Skip to main content
Log in

Influence theory

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Influence theory is a systematic study of formal models of the communicative influence of one person or group of people on another person or group. In that sense influence theory is an overarching philosophical discipline that includes aspects of decision theory and game theory as sub-disciplines as well as established models of de facto segregation, cultural change, opinion polarization, and epistemic networks. What we offer here is a structured outline of formal results that have been scattered across a range of disciplinary contexts from mathematics, physics and computer science to economics and political science, supplemented with a number of new models, emphasizing their place within the philosophical framework of a general theory of influence. What such an outline offers, we propose, is the prospect of new and important cross-fertilizations and expansions in formal attempts to model the diverse patterns of communicative influence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8
Fig. 9
Fig. 10
Fig. 11

Adapted from Zollman (2010a)

Fig. 12
Fig. 13
Fig. 14
Fig. 15
Fig. 16

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Varieties of these different mechanisms within a model for which network, timing, agents and traits are otherwise held constant are explored for example in Grim, Kokalis, Alai-Tafti, Kilb and St. Denis 2004.

References

  • Anderson, L., & Holt, C. (1997). Information Cascades in the Laboratory. American Economic Review, 87, 847–862.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin-Smith, D., & Feddersen, T. J. (2005). Deliberation and voting rules. In D. Austin-Smith & J. Duggan (Eds.), Social choice and strategic decisions: Essays in Honor of Jeffrey S. Banks. Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Austin-Smith, D., & Feddersen, T. J. (2006). Deliberation, preference uncertainty, and voting rules. American Political Science Review, 100(2), 209–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod, R. (1997). The dissemination of culture: A model with local convergence and global polarization. Journal of Conflict Resolution, 41, 203–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bala, V., & Goyal, S. (1998). Learning from neighbours. Review of Economic Studies, 65(3), 595–621. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-937X.00059

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barabási, A.-L., & Albert, R. (1999). Emergence of scaling in random networks. Science, 286(5), 09–312.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlekamp, E., Conway, J. H., & Guy, R. K. (2001). Winning ways for your mathematical plays (2nd ed., Vol. 1). A K Peters/CRC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhattacharya, A. (2021). The man from the future: The visionary life of John von Neumann. W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bikhchandani, S., Hershleifer, D., & Welch, I. (1998). Learning from the behavior of others: Conformity, fads, and informational cascades. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 12(3), 151–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burks, A. (1966). Theory of self-reproducing automata. University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castllano, C., Fortunato, S., & Loreto, V. (2009). Statistical physics of social phenomena. Review of Modern Physics, 81, 591–646.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cialdini, R. B. (2009). Influence: Science and practice (5th ed.). Pearson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook, M. (2004). Universality in elementary cellular automata. Complex Systems, 15, 1–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coughlan, P. J. (2000). In defense of unanimous Jury verdicts: Mistrials, communication and strategic voting. American Political Science Review, 94, 375–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deffuant, G., Amblard, F., Weisbuch, G., & Faure, T. (2002). How can extremism prevail? A study based on the relative agreement interaction model. Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation, 5(4).

  • DeGroot, M. H. (1974). Reaching a consensus. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 69(345), 118–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Easley, D., & Kleinberg, J. (2010). Networks, crowds, and markets: Reasoning about a highly connected world. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fedderson, T., & Pesendorfer, W. (1998). Convicting the Innocent: The Inferioriutyof Unanimous Jury Verdicts under Strategic Voting. American Political Science Review, 92(1), 23–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, J. R. P. (1956). A Formal Theory of Social Power. Psychological Review, 63(3), 181–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galam, S., Gefen, Y., & Shapir, Y. (1982). Sociophysics: A new approach of sociological collective behavior. I. Mean-behavior description of a strike. Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 9, 1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galam, S., & Moscovici, S. (1991). Towards a theory of collective phenomena: Consensus and attitude changes in groups. European Journal of Social Psychology, 21, 49–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galam, S. (1997). Rational group decision making: A random field Ising model at T=0. Physica a: Statistical Mechanics and Its Applications, 238, 66–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galam, S. (2002). Minority opinion spreading in random geometry. European. Physical Journal B, 25, 403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galam, S. (2012). Sociophysics: A physicist’s model of psycho-political phenomena. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, C., & Cooper, G. F. (1999). Computation, causation and discovery. AAAI Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Granovetter, M. (1973). The strength of weak ties. American Journal of Sociology, 78(6), 1360–1380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Granovetter, M. (1978). Threshold models of collective behavior. American Journal of Sociology, 83(6), 1360–1380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grim, P. (1995). The greater generosity of the spatialized prisoner’s Dilemma. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 173, 353–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grim, P. (1997). The Undecidability of the spatialized prisoner’s Dilemma. Theory and Decision, 42, 53–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grim, P. (2009). “Threshold Phenomena in Epistemic Networks.” Proceedings, AAAI Fall Symposium on Complex Adaptive Systems and the Threshold Effect, AAAI Press.

  • Grim, P., Mar, G., & St. Denis, P. (1998). The philosophical computer. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grim, P., Kokalis, T., Alai-Tafti, A., Kilb, N., & St. Denis, P. (2004). Making meaning happen. Journal for Theoretical and Artificial Intelligence, 16, 209–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grim, P., Singer, D. J., Fisher, S., Bramson, A., Berger, W. J., Reade, C., & Sales, A. (2013). Scientific networks on data landscapes. Episteme, 10(4), 441–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grim, P., Singer, D. J., Reade, C., & Fisher, S. (2015). Germs, Genes, and memes: Function and fitness dynamics on epistemic networks. Philosophy of Science, 82(2), 219–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hararay, F. (1959). A criterion for unanimity in French’s theory of social power. In D. Cartwright (Ed.), Studies in Social Power (pp. 168–182). Institute for Social Research.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haykin, S. (1994). Neural networks: A comprehensive foundation. Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegselmann, R., & Krause, U. (2002). Opinion Dynamics and Bounded Confirdence Models, Analysis and Simulation, Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation, 5(3).

  • Hegselmann, R., & Krause, U. (2005). Opinion dynamics driven by various ways of averaging. Computational Economics, 25(4), 381–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hegselmann, R., & Krause, U. (2006). Truth and cognitive division of labour: First steps towards a computer aided social epistemology. Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation, 9(3).

  • Helbing, D. (1991). A mathematical model for the behavior of pedestrians. Behavioral Science, 36, 298–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hong, Lu., & Page, S. E. (2004). Groups of diverse problem solvers can outperform groups of high-ability problem solvers. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 101(46), 16385–16389. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0403723101

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huberman, B. A., & Glance, N. S. (1993). Evolutionary games and computer simulations. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science USA, 90, 7716–7718.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahan, M. (1997). Social influence, social meaning, and deterrence. Virginia Law Review, 83, 276–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kermack, W. O., & McKendrick, A. G. (1927). A contribution to the mathematical theory of epidemics. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London Series A, 115(772), 700–721.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kermack, W. O., & McKendrick, A. G. (1932). Contributions to the mathematical theory of epidemics-II. The problem of endemicity. Bulletin of Mathematical Biology 1991; 53(1–2): 57–87. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02464424

  • Korb, K. B., & Nicholson, A. E. (2004). Bayesian artificial intelligence. Chapman and Hall/CRC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K., & Wagner, C. (1981). Rational consensus in science and society. D. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1843). A system of logic, ratiocinative and inductive. 8th revised edition. Harper and Brothers, 1881.

  • Nowak, M., & May, R. (1992). Evolutionary games and spatial chaos. Nature, 359, 826–829.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nowak, M., & May, R. (1993). The spatial dimensions of evolution. International Journal of Bifurcation and Chaos, 3, 35–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nowak, M., & Sigmund, K. (1992). Tit for tat in heterogeneous populations. Nature, 355, 250–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nguyen, C. T. (2020). Echo chambers and epistemic bubbles. Episteme, 17(2), 141–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, C., & Weatherall, J. (2018). Scientific polarization. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 8(3), 855–875.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, C., & Weatherall, J. (2019). The misinformation age. Yale University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Page, S. (2018). The model thinker. Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning, and inference. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J., Glymour, M., & Jewell, N. P. (2016). Causal inference in statistics: A primer. Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1998). Predicting the future: An introduction to the theory of forecasting. State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. C. (1969). Models of segregation. American Economic Review, 59(2), 488–493.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. C. (1971). Dynamic models of segregation. Journal of Mathematical Sociology, 1(2), 143–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. C. (1978). Micromotives and macrobehavior. W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. (2001). Republic.com. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. (2007). Republic.com 2.0. Princeton Universiy Press.

  • Turing, A. M. (1937). On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, Series, 2(42), 230–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walden, E., & Browne, G. (2002). Information cascades in the adoption of new technology. In International Conference on Information Systems 2002 Proceedings (Vol. 40).

  • Watts, D., & Strogatz, S. (1998). Collective dynamics of ‘small-world’ networks. Nature, 393, 440–442. https://doi.org/10.1038/30918

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M., & Muldoon, R. (2009). Epistemic landscapes and the division of cognitive labor. Philosophy of Science, 76(2), 225–252. https://doi.org/10.1086/644786

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiedlich, W. (1971). The statistical description of polarization phenomena in society. British Journal of Mathematical and Statistical Psychology, 24, 251–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiedlich, W. (1991). Physics and social science—The approach of synergetics. Physics Reports, 204, 1–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiedlich, W. (2002). Sociodynamics—A systematic approach to mathematical modeling in the social sciences. Taylor & Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfram, S. (2002). A new kind of science. Wolfram Media.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, D. (1987). Theory of computation. Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zollman, K. (2007). The communication structure of epistemic communities. Philosophy of Science, 74(5), 574–587. https://doi.org/10.1086/525605

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zollman, K. (2010a). The epistemic benefit of transient diversity. Erkenntnis, 72(1), 17–35. https://doi.org/10.1086/525605

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zollman, K. (2010b). Social structure and the effects of conformity. Synthese, 172(3), 317–340. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-008-9393-8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zollman, K. (forthcoming). Network epistemology: how our social connections shape knowledge. Oxford University Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Patrick Grim.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare there are no competing interests or relevant funding sources.

Ethical approval

No ethics approval or informed consent was required.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

A compendium of examples above in terms of parameters outlined in Sect. 2:

Model

Agents

Traits

Network

Timing

Mechanism

Purpose

Dynamics

4.1

 

2 binary X,Y

1-Way influence

N/A

Influence on neighbor

formal

Immediate unanimity

4.2

 

2 binary X,Y

Mutual influence

Simultaneous

Influence on neighbor

formal

Oscillation from XY, YX

4.3

 

2 binary X,Y

Mutual influence

Sequential

Influence on neighbor

formal

First actor determines unanimity

4.4

 

2 binary X,Y

Mutual influence,

Proba-bilistic

Simultaneous

Probability p of influence on

neighbor

formal

Asymptotic approach to equilibrium

4.5

 

2 binary X,Y

Mutual influence,

proba-bilistic

Sequential

Probability p of influence on

neighbor

formal

Asymptotic approach to equilibrium,

faster convergence than simultaneous

4.6

 

2 traits,

adaptable to multiple

Mutual influence

Simultaneous & sequential

variations

Influence on neighbor at

particular trait, deterministic

or probabilistic

formal

Allows a measure of degree of

influence in terms of number of trait

changes

4.7

 

Continuous

scale on single trait

Mutual influence

Simultaneous & sequential

variations

Each agent influences the other to move halfway to its position, or recalcitrant agents

formal

Various equilibria given differences in timing, rule and agent recalcitrance

4.8

 

2 binary, continuous, multiple

Mutual influence

Strategically handled influence

Probabilistic influence

formal

Altered probabilities with unbalanced influence events

5.1 Population model

Multiple,

proportions of population

2 binary X,Y

Fully connected or random mixing

Simultaneous all with all

Probability of conversion of neighbor

formal

Markov model, unique equilibrium regardless of initial proportions, by Perron-Frobenius theorem

5.2 SIR, SIRS infection models

Multiple,

proportions of population

Susceptible infected recovered

Random mixing

Simultaneous all with all

Infection of neighbor with R0 of pathogen, recovered immunity (SIR) or possible reinfection (SIRS)

explanatory predictive

Classical S-curve of infection for SIR model, endemic equilibrium possible in SIRS model

5.3 Deterministic cycle through states

Multiple,

proportions of population

2 binary X,Y

Fully connected

Simultaneous all with all

100% probability of conversion of neighbor

formal

Violates conditionsof Markov model: oscillation

5.4 Variable transition probabilities, Grim Mar St. Denis (1998)

Multiple,

proportions of population

2 binary X, Y and various

Fully connected

Simultaneous or sequential

Probabilistic conversion

formal

Equilibrium, oscillatory, periodic, and chaotic all possible dyanmics

5.5 Granovetter (1978)

Multiple, with hetero-geneous thresholds

2 binary: riot, not

Fully connected

Simultaneous

Agents with heterogeneous thresholds convert to ‘riot’ given specific proportions of the population rioting

explanatory

Rioting population depends not merely on average thresholds to riot but on distribution of thresholds

5.6

Lehrer and Wagner (1981)

Multiple

Multiple agents have opinion probability and reliability weights for other agents

Fully connected

Iterated

simultaneous

Agents change opinion probabilities to weighted average of population

Formal, normative

Consensus in

which all agents share same opinion probabilities develops as Markov process

6.1

Multiple

2 binary X, Y

Linear, 1-dimensional

Simultaneous

X changes to Y given a Y neighbor, or does so with probability p

formal

Total conversion to Y given any Y, speed dependent on probability

6.2

Multiple

2 binary X, Y

Linear, 1-dimensional

Simultaneous

Y changes to X if surrounded by X on both sides

formal

Results dependent on initial configuration

6.3

Multiple

2 binary X, Y

Linear, 1-dimensional

Simultaneous

Non-symmetrical: Y preceded by 2 X’s will convert to X

formal

Results dependent on initial configuration

6.4

Multiple

2 binary X, Y

Linear, 2-dimensional, finite alternation of X and Y

Simultaneous

Conversion to other view when surrounded on each side

formal

Results dependent on initial configuration

6.5

Multiple

2 binary X, Y

Linear loop

Simultaneous

Conversion to other view when surrounded on each side

formal

Oscillation with loop at one point; unanimity with loop at another

7.1 shared information

Multiple, with individual evidence as well as cumulative

Binary

Linear, 1-dimensional

Sequential along line

Agents share decisions and evidence down the line

formal

Given a small probability of correctness, individuals down the line will accumulate evidence toward the correct decision with probability 1

7.2 Information cascades Bikhchandani et al. (1998)

Multiple, with individual evidence as well as cumulative

Binary

Linear, 1-dimensional

Sequential along line

Agents share decisions but not individual evidence, make decisions on cumulative data

formal, explanatory

Cascades of decision, with calculable probabilities of misinformation

7.3 Information cascades in enclaves

Multiple in isolated enclaves, individual and cumulative evidence

Binary

Linear, 1-dimensional

Sequential along lines of each enclave

Agents share decisions but not individual evidence, make decisions on cumulative data

formal, explanatory

Increased probability of polarization, increased probability of misinformation in at least one enclave

7.4 Information cascades on trees

Multiple in isolated enclaves, individual and cumulative evidence

Binary

Tree network

Sequential from earlier on tree

Agents share decisions but not individual evidence, make decisions on cumulative data

formal, explanatory

Similar cascade phenomena

7.5

Fedderson Pesendorfer 1998; Austin-Smith Feddersen (2005, 2006)

Multiple

agents

Private signals with ‘bias’ or standard of reasonable doubt

Fully connected

Simultaneous

voting, or voting after straw poll, with either unanimous or majority decision rule

Agents may vote or share information on private signals strategically

Formal, explanatory

normative

Incentives for strategic voting are different under unanimity and majority rule; error rates are higher under unanimity

7.6 Hegselmann Krause (2002, 2005, 2006)

Multiple agents

Continuous scale of opinion

Association network with similarity threshold on trait

Simultaneous

Agents’ opinions move toward average of those in their threshold range

formal, explanatory

With high threshold, convergence on opinion. With low threshold, polarization of opinion in population

8.1 Schelling, (1969, 1971, 1978)

Multiple agents

2 unchanging traits or colors X,Y

2-dimensional lattice with low density (empty cells)

Random

Agents do not change traits, but move on array when number of ‘like’ neighbors is below threshold t

formal, explanatory

With relatively low threshold (30%), clear clustered areas of residential segregation appear

8.2 Schelling with high, low density and heterogeneous thresholds

Multiple agents

2 unchanging traits or colors X,Y

2-dimensional lattice with low or high density

Random

Agents move when number of like neighbors is below threshold t, but one set of agents have a ‘don’t care’ low threshold

formal, explanatory

At low density, agents do not cluster. At high density, they are forced to

8.3 Cultural divfusion Axelrod (1997)

Multiple agents

5 traits, each with 1 of 10 values

Agents fixed in a 2-dimensional lattice

Neighbor pairs chosen at random, interact with a probability correlate to number of traits in common

Given interaction, the ‘active’ agent changes one of its non-matching traits to that of the other agent

formal, explanatory

Wide areas of convergence a rossall traits with islands of isolated ‘cultures’

8.4 Imitative game theory Nowak & May (1992, 1993)

Multiple agents

2 strategies: Cooperate, Defect

2-dimensional lattice

Simultaneous

Play rounds of Prisoner’s Dilemma, then imitate most successful neighbor

formal

Maintained proportion of cooperative strategies; symmetrical patterns

8.5 Imitative game theory Huberman & Glance (1993)

Multiple agents

2 strategies: Cooperate, Defect

2-dimensional lattice

Random

Play rounds of Prisoner’s Dilemma, then imitate most successful neighbor

formal

Symmetrical patterns destroyed; results for cooperation altered from simultaneous case

8.6 Game of Go

Multiple agents

2 traits, black or white

2-dimensional lattice

Sequential

Strategic moves attempting to occupy points or surround opponent

formal

Strategically complex

9.1 Small worlds Watts & Strogatz (1998)

Multiple agents

Various

Range of networks from ring with probability of ring rewiring to random

Simultaneous

Influence between nodes on links

formal, explanatory

With ring networks, clustering coefficient high and characteristic path length long. At random, path length short but clustering coefficient low. In ‘small worlds,’ high clustering with short path lengths

9.2 Preferential attachment networks

Barabási & Albert (1999)

Multiple agents

Various

Networks formed with new nodes attaching with higher probability to nodes with many links

Sequential addition

Influence between nodes on links

formal, explanatory

Scale free networks form

9.3 Epistemic networks Zollman (2007, 2010a, 2010b)

multiple

Choice of theories as to the higher-paying of 2 ‘bandits’

Sample networks: ring, wheel, and complete

Simultaneous

Update chosen theory on the basis of individual testing of a chosen bandit and input from linked nodes

formal, normative

Ring formations resuilt in slower community convergence with higher group accuracy probability

9.4 Bayesian networks

multiple

Various

Directed acyclic graphs

Sequential

Bayesian updating of nodes from current links and previous values

formal

Various dynamics given differences in timing, rule, and agent recalcitrance

10.1 Wolfram rule 126

multiple

Black or white

Linear, 1-dimensional

Simultaneous

Cell is black just in case self and two neighbors not all blck or all white on previous generation

formal

Forms Sierpinski triangle

10.2 Wolfram rule 110

multiple

Black or white

Linear, 1-dimensional

Simultaneous

‘right-handed’: like 126 except a single black to the left is insufficient to make a cell black on the next generation

formal

Computationally universal, formally undecidasble (Cook, 2004)

11.1 Game of Life

multiple

Alive or dead

2-dimensional lattice

Simultaneous

If alive, stays alive on next iteration iff 2 or 3 neighbors are currently alive. If dead, stays dead unless 3 neighbors are currently alive

formal

Computationally universal, formally undecidasble (Berlekamp, Conway & Guy 1982)

11.2 Spatialized Prisoner’s Dilemma

Multiple

Many states to form electrons on wires, logic gates, memory units

2-dimensional lattice

Simultaneous

Cells play Prisoner’s Dilemma with neighbors, convert to most successful local strategy

formal

Computationally universal, formally undecidasble (Grim, Mar & St. Denis 1998)

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Grim, P., Rescher, N. Influence theory. Synthese 201, 211 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04163-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04163-w

Keywords

Navigation