Skip to main content
Log in

Reasoning in attitudes

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

People reason not only in beliefs, but also in intentions, preferences, and other attitudes. They form preferences from existing preferences, or intentions from existing beliefs and intentions, and so on. This often involves choosing between rival conclusions. Building on Broome (Rationality through reasoning, Hoboken, Wiley. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118609088, 2013) and Dietrich et al. (J Philos 116:585–614. https://doi.org/10.5840/jphil20191161138, 2019), we present a philosophical and formal analysis of reasoning in attitudes, with or without facing choices in reasoning. We give different accounts of choosing, in terms of a conscious activity or a partly subconscious process. Reasoning in attitudes differs fundamentally from reasoning about attitudes, a form of theoretical reasoning in which one discovers rather than forms attitudes. We show that reasoning in attitudes has standard formal properties (such as monotonicity), but is indeterministic, reflecting choice in reasoning. Like theoretical reasoning, it need not follow logical entailment, but for a more radical reason, namely indeterminism. This makes reasoning in attitudes harder to model logically than theoretical reasoning. But it can be studied abstractly, using indeterministic consequence operators.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Our terminology aims to prevent any confusion with ‘reasoning about attitudes’.

  2. Sophisticated intelligent systems use (artificial) reasoning to form (artificial) attitudes, including intentions that cause actions.

  3. An example is Drucker’s (2021) broader account of reasoning, which he calls ‘generalism’.

  4. Non-deductive reasoning can behave very differently, for instance non-monotonically. See Harman’s (1984) seminal distinction between reasoning (inference) and entailment (implication).

  5. Examples of logics with attitude operators are logics of preferences (e.g., Liu, 2011), of beliefs (e.g., Halpern, 2017), or of beliefs, desires and intentions (‘BDI logics’).

  6. On ‘propositionalism’, see Felappi (forth.). For a critical take, see (Montague, 2007).

  7. Let L be a set of propositions, and A a set of attitude-types, each carrying an arity \(n\in \{1,2,...\}\), usually 1 (monadic attitudes) or 2 (dyadic attitudes). Plausibly, A contains at least belief bel (monadic), desire des (monadic), intention int (monadic), preference \(\succ \) (dyadic), and indifference \(\sim \) (dyadic). Finally, define attitudes in M as tuples \(m=(p_{1},...,p_{n},a)\) where a is an attitude type in A, n is its arity, and \(p_{1},...,p_{n}\) are propositions in L. So, (pbel) is believing p, (pint) is intending p, \((p,q,\succ )\) is preferring p to q, etc.

  8. Using ‘shall’ to mark intention is little common in everyday English, although some American philosophers have appropriated ‘shall’ as a marker for intention, as a referee pointed out to us. In original English, almost the opposite used to hold: ‘shall’ was the correct auxiliary of the future tense after ‘I’ or ‘we’, and saying ‘will’ instead of ‘shall’ counted as a departure that adds extra colour and might mark an intention. In modern English, ‘will’ has mostly taken the role of ‘shall’.

  9. For instance, assume you have just one rule: the broad rule that takes you from believing that the weather is X to intending to take a walk, where X is ‘dry’ or ‘windy’. Having this rule is effectively equivalent to having two specific rules: the rule taking you from the dry-weather belief to the intention and the rule taking you from the windy-weather belief to the intention. Indeed, whether you have the broad rule or the two specific rules, you can derive the intention if and only if you initially have one of the two beliefs.

  10. Using the formalism in footnote 7, write \((P,k)=(\{( p,bel),(if\) p then \(q,bel)\},(q,bel))\) (\(p,q\in L\)) for (a); write \((P,k)=(\{(obligatorily\) \(p,bel)\},(p,int))\) (\(p\in L\)) for (b); etc. This involves composite propositions. To give them formal meaning, assume that to any propositions \(p,q\in L\) is assigned a proposition if p then q in L; that to any proposition \(p\in L\) is assigned a proposition obligatorily p in L; etc. Technically, this defines a binary operator \(L\times L\rightarrow L\); a unary operator \(L\rightarrow L\); etc. The rules (a)–(d) are now formally specified. One could go further and model propositions in L syntactically (intensionally) as sentences in a formal language, or semantically (extensionally) as subsets of some set of possible worlds. This turns operators into syntactic or semantic operators, respectively (cf. Dietrich et al. forth.).

  11. In the Venice example we could have replaced your equal-goodness belief (the third premise-attitude) by another tie-creating attitude, e.g., a preferential indifference between the means, or a belief of being unable to compare the means in terms of betterness or equal goodness.

  12. You presumably do not repeat the premises of your second reasoning because you have just said them during your first reasoning.

  13. If reasoning from absences is not explicit, and only explicit reasoning can be active (as suggested but not assumed by Broome (2013, p. 224), then reasoning in absences is not active.

  14. More precisely, Broome regards such reasoning as correct provided one adds a fourth premise-attitude, namely the belief that both means are up to you. If the means are not up to you, say because you have delegated your travel planning to a travel agent, then your intention is unnecessary. Broome may be right that correctness requires his fourth premise. We ignore this premise for expositional simplicity.

  15. While you can derive the ‘train’ intention from the four premise-attitudes (including the introspective belief) you cannot derive it after adding the ‘boat’ intention as a fifth premise-attitude. Such reasoning would rest on a strange combination of premise-attitudes, as the ‘boat’ intention (the fifth premise-attitude) clashes with the belief of not intending either means (fourth premise-attitude). Like under (i)–(ii) in the third account, you either do not even start reasoning to the ‘train’ intention, because your ‘boat’ intention is conscious. Or you start reasoning, but then, after bringing to mind some or all of the premise-attitudes, your remember your ‘boat’ intention, which lets you stop reasoning as you cannot derive the ‘train’ intention with your ‘boat’ intention as an additional premise-attitude.

  16. On the first and third account the premise-attitudes are the attitudes in P; on the second account they are the attitudes in P plus the absences of the attitudes in K; on the fourth account they are the attitudes in P plus the belief of not yet possessing attitudes in K.

  17. Some logicians study multi-conclusion inference (e.g., Restall, 2005; Beall, 2011). Multi-conclusion inference resembles our reasoning with choices in that it also generates an indeterministic reasoning operator, but often differs in that it only requries to draw at least one conclusion, not necessarily exactly one.

  18. How? Partition S into a set \(S_{1}\) of ‘mandatory’ rules (which you must apply, leaving no choice-whether) and a set \(S_{2}\) of ‘optional’ rules (which you can apply, leaving a choice-whether). \(S_{1}\) represents your reasoning obligations, \(S_{2}\) your reasoning permissions. The generalised rule-based operator \(Cn_{S_{1},S_{2}}\) is definable like \(Cn_{S}\), merely replacing ‘maximal S-reasoning’ with ‘S-reasoning that is maximal w.r.t. \(S_{1}\)’ (suitably defined). \(Cn_{S_{1},S_{2}}\) reduces to \(Cn_{S}\) if \(S_{1}=S\) and \(S_{2}=\varnothing \), i.e., if all rules are mandatory. Theorem 1 generalises partly to \(Cn_{S_{1},S_{2}}\), which remains inclusive and monotonic, but can become non-idempotent.

  19. Intuitively, S contains only good rules (‘soundness’) and sufficiently many rules (‘completeness’). Examples of good rules might be the deterministic rules in (a)–(d) in Sect. 2.2 and the indeterministic rule in the Venice example. To be complete, S might need to contain these and many other rules; for instance, without the rule in the Venice example you are handicapped, i.e., unable to form a ‘boat’ or ‘train’ intention where needed. For deterministic rules, being good might mean being correct in Broome’s sense.

  20. Mono-modal logics address one attitude, e.g., belief in ‘doxastic logics’ (e.g., Halpern, 2017) and preferences in ‘preference logics’ (e.g., Liu, 2011). Multi-modal logics address more than one attitude, e.g., Footnote 19 continued belief, desire and intention in ‘BDI logics’. Logics of attitudes capture rationality of attitudes by axioms (e.g., axioms requiring that tautologies are believed).

  21. The entailment reads: I believe paying taxes is legally required. So, I intend to pay taxes.

  22. Under an as-if interpretation, a standard rational agent behaves as if maximising expected utility, but utilities and probabilities carry no psychological meaning, merely representing behaviour (cf. Cozic & Hill 2015). Under literal or mentalist interpretations, utilities and probabilities are psychological constructs capturing values and beliefs.

  23. Presumably, the assignment \(m\mapsto m^{*}\) defines a bijective correspondence between M and the set of logical sentences of type \(O(\phi )\) for some attitude operator O.

  24. Our formal statement of EE excludes choice-whether because the reasoning operator \(Cn_{S}\) excludes it (being defined by maximal reasoning). A version of EE that includes choice-whether is obtained by replacing \(Cn_{S}\) with the generalised operator defined in fn. 17. This version would be more clearly false.

  25. The modified hypothesis is: You necessarily reason to an attitude \(\underline{\text {if and only if}}\) your initial attitudes entail that attitude. Formally, for any initial constitution \(C\subseteq M\) and attitude \(k\in M,\)

    $$\begin{aligned} k\in \cap _{C^{+}\in Cn_{S}(C)}C^{+}\Leftrightarrow \{m^{*}:m\in C\}\models k^{*}. \end{aligned}$$
  26. In this context, note that you may intend something without intending its implications; e.g., you may intend to take a boat without intending to take a boat or a train.

  27. To draw an analogy with mathematical topology: in the space of logically possible actions, the set of actions of taking some boat is topologically connected, unlike the set of actions of taking some boat or some train.

  28. Under one approach, tie-breaking is an explicit part of reasoning that requires additional premise-beliefs, for instance the belief that such-and-such possible conclusion is selected by such-and-such tie-breaking rule, plus the intention to use this rule. Here your reasoning is only apparently indeterministic: you actually reason deterministically, with some implicit premises that break a tie. Yet the problem of indeterminacy might reemerge, as you need to come to intend a tie-breaking rule, thereby facing a choice between tie-breaking rules. Under another approach, tie-breaking rules intervene automatically. Might this undermine the idea of reasoning as a mental act? We cannot settle these and similar issues here.

  29. You may reason in partial beliefs (cf. Staffel, 2013); and you can do so explicitly, using markers such as ‘probably’. Such reasoning does of course not follow entailment between the contents of partial beliefs. But by ‘reasoning in beliefs’ we mean ‘reasoning in straight beliefs’.

  30. On an alternative view, your wondering is derived from no premises, as wondering needs no grounds. Then your complete inner speech might again take the form (9), but this time your wondering in (4) is derived from no premises rather than from (1)–(3).

  31. An alternative basis of k might be the set \(P\cup \{m_{l}:l\in K\backslash \{k\}\}\), where \(m_{l}\) is the belief of not possessing attitude l.

  32. Is \(P\cup \{m^{\prime }\}\) a permissible basis of k if \(m^{\prime }\) is, say, the intention not to take a boat or train to Venice, or the intention to travel to India (which prevents taking a train or boat to Venice)? This hinges on the notion of basis, which Broome and we find hard to spell out. Perhaps \(P\cup \{m^{\prime }\}\) is a permissible basis. If not, perhaps it becomes one after adding the belief that the attitude \(m^{\prime }\) implies not intending to take a boat or train to Venice. But a so-increased basis would again contain an introspective belief.

  33. After knowing how to model an instance of indeterministic reasoning, one can easily model indeterministic reasoning in general. For the shorthand model, this step was taken by introducing a reasoning system S, and defining how constitutions can change by reasoning with S (Definition 5). For our four full models, one could proceed analogously, by introducing a construct analogous to a reasoning system and defining how constitutions can change by reasoning with this construct.

  34. A rule of this sort is definable as a triple \((P_{1} ,P_{2},k)\), and adds the attitude k to a constitution C if \(P_{1}\subseteq C\) and \(P_{2}\cap C=\varnothing \).

  35. Note that \((C\cup \{k\})\backslash \{m\}=C\cup \{k\}\) if \(m\not \in C\).

  36. One might at first think that even in the fourth model reasoning has no final effect on m, since m is removed after having been added. This conclusion is however hasty, because the initial constitution C might already contains m, so that ‘adding’ m means ‘keeping’ m. Here reasoning does have a final effect on m: m was initially present, but is finally absent.

References

Download references

Acknowledgements

We are grateful for rich feedback and suggestions from John Broome, Christian List, Robert Sugden, Frederik van de Putte, other colleagues, and referees.

Funding

Franz Dietrich acknowledges support from the French Research Agency through three grants (ANR-17-CE26-0003, ANR-16-FRAL-0010 and ANR-17-EURE-0001).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Franz Dietrich.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendices

Appendix

A Explicit introspection

While Broomean reasoning is a process of bringing to mind premise-attitudes and then creating a new attitude, introspecting is arguably a process of bringing to mind your wondering and then creating a new meta-belief—although this belief is not derived from or based on your wondering, as introspecting is not an inferential process, unlike reasoning. Like Broomean reasoning, introspecting can in principle be done explicitly. How? By saying to yourself the marked content of your wondering and your resulting belief. Using the interrogative mood as a linguistic marker of wondering, you may introspect explicitly as follows in the fourth account of indeterministic reasoning:

$$\begin{aligned} \textit{Do I already intend to take a boat or train? I do not yet intend either.} \end{aligned}$$

You say no ‘So’, as you draw no inference, unlike in Broomean reasoning.

This suggests an objection against the fourth account: if indeterministic reasoning is indeed premised on a meta-belief whose formation by introspection requires wondering (as just claimed), then you cannot reason without wondering in the first place. In the Venice example: if reasoning to a ‘boat’ or ‘train’ intention requires finding out introspectively that you have neither intention, which requires wondering whether you do, then you cannot reason without initially wondering about this. But normally you do not initially wonder about this (why should you?). Technically, if your initial constitution C does not contain the relevant attitude of wondering, you cannot introspect, hence cannot reason.

What could help? You might be lucky and start wondering automatically when needed. But if the fourth account relied on ‘automatic wondering’, we could not uphold our claim that indeterministic reasoning on this account can be a mental activity (cf. Sect. 3.3).

Surprisingly, however, you can come to wonder about something by an act of Broomean reasoning. From what premises do you derive a wondering? Intuitively, the premises are the justifications or basis for wondering. In the Venice example, your wondering whether you already have a ‘boat’ or ‘train’ intention might be derived from your intention to visit Venice and your beliefs about possible means. Then the complete process by which you form a ‘boat’ intention (on the fourth account) is made explicit by the following inner speech:

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{l} \textit{(1)}~I \textit{shall visit Venice. (2) For this I must either take a boat or take a}\\ {train. ~(3) ~Both} \textit{ means are equally good. (4) Do I already intend a means?}\\ \textit{(5) I do not intend a means. (6) So, I shall take a boat.} \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
(9)

In (1)–(3) you bring to mind attitudes; from (1)–(3) you derive the wondering (4) by reasoning; from (4) you reach (5) by introspecting; from (1)–(3) and (5) you derive (6) by reasoning.Footnote 30

Our claim that you can derive a wondering by reasoning is certainly debatable. The claim is perhaps easier to accept if, as suggested in Sect. 3.4, wondering whether is a derived attitude, such as intending (or desiring) to know whether. In this case, reasoning to wondering is reasoning to a particular intention or desire. In our Venice example it seems very natural that, based on your initial attitudes, you derive an intention or desire to know whether you already hold specific intentions as to how to reach Venice. This derivation goes so quickly and easily that it rarely happens explicitly.

B Correct indeterministic reasoning?

According to Broome (2013), you can reason correctly to one of several possible conclusions. That is, given suitable sets P of premise-attitudes and K of possible conclusion-attitudes, you can reason correctly from P to any attitude in K. Broome focuses on instrumental reasoning, in which K contains intentions of a means to an end; for instance, in our Venice example K contains the ‘boat’ and ‘train’ intention, and P contains the intention to visit Venice and certain beliefs (about which Broome is more sophisticated than us, as mentioned in fn. 14). We have questioned Broome’s correctness claim, suggesting that correctness requires adding a premise-attitude to P, namely the belief of not yet having any attitude from K.

We here discuss the issue. For argument’s sake, we adopt Broome’s general characterisation of correctness: reasoning from a set of premise-attitudes P to a conclusion-attitude k is correct if P is a rationally permissible basis of k, more precisely, if it is rationally permitted to (i) hold the attitudes p in P at some moments and (ii) hold the attitude k at some moment based on the former attitudes. This so-called ‘basing permission’ is diachronic: it relates your attitudes at different moments. Indeed, reasoning takes time. By the time you reach the conclusion, you may have lost some premise-attitude(s), despite the conclusion-attitude being based on the premise-attitudes. Broome does not analyse what ‘based on’ means; nor shall we.

Broome applies this correctness criterion to certain examples of reasoning with different possible conclusions, similar to the Venice example. He claims that reasoning to any possible conclusion passes the correctness test. Technically, if P and K are the relevant attitude sets, say those in the Venice example, then for any k in K the rule (Pk) passes the correctness test, i.e., in short, P is a permissible basis of k. We doubt this claim. Were it true, you could reason correctly to all attitudes in K one by one, thereby forming conflicting intentions in the Venice example. Arguably, Broome has underspecified the basis of a k in K: a permissible basis is not P, but \(P\cup \{m\}\), where m is the belief of not (yet) having any attitude from K. One could replace m by other introspective beliefs.Footnote 31 It is hard to say whether one could replace m by a non-introspective (‘first-order’) attitude.Footnote 32

After deriving the conclusion-attitude k from \(P\cup \{m\}\), your introspective belief m is false. So rationality does not permit holding the conclusion-attitude and all premise-attitudes in \(P\cup \{m\}\) simultaneously. Yet rationality permits holding these attitudes at different times. This is why the reasoning rule \((P\cup \{m\},k)\) can meet the correctness test.

C Full psychological models of the four accounts of choice in reasoning

The main text worked with a shorthand model of choice in reasoning, which is account-neutral thanks to focusing on the ultimate effect of reasoning on attitudes rather than the psychological process. This appendix sketches how a full psychological model might roughly look under each account. In fact, we only discuss how to model a particular instance of choice in reasoning: reasoning from a set of premise-attitudes \(P\subseteq M\) to any attitude from a set of possible conclusion-attitudes \(K\subseteq M\) (in our Venice example, P contains the intention to visit Venice and two beliefs, and K contains the ‘boat’ intention and the ‘train’ intention). The shorthand model represents this instance by the indeterministic rule (PK). A full model might instead take the following form.Footnote 33

First account. Here, a full model of reasoning from P to any attitude in K has two ingredients. One is a deterministic rule \((P,k^{\vee })\) where \(k^{\vee }\) is a suitable ‘broad’ or ‘disjunctive’ conclusion-attitude (in the Venice example: the ‘boat or train’ intention). The second ingredient represents the psychological process that refines your disjunctive attitude \(k^{\vee }\) into an arbitrary attitude k in K (in the Venice example: into the ‘boat’ intention or ‘train’ intention). The composition of your reasoning rule \((P,k^{\vee })\) and the automatic process is effectively equivalent to the indeterministic rule (PK) in our shorthand model.

Second account. Here, a full model of reasoning from P to any attitude in K involves, for each possible conclusion attitude \(k\in K\), a rule that derives k if all attitudes in P are present and all attitudes in K are absent; denote this rule by (PKk). These rules are generalised deterministic rules, premised on presences and absences of attitudes.Footnote 34 Reasoning with the rules (PKk) (\(k\in K\)) is effectively equivalent to reasoning with the single indeterministic rule (PK). Why? For any initial constitution C, either \(K\cap C\ne \varnothing \), in which case none of these rules applies and the constitution stays C; or \(K\cap C=\varnothing \), in which case any rule (PKk) applies and leads to the new constitution \(C\cup \{k\}\), after which none of the rules applies anymore, so that the constitution stays \(C\cup \{k\}\). The result is the same as for reasoning with the indeterministic rule (PK).

Third account. Here, a full model of reasoning from P to any attitude in K involves, for each possible conclusion attitude \(k\in K\), the standard deterministic rule (Pk), which forms attitude k if you have all attitudes in P. The model also contains a precondition for applying these rules: each of these rules can only be applied to constitutions not yet containing any attitude from K. This precondition operationalises the assumption that when you start reasoning from the premise-attitudes in P but already possess an attitude from K, then (on the account) your reasoning stops, caused by your having in mind or bringing to mind a preexisting attitude from K. The precondition prevents the rules from operating the usual way: they effectively operate like the generalised deterministic rules from our model of the second account (i.e., rules premised on the absence of attitudes from K). This is why reasoning in the current model is effectively equivalent to reasoning in the second model, and hence to reasoning in the shorthand model based on the indeterministic rule (PK).

Fourth account. Here, a full model of reasoning from P to any attitude in K involves, for each possible conclusion attitude \(k\in K\), the standard deterministic rule \((P\cup \{m\},k)\), which forms attitude k from the attitudes in \(P\cup \{m\}\), where the additional premise-attitude m is the belief of having no attitude from K (in the Venice example: the belief of having no ‘boat’ intention and no ‘train’ intention). We must also model the mechanism that prevents repeated reasoning to different attitudes from K (we shall only model the first such mechanism envisaged by the fourth account). To do this, we prescribe that each rule \((P\cup \{m\},k)\) (\(k\in K\)) applies in a non-standard way to a constitution C: systematically, before application the attitude m is added to your constitution, and after application m is removed again. Interpretation: while reasoning you get aware of not having any attitude from K, i.e., form the belief m, and after reasoning you lose that belief as it has become false through forming an attitude from K. More precisely, m is only added (and later removed) if \(K\cap C=\varnothing \) and \(P\subseteq C\). Why only then? If \(K\cap C\ne \varnothing \) then the belief m is false, while if \(P\not \subseteq C\) then you do not have all attitudes in P, hence stop reasoning prematurely. In both cases, you never get to the point of forming (and later losing) the belief m. In sum, the rule \((P\cup \{m\},k)\) applies in the following non-standard way to any constitution C. If \(K\cap C=\varnothing \) and \(P\subseteq C\), then C is first transformed into \(C\cup \{m\}\), which is then transformed by the rule into \(C\cup \{m,k\}\), which is then transformed into \((C\cup \{k\})\backslash \{m\}\).Footnote 35 Otherwise, C is not transformed.

This model is hardly parsimonious—a drawback of modelling the full psychological process postulated by the fourth account. Reasoning on the fourth model is effectively equivalent to reasoning on the other models or the shorthand model, because the non-standard rules of the fourth model produce the same result as the non-standard rules of the second account, and hence as the indeterministic rule of the shorthand model. To be precise, this effective equivalence holds with respect to all attitudes except the introspective belief m. Indeed, reasoning in the other models never affects the presence of m, whereas reasoning in the fourth model can have a (final) effect on the presence of m.Footnote 36

D Proof of Theorem 1

For any constitution \(C\subseteq M\), reasoning system S, and number \(n\in \{0,1,...\}\), let \(Cn_{S,n}(C)\) denote the set of constitutions reachable from C in n steps of S-reasoning. Now fix a reasoning system S. The corresponding operator \(Cn_{S}\) is obviously inclusive and idempotent, for reasons already indicated. To show monotonicity, consider constitutions \(C,D\subseteq M\) such that \(C\subseteq D\), and fix a \(D^{+}\in Cn_{S}(D)\). Let \(S^{\prime }\) be the reasoning system arising from S by replacing each rule \((P,K)\in S\) satisfying \(K\cap D^{+}\ne \varnothing \) with the rule \((P,K\cap D^{+})\). So,

$$\begin{aligned} S^{\prime }=\{(P,K)\in S:K\cap D^{+}=\varnothing \}\cup \{(P,K\cap D^{+}):(P, k)\in S:K\cap D^{+}\ne \varnothing \}. \end{aligned}$$

Claim 1

For every number of steps \(n\in \{0,1,2,...\}\), each constitution \(C^{+}\in Cn_{S^{\prime },n}(C)\) satisfies \(C^{+}\subseteq D^{+}\) and \(C^{+}\in Cn_{S,n}(C)\).

We prove this claim by an induction on n. For \(n=0\), then the claim is obvious because \(Cn_{S^{\prime },0}(C)=Cn_{S,0}=\{C\}\) and because \(C\subseteq D\subseteq D^{+}\). Now assume \(n>0\) and suppose the claim holds for smaller numbers than n. Fix any \(C^{+}\in Cn_{S^{\prime },n}(C)\). Pick a \(\tilde{C}\in Cn_{S^{\prime },n-1}(C)\) such that \(C^{+}\in Cn_{S^{\prime },1}(\tilde{C})\). The fact that \(C^{+}\in Cn_{S^{\prime },1}(\tilde{C})\) and the definition of \(S^{\prime }\) imply that \(C^{+}\subseteq \tilde{C}\cup D^{+}\). So, as by induction hypothesis \(\tilde{C}\subseteq D^{+}\), we have \(C^{+}\subseteq D^{+}\).

It remains to show that \(C^{+}\in Cn_{S,n}(C)\). As \(\tilde{C}\in Cn_{S,n-1}(C)\), it suffices to prove \(C^{+}\in Cn_{S,1}(\tilde{C})\). As \(C^{+}\in Cn_{S^{\prime },1}(\tilde{C})\), we can pick a rule \((P,K^{\prime })\in S^{\prime }\) by which \(C^{+}\) arises from \(\tilde{C}\). By definition of \(S^{\prime }\), there exists a \(K\subseteq M\) such that \((P,K)\in S\) and either [\(K\cap D^{+}=\varnothing \) and \(K^{\prime }=K\)] or [\(K\cap D^{+}\ne \varnothing \) and \(K^{\prime }=K\cap D^{+}\)]. The first case is impossible: it would imply that \(D^{+}\) is not closed under S-reasoning, because S contains the rule (PK) which modifies \(D^{+}\) since \(P\subseteq D^{+}\) (as \(P\subseteq \tilde{C}\) and \(\tilde{C}\subseteq D^{+}\)) and since \(K\cap D^{+}=\varnothing \). So the second case holds. Note that

$$\begin{aligned} \tilde{C}\cap K=\tilde{C}\cap [K^{\prime }\cup (K\backslash D^{+} )]=(\tilde{C}\cap K^{\prime })\cup (\tilde{C}\cap (K\backslash D^{+})). \end{aligned}$$

In the last expression, \(\tilde{C}\cap K^{\prime }=\varnothing \) (as otherwise the rule \((P,K^{\prime })\) could not change \(\tilde{C}\)) and \(\tilde{C} \cap (K\backslash D^{+})=\varnothing \) (as \(\tilde{C}\subseteq D^{+}\) by induction hypothesis). So \(\tilde{C}\cap K=\varnothing \). Since \(P\subseteq \tilde{C}\) and \(\tilde{C}\cap K=\varnothing \), the rule (PK) applies to \(\tilde{C}\), just as the rule \((P,K^{\prime })\). So, one can reason from \(\tilde{C}\) to \(C^{+}\) not just using \((P,K^{\prime })\), but also using (PK). In other words, \(C^{+}\) belongs not just to \(Cn_{S^{\prime },1} (\tilde{C})\), but also to \(Cn_{S,1}(\tilde{C})\). Q.e.d.

Claim 2

\(Cn_{S^{\prime }}(C)\subseteq Cn_{S}(C)\).

Let \(C^{+}\in Cn_{S^{\prime }}(C)\). Then \(C^{+}\in Cn_{S^{\prime },n}(C)\) for some \(n\in \{0,1,...\}\). So, by Claim 1, \(C^{+}\in Cn_{S,n}(C)\). It remains to show that \(C^{+}\) is stable under S-reasoning. To show this, consider any rule \((P,K)\in S\) such that \(P\subseteq C^{+}\). We must show that \(K\cap C^{+}\ne \varnothing \). Form the rule \((P,K^{\prime })\in S^{\prime }\), where \(K^{\prime }\) is K if \(K\cap D^{+}=\varnothing \) and is \(K\cap D^{+}\) otherwise. Since \(C^{+}\) is closed under \(S^{\prime }\)-reasoning, the rule \((P,K^{\prime })\) does not change \(C^{+}\), i.e., \(K^{\prime }\cap C^{+} \ne \varnothing \). So, \(K\cap C^{+}\ne \varnothing \). Q.e.d.

Claim 3

Some \(C^{+}\in Cn_{S}(C)\) satisfies \(C^{+}\subseteq D^{+}\).

Pick a \(C^{+}\in Cn_{S^{\prime }}(C)\). By Claim 2, \(C^{+}\in Cn_{S}(C)\). Further, \(C^{+}\in Cn_{S^{\prime },n}(C)\) for some n, and so \(C^{+}\subseteq D^{+}\) by Claim 1. Q.e.d.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dietrich, F., Staras, A. Reasoning in attitudes. Synthese 200, 519 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03986-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03986-3

Keywords

Navigation