Skip to main content
Log in

HOTT and heavy: higher-order thought theory and the theory-heavy approach to animal consciousness

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to what Birch (2022) calls the theory-heavy approach to investigating nonhuman-animal consciousness, we select one of the well-developed theories of consciousness currently debated within contemporary cognitive science and investigate whether animals exhibit the neural structures or cognitive abilities posited by that theory as sufficient for consciousness. Birch argues, however, that this approach is in general problematic because it faces what he dubs the dilemma of demandingness—roughly, that we cannot use theories that are based on the human case to assess consciousness in nonhuman animals and vice versa. We argue here that, though this dilemma may problematize the application of many current accounts of consciousness to nonhuman animals, it does not challenge the use of standard versions of the higher-order thought theory (“HOTT”) of consciousness, according to which a creature is in a conscious mental state just in case it is aware of being in that state via a suitable higher-order thought (“HOT”). We show this in two ways. First, we argue that, unlike many extant theories of consciousness, HOTT is typically motivated by a commonsense, and more importantly, neutral condition on consciousness that applies to humans and animals alike. Second, we offer new empirical and theoretical reasons to think that many nonhuman animals possess the relevant HOTs necessary for consciousness. Considering these issues not only reveals the explanatory power of HOTT and some of its advantages over rival accounts, but also enables us to further extend and clarify the theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Henceforth we typically drop the ‘nonhuman’ qualifier, and refer to such creatures as ‘animals’.

  2. On various uses of ‘consciousness’ and related expressions, see, e.g., Berger & Brown, 2021: Sect. 2. Going forward, uses of such expressions refer to phenomenal consciousness, unless otherwise specified.

  3. For an overview of such theories, see, e.g., Seth & Bayne, 2022.

  4. Although the objection is often framed in terms of human infants too, we focus here on the case of nonhuman animals, though what we say here arguably extend to infants as well.

  5. For a recent defense of HOTT, including replies to many objections, see, e.g., Berger & Brown, 2021.

  6. We acknowledge that some of the evidence of nonconscious perception has recently been challenged (see, e.g., Phillips, 2021). Some urge that what might seem to be evidence for subliminal perception is instead evidence for either for weakly conscious states that are simply unreported due to stringent criteria for such responses or for nonmental states that are incapable of driving genuine action. But skepticism about nonconscious mentality is questionable for several reasons that we cannot explore here (but see, e.g., Berger & Mylopoulos, 2021).

  7. Lycan has since given up HOP theory; see, e.g., Sauret & Lycan, 2014.

  8. Some theories, such as IIT, may also have organism-neutral motivations. But the conditions for consciousness on such theories are thereby typically so undemanding that they face not the necessity, but the sufficiency, horn of the dilemma. On typical interpretations of IIT, for example, the theory is highly undemanding insofar as it attributes consciousness not only to all nonhuman animals, but to anything that exhibits a sufficiently high degree of informational integration, including simple nonliving systems such as logic gates (e.g., Tononi & Koch, 2015). So, while HOTT may not have an advantage over such theories in this connection, it does have an advantage insofar as it does not face the sufficiency horn, as we argue shortly.

  9. We thank Richard Brown for raising this objection to us.

  10. Our account nonetheless differs from Gennaro’s in certain ways. Perhaps most saliently, Gennaro defends both a version of concept nativism, on which some concepts are innate, and a form of conceptualism, on which experiential states such as perceptual states are, like ordinary thoughts, conceptual states too. But we remain neutral here regarding both nativism and conceptualism. Notice, however, that HOTT does not presuppose either. Though, on HOTT, HOTs are conceptual as well as necessary and sufficient for consciousness, HOTs are themselves also typically theorized to be seldom conscious (see, e.g., Rosenthal, 2005, p. 9). Rather, they are the states in virtue of which perceptual or other states are conscious. HOTT is thus compatible with perceptual states’ being nonconceptual in some way (for a version of nonconceptualism about perception, see, e.g., Dretske, 1995). It is thus reasonable to think that all concepts might be acquired via a learning process involving perception that is both nonconceptual and nonconscious (for a similar type of account, see, e.g., Rosenthal, 2005, pp. 203ff).

  11. To be clear, we are not assuming an inferentialist or conceptual-role account of the nature of conceptual content on which concepts’ contents are individuated by those concepts’ roles in inference—that is, in terms of their inferential connections to other concepts (e.g., Harman, 1987). Our account of ease of concept acquisition is consistent with virtually any theory of the metaphysics of content, such as varieties of teleosemantics on which a concept’s content depends only on its standing in the appropriate evolutionarily developed tracking relation to what it represents (e.g., Neander, 2006). It may be that concepts are variably difficult to acquire insofar as they require possessing different ranges of concepts, though possessing those different ranges of concepts is what puts a concept into the relevant tracking relation, thereby determining that concept’s content.

  12. One might think that there is good evidence that nonhumans can be and often are aware of cognitive states—namely, in cases of animal metacognition (see, e.g., Beran, 2019; we thank Robert van Gulick for this objection). But there are several things to say. First, we are not committed to the view that no nonhuman animals possess conscious thoughts. Indeed, we believe HOTT would be even more welcomed if it attributed types of consciousness more widely. Secondly, however, it is not obvious that metacognition involves the deployment of concepts of other mental states. It could be, for example, that the metacognitive assessment of a state as being accurate or inaccurate operates nonconceptually or subpersonally (e.g., Lau, 2022).

  13. Of course, such a three-fold distinction requires an account of the nature of personal-level mental states independent of consciousness. But many theories within the metaphysics of mind, such as varieties of identity theory or functionalism, are compatible with the individuation of mental states in terms of their neural bases or causal roles, which can occur outside of consciousness.

References

  • Baars, B. J. (1988). A cognitive theory of consciousness. Cambridge University Press.

  • Barron, A. B., & Klein, C. (2016). What insects can tell us about the origins of consciousness. Proceedings of the National Academic of Science, 113, 4900–4908.

    Article  CAS  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T., Frohlich, J., Cusack, R., Moser, J., & Naci, L. (2023). Consciousness in the cradle: On the emergence of infant experience. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, S1364-6613(23), 00214–00210.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beran, M. J. (2019). Animal metacognition: A decade of progress, problems, and the development of new prospects. Animal Behavior and Cognition, 6(4), 223–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger, J., & Brown, R. (2021). Conceptualizing consciousness. Philosophical Psychology, 34(5), 637–659.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger, J., & Mylopoulos, M. (2021). Default hypotheses in the study of perception: A reply to Phillips. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 28(3–4), 206–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birch, J. (2022). The search for invertebrate consciousness. Noûs, 56(1), 133–153.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Birch, J., Ginsburg, S., & Jablonka, E. (2020). Unlimited associative learning and the origins of consciousness: A primer and some predictions. Biology & Philosophy, 35, 56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2007). Consciousness, accessibility and the mesh between psychology and neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30(5), 481–548.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, R. (2012). The myth of phenomenological overflow. Consciousness and Cognition, 21(2), 599–604.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, R. (2015). The HOROR theory of consciousness. Philosophical Studies, 172(7), 1783–1794.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, R., LeDoux, J., & Rosenthal, D. (2021). The extra ingredient. Biology & Philosophy, 36(2), 1–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2008). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12(5), 187–192.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2000). Phenomenal consciousness: A naturalistic theory. Cambridge University Press.

  • Carruthers, P. (2019). Human and animal minds: The consciousness questions laid to Rest. Oxford University Press.

  • Carruthers, P., & Gennaro, R. (2020). Higher-order theories of consciousness. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall), E. N. Zalta (Ed.), URL=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/consciousness-higher/.

  • Clayton, N., & Dickinson, A. (1998). Episodic-like memory during cache recovery by scrub jays. Nature, 395, 272–274.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Cowey, A., & Stoerig, P. (1995). Blindsight in monkeys. Nature, 373(6511), 247–249.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia, D. (2019). Animal self-awareness: Types, distribution, and ethical significance. The Routledge Handbook of Animal Ethics. Routledge.

  • Dehaene, S. (2014). Consciousness and the brain: Deciphering how the Brain encodes our thoughts. Viking.

  • Descartes, R. (1988). In J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, & D. Murdoch (trans.) (Eds.), Descartes: Selected philosophical writings. Cambridge University Press.

  • Drayson, Z. (2012). The uses and abuses of the personal/subpersonal distinction. Philosophical Perspectives, 26(1), 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. MIT Press.

  • Gennaro, R. J. (2012). The consciousness Paradox: Consciousness, concepts, and higher-order thoughts. MIT Press.

  • Gennaro, R. J. (2018). Animal consciousness. Encyclopedia of animal cognition and behavior (pp. 1–14). Springer.

  • Halina, M., Harrison, D., & Klein, C. (2022). Evolutionary transition markers and the origins of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 29(3–4), 62–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, B., Call, J., Agnetta, B., & Tomasello, M. (2000). Chimpanzees know what conspecifics do and do not see. Animal Behaviour, 59(4), 771–785.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1987). (Non-solipsistic) conceptual role semantics. In E. Lepore (Ed.), New directions in semantics (pp. 55–81). Academic.

  • Jamieson, D. & Bekoff, M. (1992). Carruthers on non-conscious experience. Analysis, 52, 23–28.

  • Koch, C., Massimini, M., Boly, M., & Tononi, G. (2016). Neural correlates of consciousness: progress and problems. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 17, 307–321.

  • Kohda, M., Bshary, R., Kubo, N., Awata, S., Sowersby, W., Kawasaka, K., Kobayashi, T., & Sogawa, S. (2023). Cleaner fish recognize self in a mirror via self-face recognition like humans. Proceedings of the National Academic of Science, 120(7), e2208420120.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Krachun, C., Carpenter, M., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2009). A competitive nonverbal false belief task for children and apes. Developmental Science, 12(4), 521–535.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Lau, H. (2022). In consciousness we trust: The cognitive neuroscience of subjective experience. Oxford University Press.

  • Lau, H., & Rosenthal, D. M. (2011). Empirical support for higher-order theories of conscious awareness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(8), 365–373.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • LeDoux, J. (2019). The deep history of ourselves: The four-billion-Year Story of how we got conscious brains. Viking.

  • LeDoux, J., Birch, J., Andrews, K., Clayton, N. S., Daw, N. D., Frith, C., Lau, H., Peters, M. A. K., Schneider, S., Seth, A., Suddendorf, T., & Vandekerckhove, M. M. P. (2023). Consciousness beyond the human case. Current Biology, 33(16), R832–R840.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G. (1996). Consciousness and experience. MIT Press.

  • Margolis, E., & Laurence, S. (2015). The conceptual mind: New directions in the study of concepts. MIT Press.

  • McDowell, J. 1994. Mind and world. Harvard University Press.

  • Merker, B. H. (2007). Consciousness without a cerebral cortex: A challenge for neuroscience and medicine. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30, 63–81.

  • Michel, M., & Morales, J. (2019). Minority reports: Consciousness and the prefrontal cortex. Mind & Language, 35(4), 493–513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 83(4), 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (2006). Naturalistic theories of reference. In M. Devitt, & R. Hanley (Eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Language (pp. 374–391). Basil Blackwell.

  • Newen, A., & Bartels, A. (2007). Animal minds and the possession of concepts. Philosophical Psychology, 20(3), 283–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Passos-Ferreira, C. (2023). Are infants conscious? Philosophical Perspectives, 1–22.

  • Phillips, I. (2021). Scepticism about unconscious perception is the default hypothesis. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 28(3-4), 186–205.

  • Plotnik, J. M., Waal, F., & Reiss, D. (2006). Self-Recognition in an Asian Elephant. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 103, 17053–17057.

  • Quine, W. V. (1960). Word and object. MIT Press.

  • Rosenthal, D. M. (1991). The independence of consciousness and sensory quality. Philosophical Issues, 1, 15–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M. (2005). Consciousness and Mind. Clarendon.

  • Rosenthal, D. M. (2008). Consciousness and its function. Neuropsychologia, 46(3), 829–840.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sauret, W., & Lycan, W. G. (2014). Attention and internal monitoring: A Farewell to HOP. Analysis, 74(3), 363–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seth, A. K., & Bayne, T. (2022). Theories of consciousness. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 23(7), 439–452.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Shepherd, J., & Mylopoulos, M. (2021). Unconscious perception and central coordinating agency. Philosophical Studies, 178(12), 3869–3893.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tononi, G. (2012). Phi: A voyage from the brain to the soul. Pantheon.

  • Tononi, G., & Koch, C. (2015). Consciousness: here, there and everywhere? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 370, 20140167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2016). Tense bees and Shell-shocked crabs: Are animals conscious? Oxford University Press.

  • Weiskrantz, L. (1986). Blindsight: A case study and implications. Oxford University Press.

  • Whiten, A. (2013). Humans are not alone in computing how others see the world. Animal Behaviour, 86(2), 213–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wild, M. (2021). Conceptual thought without language? The case from animal cognition. In C. Demmerling, & D. Schröder (Eds.), Concepts in Thought, Action, and emotion: New essays (pp. 99–116). Routledge.

  • Yoshida, M., & Isa, T. (2015). Signal detection analysis of blindsight in monkeys. Scientific Reports, 5, 10755.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Young, B., Keller, A., & Rosenthal, D. M. (2014). Quality-space theory in olfaction. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 1–15.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements and funding information

We thank Richard Brown, Alex Kiefer, Rocco Gennaro, Joseph Gottlieb, Claudia Passos, David Pereplyotchik, Adriana Renero, David Rosenthal, Dan Shargel, and the audience at the 2023 Science of Consciousness Conference in Taormina, Sicily for their helpful discussions of or comments on this material. This work was supported by a Lycoming College Professional Development Grant.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jacob Berger.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors have no conflicts of interest to declare.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Berger, J., Mylopoulos, M. HOTT and heavy: higher-order thought theory and the theory-heavy approach to animal consciousness. Synthese 203, 98 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-024-04529-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-024-04529-8

Keywords

Navigation