Skip to main content
Log in

On Hobbes’s state of nature and game theory

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Hobbes’s state of nature is often analyzed in two-person two-action non-cooperative games. By definition, this literature only focuses on duels. Yet, if we consider general games, i.e., with more than two agents, analyzing Hobbes’s state of nature in terms of duel is not completely satisfactory, since it is a very specific interpretation of the war of all against all. Therefore, we propose a definition of the state of nature for games with an arbitrary number of players. We show that this definition coincides with the strategy profile considered as the state of nature in two-person games. Furthermore, we study what we call rational states of nature (that is, strategy profiles which are both states of nature and Nash equilibria). We show that in rational states of nature, the utility level of any agent is equal to his maximin payoff. We also show that rational states of nature always exist in inessential games. Finally, we prove the existence of states of nature in a class of (not necessarily inessential) symmetric games.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For instance, Briggeman (2009) endogenizes the choice of a Pareto-Improving coercive strategy. Some scholars, however, argue that it is possible to spontaneously escape from the state of nature. For instance, Sugden (2005, p. 169) shows that the state of nature may not be a stable equilibrium, i.e., the equilibrium strategies are not evolutionary stable. Other arguments “poking Hobbes in the eye” (Leeson 2012) are presented in Powell and Stringham (2009) as well as in Leeson (2014).

  2. Inessential games can be thought off as generalizations of zero-sum games (see Moulin 1986).

  3. See, e.g., Barry (1965), Rawls (1976), Ullmann-Margalit (1977), Kavska (1986), Hampton (1986), Taylor (1987). Alexandra (1992) reviews these contributions. It seems that the first interpretation of the state of nature as a Nash equilibrium of a Prisoner’s Dilemma game appeared in Gauthier (1969).

  4. See, e.g., Gauthier (1969), Hampton (1986), Alexandra (1992), Skyrms (2001), Moeler (2009). Gauthier considers that Hobbes’s state of nature can be modeled as a Prisoner’s Dilemma game in the short-term, and a Stag Hunt game in the long-term.

  5. See Slomp (2000) and Slomp and La Manna (1996). See also Sugden (2005, chapter 4). Sugden ibid also analyzes the state of nature using the War of Attrition game and the Division game.

  6. See Neal (1988).

  7. See Dodds and Shoemaker (2002), Piirimaee (2006), Vanderschraaf (2006) (who relies on Taylor 1987), and Chung (2015).

  8. The inequations that appear in the second column of Table 1 are taken from Mikhael Shor’s website, Dictionary of Game Theory. Specifically, the inequation given for the Chicken game comes from Slomp and La Manna (1996, p. 57). As for the Coordination game, we use the inequations proposed by Neal (see Neal 1988, p. 642). The idea is that Treachery is a risky strategy whose success is only “momentary”.

  9. We shall always assume that the maximum and the minimum are realized.

  10. If we set \(\tilde{U}_{i} = - U_{i}\) a strategy profile \(\overline{s}\) is a state of nature if and only if it is a Berge equilibrium for the game \(G \equiv \langle N, (S_i)_{i \in N}, (\tilde{U}_i)_{i \in N} \rangle \). For a discussion of the notion of Berge equilibrium, see Collman et al. (2011) and Courtois et al. (2015).

  11. On the notion of Pareto-minimal point, see, e.g., Luptácǐk (2009, p. 226).

  12. This idea parallels the explanation of the relatively low value of Treachery in Neal’s version of the Coordination game. See footnote 8.

  13. The number \(\frac{g-b}{c}\) is the tipping point of the game. When \(\frac{g-b}{c}< n\), the state of nature is no longer rational.

  14. In symmetric games, where both the objectives and the strategy sets are identical for all agents, we could still use a symmetric \(2 \times 2\) game to study states of nature (Alexandra 1992, p 3, note 22). In effect, we could consider that each agent interacts with a fictional player, who denotes all the other players. Since all agents are identical, each of them would play the same game with the fictive player. We shall not, however, use Alexandra’s idea of considering that the opponents of each agent can be aggregated as a single fictive player.

  15. As we mentioned in the introduction, some scholars, albeit not all, use symmetric games.

  16. For instance, in a three-agent setting, we would have \(U_{1}({\mathbf {s}}) = U(s_{1}, s_{2}, s_{3})\), \(U_{2}({\mathbf {s}}) = U(s_{2}, s_{1}, s_{3})\) and \(U_{3}({\mathbf {s}}) = U(s_{3}, s_{1}, s_{2})\).

  17. As an example, in a three-agent setting, we would have \(U(s_{1}, s_{2}, s_{3})= U(s_{1}, s_{3}, s_{2})\).

  18. In fact, we can show that when the function to be maximized is concave and symmetric, there always exists a symmetric solution if the set of maximizers is nonempty.

  19. Notice that if there was an agent for whom \(\alpha _{i}< U_{i}(\overline{{\mathbf {s}}})\), the vector of maximin payoffs would be Pareto-dominated, which is impossible by assumption.

  20. Notice that from the definition of the maximin payoff, we have \(U_{i}(s_{i}, \overline{\mathbb {s}}_{-i}) \le U_{i}(\overline{s}_{i},\overline{\mathbb {s}}_{-i})\) for all \(s_{i} \in S\).

References

  • Alexandra, A. (1992). Should Hobbes’s state of nature be represented as a Prisoner’s Dilemma? The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 30(2), 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barry, B. (1965). Political argument. London: RKP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Binmore, K. G. (1982b). Fun and games. D.C. Heath and Company: Lexington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Briggeman, J. (2009). Governance as a strategy in state-of-nature games. Public Choice, 141, 481–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, M. (2001). Mathematical economics. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chung, H. (2015). Hobbes’s state of nature: A modern Bayesian game-theoretic analysis. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 1(3), 485–508.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collman, A. M., Koerner, T. W., Musy, O., & Tazdait, T. (2011). Mutual support in games: Some properties of Berge equilibria. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 55(2), 166–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Courtois, P., Nessah, R., & Tazdait, T. (2015). How to play games? Nash versus Berge behavior rules, 2015. Economics and Philosophy, 31(1), 123–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Curley, E. (1989–1990). Reflections on Hobbes: Recent work on his moral and political philosophy. Journal of Philosophical Research, XV, 169–250.

  • Dockès, P. (2008). Hobbes. Economie, terreur et politique, Economica

  • Dodds, G. G., & Shoemaker, D. W. (2002). Why we can’t all just get along: Human variety and game theory in Hobbes’s state of nature. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 40, 345–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, D. (1969). The logic of Leviathan. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hampton, J. (1986). Hobbes and the social contract tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, T. (1981), Leviathan. London: Penguin Classics.

  • Kavska, G. (1986). Hobbesian moral and political theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kydd, A. H. (2015). International relations theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leeson, P. (2012). Poking Hobbes in the eye: A plea for mechanism in anarchist history. Common Knowledge, 18(3), 541–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leeson, P. (2014). Anarchy unbound: Why self-governance works better than you think. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Luptácǐk, M. (2009). Mathematical optimization and economic analysis. Springer optimization and its application (Vol. 36). New York: Springer.

  • Moeler, M. (2009). Why Hobbes’ state of nature is best model by an assurance game. Utilitas, 21(3), 297–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulin, H. (1986) [1981]. Game theory for the social sciences. New-York: NYU Press.

  • Neal, P. (1988). Hobbes and the rational choice theory. Western Political Quarterly, 41, 635–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piirimaee, P. (2006). The explanation of conflict in Hobbes’s Leviathan. Trames, 10(60/55), 1, 3–21.

  • Powell, B., & Stringham, E. P. (2009). Public choice and the economic analysis of anarchy: A survey. Public Choice, 140, 503–538.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1976). A theory of justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (2001). The stag hunt. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 75, 31–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slomp, G. (2000). Thomas Hobbes and the political philosophy of glory. London: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Slomp, G., & La Manna, M. M. A. (1996). Hobbes, Harsanyi and the edge of the abyss. Canadian Journal of Political Science, 29(1), 47–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2005). The economics of rights, cooperation and welfare (2nd ed.). New York: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, M. (1987). The possibility of cooperation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ullmann-Margalit, E. (1977). The emergence of norms. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanderschraaf, P. (2006). War or peace?: A dynamical analysis of anarchy. Economics and Philosophy, 22, 243–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bertrand Crettez.

Additional information

B. Crettez thank Naila Hayek, Olivier Musy, and Gabrielle Smart for very helpful remark on a previous version of this paper.

Appendix A: Proofs of the propositions

Appendix A: Proofs of the propositions

1.1 Proof of Proposition 1

Proof

All the games gathered in Table 1 satisfy the following necessary and sufficient condition for (Attack, Attack) to be a state of nature according to our definition:

$$\begin{aligned} U_{1}(A, A)\le & {} U_{1}(\overline{A}, A), \end{aligned}$$
(21)
$$\begin{aligned} U_{2}(A, A)\le & {} U_{2}(A, \overline{A}). \end{aligned}$$
(22)

\(\square \)

1.2 Proof of Proposition 2

Proof

To obtain Eq. (3), we can follow the arguments used by Binmore (1982) to prove his Theorems 6.2.2 and 6.3.1. By definition of the state of nature and the maximin payoff, we have for all agents i:

$$\begin{aligned} U_{i} ( \overline{s}_{i}, \overline{{\mathbf {s}}}_{-i} )= & {} \min _{{\mathbf {s}}_{-i} \in S_{-i}} U_{i} ( \overline{s}_{i}, {\mathbf {s}}_{-i}), \end{aligned}$$
(23)
$$\begin{aligned}\le & {} \max _{s_{i} \in S_{i}} \min _{{\mathbf {s}}_{-i} \in S_{-i}} U_{i} ( \overline{s}_{i}, {\mathbf {s}}_{-i} ), \end{aligned}$$
(24)
$$\begin{aligned}= & {} \alpha _{i}. \end{aligned}$$
(25)

Since the state of nature is also a Nash equilibrium, we also have for all \(s_{i} \in S_{i}\)

$$\begin{aligned} U_{i}(s_{i}, \overline{{\mathbf {s}}}_{-i})\le & {} U_{i}(\overline{s}_{i}, \overline{{\mathbf {s}}}_{-i}), \end{aligned}$$
(26)
$$\begin{aligned} \Rightarrow \min _{{\mathbf {s}}_{-i} } U_{i}(s_{i}, {\mathbf {s}}_{-i})\le & {} U_{i}(\overline{s}_{i}, \overline{{\mathbf {s}}}_{-i}). \end{aligned}$$
(27)

However, then

$$\begin{aligned} \max _{s_{i} \in S_{i}} \min _{{\mathbf {s}}_{-i} } U_{i}(s_{i}, {\mathbf {s}}_{-i})&\le U_{i}(\overline{s}_{i}, \overline{{\mathbf {s}}}_{-i}). \end{aligned}$$
(28)

This proves that \(\alpha _{i} \le U_{i}(\overline{s}_{i}, \overline{{\mathbf {s}}}_{-i})\) and thus that \(U_{i}(\overline{s}_{i}, \overline{{\mathbf {s}}}_{-i}) = \alpha _{i}\). \(\square \)

1.3 Proof of Proposition 3

Proof

Let \(\overline{{\mathbf {s}}}\) be a vector of individual strategies, such that for all i \(\min _{{\mathbf {s}}_{-i}} U_{i}(\overline{s}_{i}, {\mathbf {s}}_{-i}) = \alpha _{i}\). Then, from Theorem 2.1 of Moulin (1986), we have \(U_{i}(\overline{{\mathbf {s}}}) = \alpha _{i}\) for all i.Footnote 19 By definition of the maximin payoff, this implies that \(\overline{{\mathbf {s}}}\) is a state of nature. Now, from Theorem 2.2 of Moulin (1986), this state of nature is a Nash equilibrium, and therefore, it is also rational.Footnote 20 \(\square \)

1.4 Proof of Proposition 4

Proof

Consider individual 1. Let \(s_{1}\) be given in S. By Assumption H4, there is a unique solution \((s_{2}(s_{1}), s_{3}(s_{1}), \ldots , s_{n}(s_{1}))\) in \(S^{n-1}\) to the problem: \(\min _{{\mathbf {y}} \in S^{n-1}} U(s_{1}, {\mathbf {y}})\). By Assumption H3, this solution necessary satisfies: \(s_{2}(s_{1}) = s_{3}(s_{1}) = \cdots = s_{n}(s_{1})\). Let then \(\phi (s_{1}) \equiv s_{i}(s_{1})\), \(i \not = 1\). According to Assumption H4, \(\,\phi (.)\) is a continuous application from a compact convex set S into itself. Therefore, by Brouwer’s Theorem (see, e.g., Carter 2001, page 248), this application has a fixed-point \(s^{*}\): \(s^{*}= \phi (s^*)\). Finally, using assumptions H1–H4, we can check that the strategy profile \((s_{1}, \ldots , s_{n}) = (\overline{s}, \ldots , \overline{s})= (s^{*}, \ldots , s^{*})\) is a state of nature. That is, if any individual plays strategy \(s^*\), then the other individuals minimize his utility function by each choosing \(s^*\). \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Crettez, B. On Hobbes’s state of nature and game theory. Theory Decis 83, 499–511 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-017-9626-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-017-9626-8

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation