Skip to main content
Log in

Perceptual justification and objectual attitudes

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Some philosophers claim that perception immediately and prima facie justifies belief in virtue of its phenomenal character (Huemer, Skepticism and the veil of perception. Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, 2001; Pryor, There is immediate justification. In: Steup M, Sosa E (eds) Contemporary debates in epistemology. Blackwell, London (2014), pp. 181–202, 2005). To explain this special justificatory power, some appeal to perception’s presentational character: the idea that perceptual experience presents its objects as existing here-and-now (Chudnoff, Intuition. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2013; Berghofer, Husserl Stud 34(2):145–170, 2018). As some philosophers have noted, if perception justifies in virtue of its presentational character alone, the kind of content perception has should not matter for perceptual justification; more precisely, it should not matter whether perceptual content is propositional or not (e.g., Smithies, The epistemic role of consciousness. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2019; Kriegel, Australas J Philos, 2021. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2021.1978513). However, most philosophers tend to resist this conclusion, holding that perception must be propositional in order to justify, on the ground that all our model of justification are propositional (e.g., Gauker, Philos Perspect 26(1):19–50, 2012). This paper challenges this claim. The paper consists of a negative and a positive part. In the negative part, I discuss and reject the master argument for the propositionality of perception; the conclusion is that propositional content is neither sufficient nor necessary to explain perception’s justificatory power. In the positive part, I take this conclusion seriously and outline an objectual model of perceptual justification. I define objectual attitudes as mental states whose content is not a full proposition, but a sub-propositional representational item, such as the representation of objects, properties, and kinds (Grzankowski and Montague, Non-propositional intentionality. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2018), and show that it is plausible that some perceptions and some beliefs are attitudes of this kind. I then argue that objectual perceptual experiences have the right kind of phenomenal character and the right kind of structure to serve for immediate prima facie justification. I conclude by defending my objectual model from three objections.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The epistemic dispensability of belief for knowledge of things occurs also in Duncan’s (2020) representationalist version, in which knowledge of things is constituted by veridical representational “awareness” states. However, while it is clear how belief can be dispensable in acquaintance-based accounts of perceptual knowledge because direct contact with objects in the world has epistemic priority, it is not clear to me that belief is similarly dispensable in representationalist accounts. In fact, I believe that only an appeal to some doxastic component of perceptual experience (i.e., a belief, belief-component, or assertoric character) can fully explain the distinctive character of perceptual experience and its special epistemic role in our mental economy, as well as the relation between the two (Martin, 2002, p. 387ff.). I discuss this in Sect. 3.

  2. Something along the lines of PO, in the form here discussed, can be found in Crane (2013), Montague (2007), Kriegel (2019), and Duncan (2020), although the thesis that perception can be directed at objectual contents has important precursors, as we are going to see, in Brentano and Husserl.

  3. These remarks might remind the reader of Dretske’s distinction between fact- and object-seeing (Drestske, 1979). However, there are important differences between my account in this paper and Husserl’s and Dretske’s proposals. The first lies in the fact that both Husserl’s and Dretske’s simple seeing are thoroughly non-epistemic. Husserl writes that simple seeing cannot be part of a judgment because judging is a complex of naming and predicating; vice versa, no judgment can include a perception, because judgment is essentially non-intuitive (Husserl, 2001; cf. Mulligan, 1995, pp. 171–172). Dretske claims that simple seeing O is compatible with having no beliefs about O (1979, p. 100). Both stances are incompatible with the thesis that I shall defend in this paper, namely that seeing O is compatible only with having no prior beliefs about O; seeing O comes with (posterior) beliefs in O. This will become clearer later in the text. A second important difference is that Dretske’s simple seeing is de re, while my objectual seeing, qua a representational state, is not (see also Mulligan, 1995 for a naïve realistic interpretation of Husserl’s simple seeing).

  4. The exclamation mark is a typographic expedient I use to denote the assertoric character of perception. On the notion of assertoric force, see the next sections.

  5. Notice that Duncan must understand veridicality as equivalent to Crane’s idea of accuracy—or else, the second clause of veridicality (that Q/O is instantiated/present “as it’s represented”) would generate a truth-evaluable context; that is, it must be possible that an awareness state represents things more or less veridically without representing them in a truth evaluable manner.

  6. Following Firth (1978), it is customary to distinguish two senses in which experiences can epistemically justify belief: propositional and doxastic justification. A belief is propositionally justified when subjects have justification to hold the belief, whether or not the subject actually holds it; a belief is doxastically justified when a subject holds a belief in a justified way.

  7. Similar reconstructions can be found in Gauker (2012), Echeverri (2013), and Almäng (2014).

  8. “Only things with sentential structure can be premises of inference” (Brandom, 1997, p. 128). These propositions can also be unstructured, as in Stalnaker’s account (1984); but this view has had historically less fortune in the philosophy of perception compared to the view of propositions as structured entities.

  9. This objection can also be also formulated in phenomenological terms: What is so special about perceptual phenomenology that it can immediately justify beliefs, when no other kinds of phenomenology can? (Siegel & Silins, 2015; see Kriegel, 2021 for discussion).

  10. The propositionalist has three possible replies. (i) They can commit to a thesis for which all mental states, including pain, have propositional content; but they must give an independent argument for it (see Echeverri, 2013 for this objection). (ii) They can bite the bullet and argue that, if there are non-propositional mental states, these cannot play any justificatory role; this move narrows the scope of the propositionalist thesis and, most problematically, leaves out states that can plausibly justify, such as pain (ibid.). (iii) They can argue that it is the fact of my being in pain that justifies my belief of being in pain. (iii) Is in my opinion the strongest reply, but it does not work either. It seems wrong to say that what we perceive are facts; we judge that something is a fact; but what is the fact we judge or ‘take in’ when undergoing an illusion or when hallucinating? (Crane, 2006, p. 464).

  11. I than an anonymous reviewer for pushing me on this point. See also Pryor (2005, pp. 194–195).

  12. On the epistemic role of conscious perception vis-à-vis blindsight, see Smithies (2019, p. 76ff.).

  13. I am indebted to Mark Textor for this point.

  14. I will soon expose at length the characteristics of this model. But to give some initial plausibility to the claim, consider that objectual beliefs are not a novelty in the philosophical debate. Szabó (2003) is a classical place to start to find arguments against the reductive propositionalist analysis of belief-in statements.

  15. Cf. Husserl (2001, p. 137): “In perception the object seemed to achieve full-bodied presence, to be there in propria persona.” (orig. emph.). See also Berghofer (2018).

  16. See Textor (2007, 2021a) for discussion. See also Owen (2003) for a discussion about a similar view in Hume.

  17. To be more precise, Brentano talks of “presentation” (Vorstellung), “the fundamental way of being conscious of an object” (Crane, 2006, p. 45). The term has various translations, such as ‘representation’, ‘idea’, ‘presentation’, or ‘content’.

  18. A sense that is customary also among other philosophers such as Frege and Quine.

  19. Recall that because I write the forces of each state in their attitude component, the content of each attitude is simply \(\langle {\text{O}}\rangle\) and does not specify the force nor the kind of attitude. For the opposite view, i.e., that one can read psychological kinds off representational contents, see Montague (2022).

  20. As I understand him, Evans proposes something along these lines in his explanation of how a subject can consciously access their sub-personal informational states. This passage, according to Evans, requires conceptualization. But we should not let this fact “obscure” the general picture: “a subject can gain knowledge of his internal informational states in a very simple way: by re-using precisely those skills of conceptualization that he uses to make judgements about the world” (1982, p. 227). I think we should accept the spirit of Evans’s remark independently of his reliabilist view; in other words, we do not need to postulate special conceptual skills to explain the passage from non-conceptual, non-propositional, to conceptual and propositional content.

  21. It is difficult to say what demonstrative concepts are, not only because the literature about demonstrative concepts is controversial, but also because there is no agreement as to what concepts are. McDowell (1994) famously invokes demonstrative concepts to reply to the non-conceptualist argument that one’s conceptual capacities are by far overcome by one’s discriminatory capacities, and thus must be concept-independent (Evans, 1992). Against McDowell, Kelly (2001) maintains that demonstrative concepts are not genuine concepts as they do not allow the re-identification over time of the same perceptual item; I later quote Speaks (2005), who suggests that this may not be an essential feature of conceptual capacities (see also Camp, 2009). See also Levine (2010) for discussion about the misuse of demonstrative concepts in the case of experiential conceptualism (which I discuss in the next footnote), phenomenal concepts and concept acquisition.

  22. Levine (2010) suggests a theory of mental demonstratives (the mental equivalent of linguistic demonstratives) as directly referential semantic mechanisms, whose semantic values are the objects in the world they refer to or some features of them. Against McDowell’s experiential conceptualism, he maintains that if mental demonstratives are so, then they could not be concepts themselves nor ways of conceptualizing, but simply mental ‘pointers’ directed at some part of an already existing perceptual representation singled out in attention. I am sympathetic to the proposal because if mental demonstrative are not concepts but primitive mental functions that allow the subject to have thoughts about what they perceive, they can be freely ascribed to non-propositional thinking creatures. But while they might not be concepts themselves, I do not see why they could not be thought of ways of conceptualizing, if they serve “to incorporate the content of the perceptual representation into the thought of which it is a constituent” (Levine, 2010, p. 190–191) and if, following Speaks, to say that a creature has a demonstrative concept of F is just to say that it can have thoughts about F.

  23. On loosening up our criteria of concept ascription, see Camp (2009).

  24. Kriegel (2023) has recently developed a similar strategy.

  25. For a discussion of such cases see, e.g., Armstrong (1968), Craig (1976), Smith (2001), and Byrne (2021).

  26. This strategy is already discussed by Brentano: “Similarly, an acceptance of an object given in sensation, which is disapproved of by a higher judgement, could persist. Indeed, it is not at all clear, how the lower activity should be changed in its intrinsic character because of the occurrence of the higher activity; if the lower activity had a relation of acceptance to the outer object before, it will have it later” (Brentano 1903, p. 26. Trans. by Textor in Textor, 2007).

References

  • Almäng, J. (2014). Perception, non-propositional content and the justification of perceptual judgments. Metaphysica, 15(1), 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1968). A materialist theory of the mind. Routledge.

  • Atiq, E. H. (2021). Acquaintance, knowledge, and value. Synthese, 199(5–6), 14035–14062.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Yami, H. (1997). Against characterizing mental states as propositional attitudes. Philosophical Quarterly, 47(186), 84–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berghofer, P. (2018). Husserl’s conception of experiential justification: What it is and why it matters. Husserl Studies, 34(2), 145–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berghofer, P. (2020). Towards a phenomenological conception of experiential justification. Synthese, 197(1), 155–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1997). Study guide. In W. Sellars (Ed.), Empiricism and the philosophy of mind (pp. 119–181). Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1883). Miklosich Über Subjektlose Sätze. Wiener Zeitung, 13, 261.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1903). Von der Natur der Vorstellung. Conceptus: Zeitschrift Fur Philosophie, 21(53/54), 25–31 (1987).

  • Brentano, F. (2009). Psychology from an empirical standpoint (C. Rancurello, B. Terrell, & L. L. McAlister, Trans.). Taylor & Francis e-Library. Original work 1874.

  • Brewer, B. (1999). Perception and reason. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, B. (2005). Perceptual experience has conceptual content. In E. Sosa & M. Steup (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology. Blackwell.

  • Buchanan, R., & Grzankowski, A. (2022). Propositions as objects of the attitudes. In C. Tillman & A. Murray (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of propositions. Routledge.

  • Byrne, A. (2005). Perception and conceptual content. In E. Sosa & M. Steup (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 231–250). Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2021). Concepts, belief, and perception. In C. Demmerling & D. Schröder (Eds.), Concepts in thought, action, and emotion: New essays (pp. 60–74). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2007). Thinking with maps. Philosophical Perspectives, 21(1), 145–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2009). Putting thoughts to work: Concepts, systematicity, and stimulus-independence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 78(2), 275–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chudnoff, E. (2013). Intuition. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Church, J. (2013). Possibilities of perception. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, E. (1976). Sensory experience and the foundations of knowledge. Synthese, 33, 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2003). The intentional structure of consciousness. In Q. Smith & A. Jokic (Eds.), Consciousness: New philosophical perspectives (pp. 33–56). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2006). Brentano’s concept of intentional inexistence. In M. Textor (Ed.), The Austrian contribution to analytic philosophy (pp. 41–48). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2009). Is perception a propositional attitude? Philosophical Quarterly, 59(236), 452–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2013). The objects of thought. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1986). A coherence theory of truth and knowledge. In E. LePore (Ed.), Truth and interpretation. Perspectives on the philosophy of Donald Davidson (pp. 307–319). Blackwell.

  • Dretske, F. (1979). Simple seeing. In D. F. Gustafson & B. L. Tapscott (Eds.), Body, mind, and method. Reprinted in Perception, knowledge and belief: selected essays. Cambridge University Press (2000).

  • Duncan, M. (2020). Knowledge of things. Synthese, 197, 3559–3592. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01904-0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Echeverri, S. (2013). Is perception a source of reasons? Theoria, 79(1), 22–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, K. (2019). Objectual knowledge. In T. Raleigh & J. Knowles (Eds.), Acquaintance: New essays (pp. 260–276). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Firth, R. (1978). Are epistemic concepts reducible to ethical concepts? In A. Goldman & J. Kim (Eds.), Values and morals. D. Reidel.

  • Forbes, G. (2000). Objectual attitudes. Linguistics and Philosophy, 23(2), 141–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gauker, C. (2012). Perception without propositions. Philosophical Perspectives, 26(1), 19–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gauker, C. (2018). Do perceptions justify beliefs? The argument from “Looks” talk. In J. Gersel, R. T. Jensen, M. Thaning, & S. Overgaard (Eds.), In light of experience: Essays on reason and perception (pp. 141–160). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glüer, K. (2009). In defence of a doxastic account of experience. Mind and Language, 24(3), 297–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grzankowski, A. (2016). Attitudes towards objects. Noûs, 50(2), 314–328.

  • Grzankowski, A. (2018a). A theory of non-propositional attitudes. In A. Grzankowski & M. Montague (Eds.), Non-propositional intentionality (pp. 34–151). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grzankowski, A. (2018b). Non-propositional contents and how to find them. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 25(3–4), 233–241.

  • Grzankowski, A., & Montague, M. (Eds.) (2018). Non-propositional intentionality. Oxford University Press.

  • Huemer, M. (Ed.) (2001). Skepticism and the veil of perception. Rowman & Littlefield.

  • Husserl, E. (2001). In D. Moran (Ed.), Logical investigations (Vol. II) (J. N. Findlay, Trans.). Routledge. Original work 1900–1901.

  • Kelly, S. D. (2001). Demonstrative concepts and experience. Philosophical Review, 110(3), 397–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2015). How to speak of existence. A Brentanian approach to (linguistic and mental) ontological commitment. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 91(1), 81–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2019). Phenomenal intentionality and the perception/cognition divide. In A. Sullivan (Ed.), Sensations, thoughts, and language: Essays in honor of Brian Loar. Routledge.

  • Kriegel, U. (2021). The structure of phenomenal justification. Australasian Journal of Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2021.1978513

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2023). The structure of phenomenal justification. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 101(2), 282–297.

  • Levine, J. (2010). Demonstrative thought. Mind and Language, 25(2), 169–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (2002). The transparency of experience. Mind and Language, 17(4), 376–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (2005). Seeing, doing, and knowing: A philosophical theory of sense perception. Oxford University Press.

  • McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2009), Avoiding the myth of the given. In The engaged intellect Cambridge (pp. 256–274). Harvard University Press.

  • Mendelovici, A. (2018). Propositionalism without propositions, objectualism without objects. In A. Grzankowski & M. Montague (Eds.), Non-propositional intentionality (pp. 214–233). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, M. (2007). Against propositionalism. Noûs, 41(3), 503–518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montague, M. (2022). Rethinking the attitudes. In U. Kriegel (Ed.), Oxford studies in philosophy of mind (Vol. 2). https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780192856685.003.0009

  • Mulligan, K. (1995). Perception. In B. Smith & D. W. Smith (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Husserl (pp. 168–238). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan, K. (2003). Seeing, certainty and apprehension. In H. Fossheim, T. M. Larsen, & J. R. Sapeng (Eds.), Non-conceptual aspects of experience (pp. 27–44). Oslo Unipub Forlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Owen, D. (2003). Locke and Hume on belief, judgment and assent. Topoi, 22(1), 15–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pagin, P., & Neri M. (2021). Assertion. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/assertion/

  • Papineau, D. (2021). The metaphysics of sensory experience. Oxford University Press.

  • Pelser, A. (2010). Belief in Reid’s theory of perception. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 27(4), 359–378.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pryor, J. (2000). The skeptic and the dogmatist. Noûs, 34(4), 517–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pryor, J. (2005). There is immediate justification. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 181–202). Blackwell (2014).

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1956). Quantifiers and propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 53(5), 177–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shin, S. J. (1994). The logical status of diagrams. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. (2006). Subject and object in the contents of visual experience. Philosophical Review, 115(3), 355–388.

  • Siegel, S. (2010). The contents of visual experience. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S., & Silins, N. (2015). The epistemology of perception. In M. Mohan (Ed.), Oxford handbook of philosophy of perception. Oxford University Press.

  • Smith, D. A. (2001). Perception and belief. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62, 283–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smithies, D. (2019). The epistemic role of consciousness. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Speaks, J. (2005). Is there a problem about nonconceptual content? Philosophical Review, 114(3), 359–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szabó, Z. G. (2003). Believing in things. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66(3), 584–611.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Textor, M. (2007). 5. Seeing something and believing IN it. In M. M. McCabe & M. Textor (Eds.), Perspectives on perception (pp. 65–86). De Gruyter. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110327557.65

  • Textor, M. (2021a). Acquaintance, presentation and judgement: From Brentano to Russell and back again. Inquiry. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2021.1899043

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Textor, M. (2021b). States of affairs. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (summer 2021 edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/states-of-affairs/

  • Thagard, P. (2006). Desires are not propositional attitudes. Dialogue, 45(1), 151–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Previous versions of this paper have been presented at the Vienna Language and Mind Workshop, the 2021 London Graduate Philosophy Conference and the 2022 SoPhA Workshop for Young Researchers at the University of Geneva; I thank the audience for their useful insights. I would also like to thank Tim Crane, Kerem Eroglu, Katalin Farkas, and Mark Textor for their help and guidance. Finally, I am grateful to four anonymous reviewers, whose thorough and patient comments have sensibly improved this paper.

Funding

The research supporting this article was partly sponsored by Central European University Foundation of Budapest (CEUBPF). The theses explained herein represent the ideas of the author, and do not necessarily reflect the views of CEUBPF.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Valentina Martinis.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author has no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Martinis, V. Perceptual justification and objectual attitudes. Synthese 203, 165 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-024-04597-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-024-04597-w

Keywords

Navigation