Skip to main content
Log in

Emergent mental properties are not just double-preventers

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We examine Sophie Gibb’s emergent property-dualist theory of mental causation as double-prevention. Her account builds on a commitment to a version of causal realism based on a powers metaphysic. We consider three objections to her account. We show, by drawing out the implications of the ontological commitments of Gibb’s theory of mental causation, that the first two objections fail. But, we argue, owing to worries about cases where there is no double-preventive role to be played by mental properties, her account, which solely affords mental properties a double-preventive role, is incomplete and vulnerable to a causal exclusion objection. We propose a friendly modification to her theory of mental causation that is consistent with her theory’s ontological commitments. Specifically, we sketch an account on which mental properties have a more pronounced causal-structuring role that is not exhausted by the role Gibb assigns them as double-preventers. The result is a novel emergentist theory of mental causation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, especially, the work of E. J. Lowe (2006, 2008).

  2. While both of the authors of this article regard Gibb’s strategy and her general theory of mental causation as attractive, providing a promising framework for developing a solution to the causal exclusion problem for emergent property dualists, it is not the case that both authors accept dualism of any sort. One of the authors (Andrei Buckareff) favors a version of neutral monism that is best described as a version of panprotopsychism on which all properties are proto-phenomenal powers. That said, both authors regard the account sketched here to be the best way to fix Gibb’s account and think it is the best option for those who endorse theories that are committed to mental properties being strongly emergent.

  3. We specify some further ways a property can be causally relevant in Sect. 6, below.

  4. Specifically, Schneider (2012) has argued that property-dualism commits one to either Cartesian substance dualism or a dualism of physical and hybrid substances. The argument is based on the assumption that properties are ways that substances are. Thus, if a substance has both mental and physical properties, one of the ways it is is characterized by the mental properties. Hence, we have a hybrid substance that is not purely physical. Schneider suggests that the property dualist endorse the hybrid view. We expect that Gibb would be sympathetic to this claim given that she endorses the view that properties are borne by and are ways that substances are (see Gibb 2017).

  5. See Buckareff 2022a for a powers realist argument against identifying powers with dispositions and against taking ‘power’ and ‘disposition’ to be interchangeable (powers provide the truthmakers for disposition-ascriptions).

  6. See Taylor 2018 for an argument to the effect that there is no real difference between a pure powers view and at least certain accounts of powers as powerful qualities.

  7. Martin’s discussion, while quite rich, is very short (spanning pages 48–51 of his 2008).

  8. For more on the activation of causal powers in causal processes in the context of exercising intentional agency, see Buckareff (2018, 2022b) and Aguilar and Buckareff (2022).

  9. Gibb explicitly endorses a Kimean metaphysics of events. She takes both causes and effects to be Kimean events (Gibb, 2019, p. 119, n. 1).

  10. See Buckareff (2018) and Mumford and Anjum (2011) for more on how causal processes can have a zero-sum outcome.

  11. Incidentally, Gibb (2010) offers a critique of the role afforded conserved quantity views of causation in defenses of physicalism. Specifically, she argues that, while they may capture something that is correct about physical causation, the move to saying that a transference of a conserved physical quantity is characteristic of all causal relations is question-begging (see Ibid., pp. 376–377).

  12. A referee for this journal raised worries about whether the locality condition is a commitment of a powers-theory of causation. They offered the example of gravity, in particular where gravitational force is exerted across a vast distance (e.g., between the Sun and the Earth). The worry is that such a view requires that one take such objects to be connected by something such as interacting fields or spacetime regions. On such a view, for instance, the constitutive powers of the gravitational field of the Sun are manifested when partnered with the constitutive powers of the Earth’s gravitational field. The worry may be that this renders a metaphysical theory of causation hostage to the sciences. Suppose we learn tomorrow that putative cases of action at a distance do, in fact, violate the locality condition. In that case, then we may either need to abandon causal realism entirely or treat the locality condition as typically satisfied but as a non-essential feature of processes of causal production. The second option may lead one to endorse a version of causal pluralism (see, e.g., Cartwright, 2007) on which the locality condition is satisfied with certain processes and not with others. In any case, for our purposes here, the sorts of causal processes we are interested in are ones that would satisfy the locality condition (see Gibb, 2013, p. 200). Such causal processes involve the polygenic production of an outcome by a constellation of powers whose manifestations depend upon their interacting in a way that would satisfy the locality condition (even if it is best to endorse a capacious notion of “local,” see Williams, 2019, pp. 144–146).

  13. For one, we do not accept the distinction between the agent/person and their body that Lowe endorses. Rather, as noted, we assume that an agent is a functionally integrated hybrid system composed of simple objects and their properties, including emergent psychological properties.

  14. Alexander Carruth and Sophie Gibb argue that Lowe’s “distinction between fact and event causation is difficult to maintain within most common ontological systems” (2018, p. 150).

  15. None of this is meant to imply that these three philosophers endorse the same metaphysics of mind. They are quite different. Lowe defended a non-Cartesian substance dualism. Dretske endorsed physicalism. Finally, Jaworski endorses a stronger version of hylomorphism than we are presenting here on which psychpowers exert downward causal influence. Limitations of space do not allow us to examine any differences and similarities between what we are proposing and the various proposals offered by Dretske, Jaworski, and Lowe.

  16. A referee for this journal suggested that there are similarities between our account and the program explanation account of Jackson and Pettit.

  17. See Prior et al. (1982) for more details about the view of dispositional properties that is assumed by Jackson and Pettit. For a critique, see Heil (2003, pp. 87–89).

  18. See Aristotle, Physics 194b23-35 (1996). We are not suggesting that the way of carving up the four causes we present actually tracks how Aristotle treated his four causes.

  19. Note that we assume that bodily activity is not limited to overt actions. Mental actions involve bodily activity in the form of neurophysiological activity.

  20. The authors wish to thank two anonymous referees for this journal for their very helpful feedback on an earlier version of this article. Some of Andrei Buckareff’s work on this article was generously supported by a grant from the John Templeton Foundation (Grant #62683, “Panpsychism and Pan(en)theism: Philosophy of Mind Meets Philosophy of Religion). None of the views presented in this article necessarily represent those of the John Templeton Foundation.

References

  • Aguilar, J., & Buckareff, A. (2022). Agency and causation. In L. Ferrero (Ed.), Routledge handbook of philosophy of agency (pp. 27–36). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1996). Physics. In R. Waterfield (Ed.), Oxford World’s classics: Aristotle: Physics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckareff, A. (2018). I’m just sitting around doing nothing: On exercising intentional agency in omitting to act. Synthese, 195, 4617–4635.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckareff, A. (2022a). Disentangling dispositions from powers. Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review, 61, 107–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckareff, A. (2022b). Two-way powers as derivative powers. In M. Brent & L. Titus (Eds.), Mental action and the conscious mind (pp. 228–254). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Carruth, A., & Gibb, S. (2018). The ontology of E. J. Lowe’s substance dualism. In A. Carruth, S. Gibb, & J. Heil (Eds.), Ontology, modality, and mind: Themes from the metaphysics of E. J. Lowe. Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (2007). Hunting causes and using them: Approaches in philosophy and economics. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, K. (2016). Powers, double prevention, and mental causation. Metaphysica, 17, 37–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1997). Naturalizing the mind. The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gibb, S. (2010). Closure principles and the laws of conservation of energy and momentum. Dialectica, 64, 363–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibb, S. (2013). Mental causation and double prevention. In S. Gibb, E. J. Lowe, & R. Ingthorsson (Eds.), Mental causation and ontology (pp. 193–214). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gibb, S. (2015a). Defending dualism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 115, 131–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibb, S. (2015b). The causal closure principle. Philosophical Quarterly, 65, 626–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibb, S. (2015c). Physical determinability. Humana Mente: Journal of Philosophical Studies, 29, 69–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibb, S. (2017). The mental causation debate and qua problems. In M. P. Paoletti & F. Orilia (Eds.), Philosophical and scientific perspectives on downward causation. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibb, S. (2019). Causal closure. In S. Gibb, R. Hendry, & T. Lancaster (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of emergence (pp. 111–120). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. (2004). Two concepts of causation. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 225–276). The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. (2003). From an ontological point of view. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F., & Pettit, P. (1988). Functionalism and broad content. Mind, 97, 381–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F., & Pettit, P. (1990a). Causation in the philosophy of mind. Philosophy and Phenoenological Research, 50, 195–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F., & Pettit, P. (1990b). Program explanation: A general perspective. Analysis, 50, 107–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaworski, W. (2016). Structure and the metaphysics of mind: How hylomorphism solves the mind-body problem. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1976). Events as property exemplifications. In M. Brand & D. Walton (Eds.), Action theory (pp. 159–177). D. Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1989). Mechanism, purpose and explanatory exclusion. Philosophical Perspectives, 3, 77–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2005). Physicalism, or something near enough. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2010). Causation and mental causation. In J. Kim (Ed.), Essays in metaphysics of mind (pp. 243–262). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lombard, L. (1979). Events. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 9, 425–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lombard, L. (1998). Ontologies of events. In S. Laurence & C. Macdonald (Eds.), Contemporary readings in the foundations of metaphysics (pp. 277–294). Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2000). Causal closure principles and emergentism. Philosophy, 75, 571–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2006). Non-Cartesian substance dualism and the problem of mental causation. Erkenntnis, 65, 5–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2008). Personal agency: The metaphysics of mind and action. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Malcolm, N. (1968). Conceivability and mechanism. The Philosophical Review, 77, 45–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. B. (2008). The mind in nature. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molnar, G. (2003). Powers: a study in metaphysics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (2009). Passing powers around. The Monist, 92, 94–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S., & Anjum, R. (2009). Double prevention and powers. Journal of Critical Realism, 8, 277–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S., & Anjum, R. (2011). Getting causes from powers. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Prior, E., Pargetter, R., & Jackson, F. (1982). Three theses about dispositions. American Philosophical Quarterly, 19, 251–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, S. (2012). Why property dualists must reject substance physicalism. Philosophical Studies, 157, 61–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, H. (2018). Powerful qualities and pure powers. Philosophical Studies, 175, 1423–1440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, N. (2019). The powers metaphysic. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrei A. Buckareff.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors have no known conflicts of interest in submitting this article for review.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Buckareff, A.A., Hawkins, J. Emergent mental properties are not just double-preventers. Synthese 202, 53 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04282-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04282-4

Keywords

Navigation