Skip to main content
Log in

Physicalism, supervenience, and monism

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Physicalism is standardly construed as a form of monism, on which all concrete phenomena fall under one fundamental type. It is natural to think that monism, and therefore physicalism, is committed to a supervenience claim. Monism is true only if all phenomena supervene on a certain fundamental type of phenomena. Physicalism, as a form of monism, specifies that these fundamental phenomena are physical. But some argue that physicalism might be true even if the world is disorderly, i.e., not ordered by supervenience relations in the way commonly supposed (Montero in J Philos 110:92–110, 2013; Leuenberger in Inquiry 57:151–174, 2014; Montero and Brown in Topoi 37(3):523–532, 2018; Zhong in Philos Stud 178(5):1529–1544, 2021). Unless these authors intend to challenge the claim that physicalism is a type of monism—a claim so central to the dialectic in philosophy of mind that rejecting it risks changing the subject—they are committed to challenging a supervenience requirement for monism. We argue that monism entails that there are substantial supervenience relations among concrete phenomena: relations that would not obtain in a disorderly world. Our argument thus has implications for debates about physicalism and supervenience, and sheds light on an under-discussed issue: what is implied by classifying a theory in the philosophy of mind as a form of monism? We also argue that physicalism’s commitment to monism creates problems for via negativa physicalism, on which the physical is characterized negatively.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Kripke (1972), Lewis (1983), Jackson (1998), Chalmers (1996, 2010), Witmer (2001), Kim (2005), Wilson (2005), Stoljar (2010), Pereboom (2011) and Howell (2013).

  2. The restriction to concrete phenomena sidesteps issues concerning abstract phenomena such as numbers and sets—issues that are not directly relevant to the mind–body debate (pace Schneider, 2017). This restriction will be assumed in what follows. We use “phenomena” to refer to entities, properties, relations, and events, i.e., everything.

  3. For other responses to those arguments, see Alter (2021). For responses to the arguments in Montero (2013) specifically, see also Howell (2012), Jackson (2012) and Witmer (2012.).

  4. We thank both anonymous referees for Synthese for pressing us to flesh out the motivations and commitments of monism.

  5. Some views classified as “neutral monism” are monistic in name only (Stubenberg, 2018), but we set those aside. A neutral monism that is genuinely monistic claims that there is a substantive unified nature underlying mental and physical entities (and indeed all other non-fundamental entities) which is neither mental nor physical but more fundamental than each.

  6. We use the terms “category”, “type”, and “nature” more or less interchangeably.

  7. The main traditional theories concerning the mind–body problem are monist or dualist. But there are other possibilities in logical space, such as a pluralist theory on which there are more than two distinct fundamental categories and a nihilist view on which there are no fundamental categories. And there are, of course, other theories in the vicinity, such as functionalism, that can be dualist or monist, depending on how they are explicated.

  8. Robinson (2020) (see also Schaffer, 2010). Here “fundamental” modifies types or categories, rather than token phenomena (for a discussion of token monism, see Horgan & Potrč, 2000). Monism of the relevant kind applies to all (concrete) phenomena, fundamental and non-fundamental alike.

  9. Further, these concerns arise only assuming that being concrete and being mental or physical are fundamental categories, and that assumption is questionable, especially regarding the latter, disjunctive property.

  10. Note that this commitment of monism is existential, asserting that there is a fundamental, unified, substantive nature that all phenomena share. That does not entail that we know, or even can know, much about what that shared nature is.

  11. There are probably some hard cases: theories for which it is debatable whether their central claims can be expressed in terms of M. That is partly because M requires that the relevant shared nature be unified, and what it takes for a nature to be unified might not always be entirely clear. A potential example is the “panprotopsychist” version of Russellian monism (Alter & Pereboom, 2019). According to this view, the basic structural properties posited by fundamental physics (e.g., mass and charge) are underlain by non-structural, protophenomenal properties, where “protophenomenal properties are special properties that are not phenomenal…but that can collectively constitute phenomenal properties, perhaps when arranged in the right structure” (Chalmers, 2013, p. 259). Is panprotopsychist Russellian monism a version of monism? Perhaps not: the view posits not one but two fundamentally distinct sorts of properties, structural and non-structural. Or perhaps so: on this view, “nature consists of entities with intrinsic (proto)phenomenal qualities standing in causal relations within a space-time manifold” (Chalmers, 2010, pp. 133–134). As Chalmers (2010, p. 134) observes, “This view has elements in common with both materialism and dualism…One might suggest that while the view arguably fits the letter of materialism, it shares the spirit of anti-materialism”. One might make the reverse suggestion regarding whether panprotopsychist Russellian monism is a version of monism: while the view shares the spirit of monism, it fits the letter of dualism.

  12. Howell’s proposal is “neo-Cartesian” because it is modeled on the Cartesian view that to be physical (or bodily) is to be extended in three spatial dimensions.

  13. This is a simplification. As Howell (2013) explains, there are complications surrounding categorical bases, as well as the potential emergence of spacetime, as well as a potential “Hempel’s dilemma” for the notion of spacetime (see Sect. 4). But the simplified version suffices for present purposes.

  14. For other examples, see Chalmers (2020b), Loewer (2001) and Wilson (2006).

  15. We thank an anonymous referee for raising this concern.

  16. The term “arché” means roughly “first principle” or “origin.” As Guthrie (1962, p. 7) writes, “It means, first, the original state out of which the manifold world has developed, and, secondly, the permanent ground of its being, or as Aristotle would call it, the substratum”. The goal was to find a single element which served this purpose, e.g., water, for Thales.

  17. Montero (2012, p. 1).

  18. For example, Loewer (2001, p. 47) writes, “Physicalism claims that all facts obtain in virtue of the distribution of the fundamental entities and properties—whatever they turn out to be—of completed fundamental physics”. If the physicalist’s shared nature comes down to being posits of completed fundamental physics, or existing in virtue of those posits, then once again matter and anti-matter would plainly qualify has having that nature.

  19. Physicalists typically take the fundamental properties to be specific properties posited by physics, such as mass and charge. The category of being physical, however explicated, is not an additional fundamental property, alongside those specific physical properties. Nothing we say should be understood as implying otherwise.

  20. One might prefer to characterize the physical in terms of laws rather than natures. For example, one might say that physicalism is true if and only if everything is determined by physical laws. But what makes a law a physical law? Would psychophysical laws qualify? What should be said about “naturalistic dualists” who can allow that, as a matter of contingent fact, the mental supervenes on the physical (Chalmers, 1996)? More generally, analogues of the issues we address concerning physical natures arise for law-oriented conceptions of physicalism.

  21. Howell (2013) recognizes the complication and handles it similarly (cf. Chalmers, 2004, pp. 286–287, 2010, p. 142). Again, we refer to Howell’s account of the physical only for purposes of illustration. If a different account (such as, e.g., Loewer 2001) is preferred, that can be substituted in the definition of “physical*”.

  22. Officially, we take no stand on how best to express the monist’s commitment. For stylistic convenience, we will usually stick with the formulation just mentioned, that all (concrete) phenomena are nothing over and above n-phenomena.

  23. A more precise formulation of PSV would address issues arising from indexicality (Chalmers, 2010, chap. 6). But those issues are not especially relevant here. The same qualification applies to the other supervenience claims we discuss below, such as SV.

  24. For examples of type-A materialism, see Armstrong (1968) and Lewis (1966). For examples of type-B materialism, see Block (2006), Howell (2013) and Papineau (2002).

  25. Armstrong (1968), Lewis (1966), Place (1956) and Smart (1959).

  26. Premise 2 uses the “nothing over and above” locution to express a commitment of monism that could be expressed in other ways, e.g., in terms of constitution; see above, Sect. 2. Those other expressions all have the same implications regarding supervenience that premise 3 expresses.

  27. For the sake of argument, we grant that Montero’s disorderly world is metaphysically possible.

  28. There might be a way to avoid those consequences without committing to monism. But if so, it is not clear what that way is. Nor is it clear that any such way would also preserve the result Montero desires, of detaching physicalism from supervenience claims such as PSV.

  29. Spurrett (2001), Wilson (2006) and Witmer (2018) could be understood as suggesting a view roughly along these lines.

  30. We state this problem in this way because we understand via negativa physicalism to assert a metaphysical thesis, about what being physical consists in. One could instead understand that metaphysical thesis to motivate via negativa physicalism, and define the view in another way, e.g., as a linguistic thesis about the meaning of the word “physical”. In that case, the incompatibility problem would concern not via negativa physicalism itself but rather the metaphysical thesis that motivates it. (We thank an anonymous referee for pointing this out). But that would not diminish the problem’s significance.

  31. For example, a nature defined as a lack of fundamental mentality would not be projectable (wouldn’t allow law-like generalizations) in the way a physical nature should be (Kim, 1993).

  32. Chalmers (1996, 2002, 2010). A hypothesis h is ideally conceivability if h is conceivable on ideal rational reflection (Chalmers, 2002).

  33. One such truth about consciousness is “Consciousness exists”. Regarding structural properties, Chalmers (2013, p. 256) writes, “a structural property is one that can be fully characterized using structural concepts alone, which I take to include logical, mathematical, and nomic concepts, perhaps along with spatiotemporal concepts”. Claims such as (i) and (ii) need not be formulated in terms of structure. For example, in both (i) and (ii), “structural truths” could be replaced with “truths about features exhausted by their spatiotemporal implications”, as on Howell’s (2013) account of the physical.

  34. Cf. Alter and Coleman (2021, Sect. 4). Note that we are not assuming either that the zombie argument is sound or that the premise that zombies are conceivable is true. We do assume that premise has some prima facie plausibility. But that much even critics of the argument usually concede (Kirk, 2021; Stoljar, 2006).

  35. Another monism-related problem for via negativa physicalism concerns neutral monism. On neutral monism, there is no fundamental mentality: mentality is a manifestation of a deeper reality, which is neither physical nor mental—and thus not fundamentally mental. Therefore, on via negativa physicalism, neutral monism threatens to collapse into a form of physicalism (cf. Kind, 2015). But that result seems undesirable. Neutral monism should qualify as a distinct position in its own right, on par with physicalism, dualism, and idealism. At least, such a form of neutral monism should not be excluded from theoretical space.

  36. We will usually assume the “fully” qualification is understood.

  37. Skiles’ (2015, p. 738) formulation of global supervenience (with which he says grounding contingentism is compatible) is slightly stronger than SV, since his formulation omits a minimality constraint.

  38. Objection: Skiles's cases, such as his tuna sandwich case, show that grounding does not always entail necessitation; therefore, it is ad hoc to insist that a global grounding claim requires a global necessitation claim. Reply: If Skiles's cases involve grounding without necessitation, that is due to features specific to local grounding, e.g., features of our concept of a sandwich. It does not follow that it is ad hoc to assume that global grounding entails global supervenience. Fine (2012) and Rosen (2010), and many others take that entailment claim as axiomatic. (Fine (2012, p. 1) writes that the grounding relation “is like that of consequence in that a necessary connection must hold between the relata if the relation is to obtain”.) Further, Skiles’s argument depends on accepting the assumption that an ordinary composite object, such as a sandwich, is fully grounded in its parts. One could take his cases to challenge that assumption, rather than establishing even the local version of grounding contingentism he takes them to establish. And again, his view does not conflict with the global supervenience of every fact on the fundamental facts.

  39. Our main objections also apply to Leuenberger’s other argument against Entailment, mutatis mutandis.

  40. It is also worth noting that, if considered in isolation, the premise could be taken to express a claim that is highly plausible but far too weak for Leuenberger’s argument to succeed. One might take the word “Possibly” to mean not “There is a possible world in which” but rather “We do not know for certain that”. It is hard to deny that we do not know for certain that physicalism is false. Even dualists should concede that much, in the name of rational humility. But if the premise expressed merely a non-certainty claim and nothing more, then Leuenberger’s argument against Entailment would be plainly invalid. From a concession to humility, nothing interesting about Entailment follows.

  41. That is PSV. Again, PSV is modeled on Jackson’s formulation of the physicalist’s supervenience claim, in which the minimality condition is also stated expressly: “Any world that is a minimal physical duplicate of our world is a duplicate simpliciter of our world” (Jackson, 1998, p. 12, italics in original).

References

  • Alter, T. (2021). A defense of the supervenience requirement on physicalism. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, 10(4), 264–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alter, T., & Coleman, S. (2021). Russellian monism and mental causation. Noûs, 55, 409–425.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alter, T., & Pereboom, D. (2019). Russellian monism. In E. N. Zalta (Eds.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2019 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/russellian-monism/.

  • Armstrong, D. (1968). A materialist theory of mind. Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkeley, G. (1710). A treatise concerning the principles of human knowledge. In A. Luce & T. Jessop (Eds.), The works of George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne (pp. 1948–1957). Thomas Nelson and Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2006). Max Black’s objection to mind-body identity. In R. Zimmerman (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 2, pp. 3–78). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2002). Does conceivability entail possibility? In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and Possibility (pp. 145–200). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2004). Phenomenal concepts and the knowledge argument. In P. Ludlow, D. Stoljar, & Y. Nagasawa (Eds.), There’s something about Mary: Essays on phenomenal consciousness and Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument (pp. 269–298). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2010). The character of consciousness. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2013). Panpsychism and panprotopsychism. Amherst lecture in philosophy. http://www.amherstlecture.org/index.html. Also in T. Alter and Y. Nagasawa (Eds.) (2015), Consciousness in the physical world: Perspectives on Russellian Monism (pp. 246–76). Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2020a). Idealism and the mind-body problem. In W. Seager (Ed.), The routledge handbook of panpsychism (pp. 353–373). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2020b). Spatiotemporal functionalism v. the conceivability of zombies. Noûs, 54(2), 488–497.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E., & Sider, T. (2005). Riddles of existence: A guided tour of metaphysics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2012). The pure logic of ground. Review of Symbolic Logic, 5, 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiorese, R. (2016). Stoljar’s dilemma and three conceptions of the physical: A defence of the via negativa. Erkenntnis, 81(2), 201–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guthrie, W. K. C. (1962). A history of Greek philosophy: Volume 5, The Later Plato and the academy. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., & Potrč, M. (2000). Blobjectivism and indirect correspondence. Facta Philosophica, 2, 249–270.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howell, R. J. (2013). Consciousness and the limits of objectivity: The case for subjective physicalism. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howell, R. J. (2012). Comments on Montero’s “Must physicalism imply the supervenience of the mental on the physical?”. Retrieved from https://consciousnessonline.files.wordpress.com/2012/02/howell-comments-on-montero.pdf

  • Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics: A defence of conceptual analysis. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (2012). Response by Frank Jackson to Barbara Gail Montero’s “Must Physicalism Imply the Supervenience of the Mental on the Physical?”. Retrieved from https://consciousnessonline.files.wordpress.com/2012/02/jackson-comments-onmontero.pdf

  • Kim, J. (1993). Supervenience and mind: Selected philosophical essays. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2005). Physicalism, or something near enough. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kind, A. (2015). Pessimism about Russellian monism. In T. Alter & Y. Nagasawa (Eds.), Consciousness in the physical world: Perspectives on Russellian monism (pp. 401–421). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirk, R. (2021). Zombies. In E. N. Zalta (Eds.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2021 Edition). Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/zombies/

  • Kripke, S. (1972). Naming and necessity. In Harman and Davidson (Eds.), The semantics of natural language (pp. 253–355). D. Reidel Publishing Company.

  • Leuenberger, S. (2014). Grounding and necessity. Inquiry, 57, 151–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. (2001). Purple haze: The puzzle of consciousness. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1966). An argument for the identity theory. Journal of Philosophy, 63, 17–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61, 343–377.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. M. (2001). From physics to physicalism. In C. Gillett & B. Loewer (Eds.), Physicalism and its discontents (pp. 37–56). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. G. (2005). What is the physical? In B. McLaughlin (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mind (pp. 173–188). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. G. (2013). Must physicalism imply supervenience of the mental on the physical? Journal of Philosophy, 110, 93–110.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. G. (2012). Response to Robert J. Howell’s commentary. Retrieved from https://consciousnessonline.files.wordpress.com/2012/02/montero-response-to-howell.pdf

  • Montero, B., & Brown, C. D. (2018). Making room for a this-worldly physicalism. Topoi, 37(3), 523–532.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B., & Papineau, D. (2005). A defence of the via negativa argument for physicalism. Analysis, 65, 233–237.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2002). Thinking about consciousness. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pelczar, M. (2015). Sensorama: A phenomenalist analysis of spacetime and its contents. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2011). Consciousness and the prospects of physicalism. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Place, U. T. (1956). Is consciousness a brain process? British Journal of Psychology, 47, 44–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1967). The nature of mental states. Originally entitled “Psychological predicates.” In W. H. Capitan & D. D. Merrill (Eds.), Art, mind, and religion (pp. 37–48). Pittsburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, H. (2020). Dualism. In E. N. Zalta (Eds.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2020 Edition). Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/dualism/

  • Rosen, G. (2010). Metaphysical dependence: Grounding and reduction. In B. Hale & A. Hoffman (Eds.), Modality: Metaphysics, logic, and epistemology (pp. 109–135). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2010). Monism: The priority of the whole. Philosophical Review, 119, 31–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, S. (2017). Does the mathematical nature of physics undermine physicalism? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 24(9–10), 7–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skiles, A. (2015). Against grounding necessitarianism. Erkenntnis, 80, 717–751.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. J. C. (1959). Sensations and brain processes. Philosophical Review, 68, 141–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spurrett, D. (2001). What physical properties are. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 82(2), 201–225.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spurrett, D., & Papineau, D. (1999). A note on the completeness of ‘physics.’ Analysis, 59, 25–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2006). Ignorance and imagination: The epistemic origin of the problem of consciousness. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2010). Physicalism. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stubenberg, L. (2018). Neutral monism. In E. N. Zalta (Eds.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2018 Edition). Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/neutral-monism/

  • Wilson, J. M. (2005). Supervenience-based formulations of physicalism. Noûs, 39, 426–459.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (2006). On characterizing the physical. Philosophical Studies, 131, 61–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Witmer, D. G. (2001). Sufficiency claims and physicalism: A formulation. In C. Gillett & B. Loewer (Eds.), Physicalism and its discontents (pp. 57–73). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Witmer, D. G. (2018). Physicality for physicalists. Topoi, 37(3), 457–472.

    Google Scholar 

  • Witmer, G. (2012). Comments on Montero’s “Must physicalism imply the supervenience of the mental on the physical?”. Retrieved from https://consciousnessonline.files.wordpress.com/2012/02/witmer-comments-on-montero-co4-copy.pdf

  • Worley, S. (2006). Physicalism and the via negativa. Philosophical Studies, 131(1), 101–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhong, L. (2021). Physicalism without supervenience. Philosophical Studies, 178(5), 1529–1544.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper was inspired by a challenge Amy Kind posed to us at the 2022 Central Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association. We thank her for that and for providing helpful comments on a draft. Thanks also to Alyssa Ney, who was the commentator at that APA session and who pressed us to address arguments by Skiles and Leuenberger. We presented our main argument to a “Mind and Language” Zoom group organized by Melissa Ebbers and Luke Roelofs, and we received helpful feedback; we thank Ebbers, Roelofs, and the others who participated. Finally, we thank Derk Pereboom and both anonymous referees for Synthese, all of which gave us helpful suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Torin Alter.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

There are no potential conflict of interest.

Research involving human participants and/or animals

This paper involved no such research.

Informed consent

This paper involved no subjects, human or otherwise.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Addendum: grounding and supervenience

Addendum: grounding and supervenience

We have argued that monism is committed to a “nothing over and above” claim, or something similar. Such claims are sometimes expressed in terms of (metaphysical) grounding. For example, the “nothing over and above” claim associated with physicalist monism is sometimes expressed as the claim that all truths (at least, all truths about the concrete world) are fully grounded in physical (or physical*) truths.Footnote 36 Grounding is widely held to entail metaphysical necessitation, that is, supervenience (Fine, 2012; Rosen, 2010). Given that widely held view, the claim that all truths are grounded in physical (or physical*) truths implies a further commitment to a supervenience claim such as PSV.

However, that the widely accepted connection between grounding and supervenience has been disputed. Arguments for what is sometimes termed “contingent grounding” have been developed by Leuenberger (2014) and Skiles (2015). Thus, those arguments might appear to threaten our claims about monism, physicalism, and supervenience. In this addendum, we will consider those arguments. We will argue that they do not undermine our claims.

Skiles (2015) argues for grounding contingentism, which holds that a fact P can be grounded in a set of facts Γ but without supervening on Γ. He bases his argument largely on counterexamples to grounding necessitarianism, which holds that if Γ grounds P, then P supervenes on Γ. One type of counterexample begins with the idea that an ordinary composite object is grounded in its parts (Conee & Sider, 2005, p. 68). Skiles then considers rearrangements of those parts, modeled on the ship of Theseus:

Let ‘‘o’’ pick out a particular tuna sandwich. Suppose that in an earlier epoch, the existence of o is grounded in an arrangement of its parts, the as (call this arrangement ‘‘Γ’’). At a later epoch, one of the as (call it ‘‘a1’’) is sloughed off and replaced with a duplicate (call it ‘‘b1’’). There is now a sandwich composed of b1, a2, … an: this sandwich (call it ‘‘o1’’) is presumably identical to o. Suppose this process of gradual replacement repeats so that eventually in a later epoch, we are left with two sandwiches: one (call it ‘‘on’’) identical to o and composed of b1, b2, ..., bn, but also another sandwich (call it ‘‘oR’’, for replacement) composed of a1, a2, ..., an and placed in the same arrangement, Γ, they were in when they composed o in the earlier epoch. Finally, o is destroyed, leaving oR unscathed. Although all the facts in Γ obtain during this later epoch, [o exists] does not; hence although the existence of o was grounded in these facts about its parts, they do not necessitate o’s existence. (Skiles, 2015, p. 722)

Skiles’s case is a counterexample to grounding necessitarianism only if the latter is viewed as a local doctrine about a particular part of reality being grounded in another part of reality. His case doesn’t challenge global necessitarianism, however, which is all we need for our purposes. SV is a form of global supervenience. It says that any possible world that is a minimal n-duplicate of the actual world is a duplicate simpliciter of actual world. If successful, Skiles’s argument would show only that grounding does not entail certain local supervenience claims. The same is true of Skiles’s other counterexamples to grounding necessitarianism. Indeed, Skiles acknowledges the point, noting that, “grounding contingentism is…compatible with the global supervenience of every fact on the fundamental facts” (Skiles, 2015, p. 738).Footnote 37 We shouldn’t infer from the failure of local necessitation that global necessitation fails any more than we should infer from the fact that someone can stand without a foot on the ground that they can stand without any feet on the ground.Footnote 38

Let us turn to Leuenberger’s argument. His “main target” (Leuenberger, F, p. 155) is the following claim, where ‘Γ’ is the set of facts that grounds fact A, ‘<’ denotes the grounding relation, ‘□’ is a metaphysical necessity operator, ‘O(A)’ and ‘O(Γ)’ “express that A obtains and that all members of Γ obtain, respectively” (Leuenberger, 2014, p. 154):

Entailment Necessarily, if Γ < A then □(O(Γ) -> O(A)). (Leuenberger, 2014, p. 155).

Leuenberger presents two arguments against Entailment. We will focus on the one that is most relevant to present concerns.Footnote 39

That argument concerns physicalism, which, he notes, entails that all facts, including phenomenal facts, are grounded in actual physical facts. As an example of a phenomenal fact, he mentions ‘Red’: “the fact that I am having a red experience” (Leuenberger, 2014, p. 157). In his view, it is conceivable, and therefore possible, that all actual physical facts obtain but Red does not. And that, he claims, is compatible with the physicalist claim that Red is grounded in the actual physical facts.

Leuenberger’s argument can be formalized as follows:

  1. 1.

    Possibly, physicalism is true and Red obtains as a non-fundamental fact.

  2. 2.

    Necessarily, there are no physical facts Γ such that □(O(Γ)—> O(Red)).

  3. 3.

    Necessarily, if physicalism is true, then for every non-fundamental fact A there are physical facts Γ such that Γ < A.

From these premises, it follows (even in a very weak modal logic) that it is not necessary that for all Γ, if Γ < Red then □(O(Γ) —> O(Red)), and hence that Entailment has a false instance. (Leuenberger, 2014, p. 157)

Unlike Skiles’s argument, Leuenberger’s might, if convincing, threaten our contention that grounding of the sort to which monists are committed entails a supervenience claim such as SV (though as we will explain, this is not entirely clear). However, his argument is not convincing. Consider premise 1. That premise says (or immediately entails) that there is a possible world in which the only fundamental facts are physical and yet Red obtains. But the latter is precisely the sort of claim that dualists deny. In the context of the debate over what physicalism requires, such a claim cannot be asserted without independent support—support that should be convincing to a neutral party, that is, to someone who is neither committed to physicalism nor committed to non-physicalism. But Leuenberger provides no such independent support.

Leuenberger considers a variant of the foregoing objection to his premise 1. He labels that variant “the objection from dualism” and suggests that the objection is dialectically problematic. He does not make his basis for that suggestion entirely clear, but the gist of it seems to be that to resist his argument against Entailment, one would have to be “saddle[d]…with a commitment to the falsity of physicalism” (Leuenberger, 2014, p. 158). But that is not so. One need not assume that physicalism is false in order to object that premise 1 is dialectically inapt. That dialectical concern about premise 1 can be raised by someone who is neutral regarding physicalism’s truth or falsity.Footnote 40

A similar problem arises for premise 2. That premise asserts a claim that is hotly contested in the mind–body literature. It requires substantial independent support. Leueberger fails to satisfy that requirement. Instead, he merely asserts that it is conceivable for the physical facts to obtain while Red does not that this conceivability suggests the corresponding possibility, and that “we have no particular reason to think that the appearance of possibility is misleading in this case” (Leuenberger, 2014, p. 157). But as he concedes, “it is hard to substantiate these claims, and flesh out a modal epistemology to back up one’s modal claim” (Leuenberger, 2014, p. 158). Further, in the context of the debate over what physicalism requires, the plausibility of those claims—claims that physicalists reject—cannot be simply taken for granted.

Leuenberger considers an objection in the vicinity of that dialectical concern. But once again, he mischaracterizes it, labeling it “the objection from necessitarianism” and suggesting that it rests on a controversial “necessitarian” doctrine, on which “metaphysical possibility is just logical compatibility with the laws of nature” (Leuenberger, 2014, p. 158). But the dialectical concern rests on no such doctrine. Instead, the concern is that he bases premise 2 on claims that are, in the context of the mind–body debate, not merely contentious but centrally disputed—and that he does so without providing anything close to sufficient justification.

Leuenberger gives one further argument that is worth considering. He argues that physicalism is compatible with the possibility of zombies. He develops that argument in response to an objection to the compatibility of his premises 1 and 2, but it could as easily be seen as an independent argument against Entailment. The argument involves the following variant Kripke’s creation metaphor, which we discussed above, in Sect. 3:

In the actual world, God had put all the physical facts in place by the end of day seven. This was enough to make it the case that Red obtains. God henceforth left the world alone. In world wb, God on day eight ensured that in the region occupied by my brain, a non-physical fundamental property, to be called ‘chromaplasm’, is instantiated. Chromaplasm makes visual phenomenology disappear. In wb, I do not have a red experience, i.e. Red does not hold. (Leuenberger, 2014, p. 160)

As Leuenberger (2014, p. 160) notes, physicalism is not true of wb “because of the presence of chromaplasm”. And yet, he claims, physicalism is true of the actual world, as he describes it.

Since in the actual world God only created physical facts and then retired, physicalism is true. All the actual fundamental facts are physical, after all, and that seems to be sufficient condition for the truth of physicalism. Hence Red is grounded by some class of physical facts. (Leuenberger, 2014, p. 161)

However, that argument faces at least two problems. First, it is dialectically problematic in the same way that his premises 1 and 2 are. In describing his variant of Kripke’s creation myth, he asserts that God’s creating the physical facts “was enough to make it the case that Red obtains”. But in the context of the mind–body debate, the claim that creating the physical facts suffices to create phenomenal facts such as Red cannot be simply asserted. Second, the supervenience claim to which physicalists are arguably committed includes a minimality condition: any world that is a minimal physical* duplicate of our world is a duplicate simpliciter of our world.Footnote 41 Although wb is a physical duplicate of the actual world, it is not a minimal physical duplicate, due to the presence of chromoplasm. This is important, because the minimality condition reflects an important feature of the grounding claim: the phenomenal fact Red is fully grounded in certain physical conditions and the fact that nothing else is added. So, the scenario Leuenberger describes is not one where the physicalist’s grounding claim is true while her supervenience claim fails.

Thus, neither Skiles's argument nor Leuenberger’s argument establish the compatibility of physicalist’s grounding claim with the denial of her supervenience claim.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Alter, T., Howell, R.J. Physicalism, supervenience, and monism. Synthese 200, 515 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03965-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03965-8

Keywords

Navigation