then this axiom states that the ratio of the payoff totals to all players of the siblings remains invariant for such games if none of the sums is zero. The following proposition lists some axioms that are satisfied by a weighted Shapley support levels value.

Proposition 4.4

Let \(w \in W^{\text {dis}}\). \({\textit {Sh}}^\textit{wSL}\) satisfies E, N, A, LG, SMon, Depw, and MDep.

The next proposition can be seen as an extension of characterizations of the weighted Shapley values with exogenously given weights in Nowak and Radzik (1995).

Proposition 4.5

Let \(w \in W^{\text {dis}}\). \({\textit {Sh}}^{wSL}\) is the unique LS-value that satisfies E, N, Depw, and A.

Our last theorem axiomatizes the class of all weighted Shapley support levels values. It is closely related to an axiomatization of the class of weighted Shapley values in Nowak and Radzik (1995, Theorem 2.4, Remark 2.3).

Theorem 4.6

An LS-value \(\varphi\) satisfies E, N, SMon, A, and MDep if and only if \(\varphi \in \mathcal{WS}^{SL}\).

5 Example

We give a numerical example to compare the distributions for different values. Let \((N,v,\,\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}) \in \mathbb {VL}^N\!,\,N := \{1,2,3,4,5,6,7,8,9\},\,\) and \(\underline{{\mathcal{B}}}=\{{\mathcal{B}}^0\!, {\mathcal{B}}^{1}\!,{\mathcal{B}}^{2}\!,{\mathcal{B}}^{3}\},\) with \({\mathcal{B}}^{1}\! := \{\{1,2\},\{3,4\},\{5,6\},\{7\},\{8,9\}\},\, {\mathcal{B}}^{2}\!: = \{\{1,2,3,4\},\{5,6,7\},\{8,9\}\}\) (see Fig. 1).

Fig. 1
figure 1

Structure of the components in different levels

The coalition function v is given by the following dividends:

$$\begin{array} {lll} \Delta _v(\{3\})=1, & \Delta _v(\{1,2\})=2, & \Delta _v(\{1,2,3\})=6, \\ \Delta _v(\{5,6,7\})= 6, & \Delta _v(\{1,2,5,7\})=2, & \Delta _v(\{1,2,3,8,9\})=5, \\ \Delta _v(\{5,6,7,8,9\})=6, & \Delta _v(\{1,2,3,5,6,7,8,9\})=12,\end{array}$$

and all other coalitions have zero dividends in v.

For reasons of simplicity, we choose a weight system \(w \in W^{\text {dis}}\) such that \(w_{S}:=|S|\) for all \(S\in \Omega ^N\).

Furthermore, we denote by \(i^{\#}\) the number of all sub-members of a player \(i\in {\mathfrak {U}}\). We use a level sharing system \(\lambda \in {\Lambda ^{\text {dis}}}\), given by \(\lambda _{{\mathcal{B}}^2\!,\{1,2,3,4\}}:=0.4,\,\lambda _{{\mathcal{B}}^2\!,\{5,6,7\}}:=0.3,\,\lambda _{{\mathcal{B}}^2\!,\{8,9\}}:=0.3\), and, for all other \(S \in {\mathcal{N}}^{\text {dis}},\,S\ne S'\) such that \(|S'|=|{\mathcal{B}}^2|\) and for each \(i\in S'\) we have a \(j\in {\mathcal{B}}^2\) which has the same sub-members as i, we have

$$\begin{aligned} \lambda _{S,i}:=\frac{i^{\#} }{\sum _{j \in S}j^{\#}}\text { for all }i \in S. \end{aligned}$$

It should be mentioned that here the weighted Shapley hierarchy levels value \({\textit {Sh}}^{w\!\textit{HL}}\) coincides with the LS-value presented in Gómez-Rúa and Vidal-Puga (2011). We obtain Table 1. Note that player 4 is a null player, players 1 and 2 and players 8 and 9 respectively are dependent in (Nv), and components \(\{5,6\}\) and \(\{7\}\) are dependent players in \(({\mathcal{B}}^1\!,v^1)\).

Table 1 Comparison of different values

The payoffs to the dependent players in (Nv) are equal, they have the same weights. The components which are dependent players in \(({\mathcal{B}}^1\!,v^1)\) have different weights. Thus, the payoffs to players 5 and 6 do not sum up to the payoff to player 7 for \({\textit {Sh}}^{w\textit{HL}}\), \({\textit {Sh}}^{w\textit{SL}}\) or \(H^{\lambda \textit{SL}}\). We see that the Shapley levels value benefits player 7 who has not joined a team with other players in the first level. The payoffs to players 8 and 9 are higher by \(H^{\lambda \textit{SL}}\) than by \({\textit {Sh}}^{w\textit{HL}}\) or \({\textit {Sh}}^{w\textit{SL}}\) since \(H^{\lambda \textit{SL}}\) takes into account the higher weight of the component \(\{8,9\}\) within \({\mathcal{B}}^2\) in the level sharing system \(\lambda\) compared to that in the weight system w.

6 Conclusion and discussion

The rapidly increasing volume of collected data and global networking make it possible and necessary to share benefits between cooperating actors, often hierarchically structured. According to the above examinations, for the distribution of the generated surpluses, the presented LS-values of the new classes provide an alternative to the Shapley levels value and the weighted Shapley hierarchy levels values. A close examination of the definition of the Shapley levels value, given by (8), shows that in unanimity games, it is not advantageous for the individual player to merge into components: all components which are siblings have the same weight, even if a sibling is a singleton (see also the payoff to player 7 in Table 1).

The same need not apply to the LS-values of our new classes and the weighted Shapley hierarchy levels values: the greater the weight of a component, the higher the payoff in a unanimity game. By the weighted Shapley hierarchy levels values, null players also receive a positive payoff if they are part of an involved component (see Table 1) which can be seen as a reward for their contribution to the component’s weight.

On the contrary, the LS-values of the Harsanyi support levels set (and, thus, also the weighted Shapley support levels values) always leave null players without benefits. Again, it can be a great competitive advantage for the players to join forces. First, for those who form a cooperating subgroup within the carrier of a unanimity game. And then for all players who belong to coalitions with positive dividends within the whole coalition function. Here, the players of a component can “support" each other in changing unanimity games, even if they do not belong to the carrier. Nevertheless, null players do not receive any payoff, even if they contribute to the total weight of components. However, we can also interpret this in the spirit of cooperative game theory: “As a null player in this game, I support you with all my power, even if I have nothing of it at first. But I know that you as a null player in another game will support me with all your power, even if you have nothing of it there.”

This “support” is a fundamental principle of solidarity in all societies. E.g., it forms the business model of all associations and insurance companies. It can be disadvantageous, to kick a null or dummy player out of a group where everyone can rely on each other! This also means that an adaptation for LS-values of the well-known null player out property in Derks and Haller (1999) is violated, which says that removing a null player from the game does not change the payoff to the other players. An exception is the Shapley levels value. Although it belongs to both the weighted Shapley support levels values and the weighted Shapley hierarchy levels values, null players are not paid and cannot support the corresponding group with their power (weight). Here the groups are powerless in the sense that each group, regardless of size and importance which is not reflected in the coalition function, has the same weight. Despite the fact that additivity is usually considered to be of little economic importance (see, e.g., Casajus and Huettner (2014)), it takes on a new quality in the context of group formation, group solidarity, and the Harsanyi support levels solutions.