Skip to main content
Log in

Inductive neutrality and scientific representation

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Prima facie, accounts of scientific representation should illuminate how models support justified surrogative reasoning while remaining neutral on the nature of inductive inference. We argue that doing both at once is harder than it first appears. Accounts like “DEKI,” which distinguish justified and unjustified surrogative inferences by appealing to a distinction between derivational and factual correctness, cannot accommodate non-formal, non-rule-based accounts of inference such as John Norton’s material theory of induction. In contrast, a recent expressivist-inferentialist account appears compatible with material inference, but at the cost of abandoning inductive neutrality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Namely, Frigg and Nguyen (2023) and Millson and Risjord (2023a; 2023b) in Lawler et al. (2023).

  2. We could add a third type, Model-Entry Transitions, that concern inferences that go into the production of the model/map, but such inferences are external to surrogative reasoning proper, so we set them aside.

  3. See Shech (2015) on scientific misrepresentation, and see Shech (2018) and (2023) for more on idealizations in science.

  4. Even if he himself focuses on inferences he takes to be “deductively valid” (Swoyer 1991, p. 500 n4).

  5. It is beyond the scope of this paper to defend the MTI and rehearse such details which can be found, e.g., in Norton (2003, 2021).

  6. Millson and Risjord (2023b) insist that, even with the derivational-factual correctness distinction, DEKI is unable to distinguish justified from unjustified inferences. For our purposes, we refrain from taking a position on this issue.

  7. For an incompressible fluid the Navier-Stokes equations read as:

    $$-\nabla p+\eta {\nabla }^{2}{\textbf{v}}=\rho \frac{\partial {\textbf{v}}}{\partial t}+({\textbf{v}}\cdot \nabla )\rho {\textbf{v}},$$

    where \(\rho\) is the density, \(\eta\) the viscosity coefficient, and \({\textbf{v}}\) is the velocity of the fluid.

  8. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for highlighting this point.

  9. We thank an anonymous reviewer for pushing us to make this point clearer and for the example of a Bayesian version of KMR.

  10. A way to create the required space is by appealing to a teleological function. Springle’s (2021) analysis of representation may be especially promising, as this analysis suggests that epistemic representations function to enable non-accidentally successful surrogative inferences about a target system.

  11. We thank an anonymous reviewer for encouraging us to make this point explicit.

  12. See Shech (2015) and Shech (2016) for outlines of a content-based account of representation that ostensibly satisfies Inductive Neutrality, and also see Springle (2021).

References

  • Cheng, T.-P. (2013). Einstein’s physics: Atoms, quanta, and relativity derived, explained, and appraised. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1926/1956). Investigations on the theory of Brownian movement. In R. Fürth, & A. D. Cowper (Eds.), Dover Publications.

  • Frigg, R., & Nguyen, J. (2020). Modeling nature: An opinionated introduction to scientific representation. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., & J. Nguyen. (2023). DEKI and the mislocation of justification: A response to Millson and Risjord. In Lawler et al. (2023) (pp. 296–301).

  • Khalifa, K., Millson, J., & Risjord, M. (2022). Scientific representation: An inferentialist-expressivist manifesto. Philosophical Topics, 50, 263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawler, I., Khalifa, K., & Shech, E. (Eds.). (2023). Scientific understanding and representation. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millson, J., & M. Risjord. (2023b). DEKI and the justification of surrogative inference: A response. In Lawler et al. (2023b), (pp. 301–306).

  • Millson, J., & M. Risjord. (2023a). DEKI, denotation, and the fortuitous misuse of maps. In Lawler et al. (2023a), (pp. 280–296).

  • Norton, J. D. (2003). A material theory of induction. Philosophy of Science, 70, 647–670.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. D. (2021). The material theory of induction. University of Calgary Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shech, E. (2015). Scientific misrepresentation and guides to ontology: The need for representational code and contents. Synthese, 192(11), 3463–3485.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shech, E. (2016). Fiction, depiction, and the complementarity thesis in art and science. The Monist, 99(3), 311–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shech, E. (2018). Infinite idealizations in physics. Philosophy Compass. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12514

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shech, E. (2023). Idealization in physics. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Springle, A. (2021). Intentionality: A problem-solving approach. Doctoral Dissertation, University of Pittsburgh.

  • Swoyer, C. (1991). Structural representation and surrogative reasoning. Synthese, 87, 449–508.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elay Shech.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors have no conflicts of interest to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Shech, E., Springle, A.A. Inductive neutrality and scientific representation. Synthese 201, 181 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04161-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04161-y

Keywords

Navigation