Skip to main content
Log in

Shared consciousness and asymmetry

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is widely held that there is an asymmetry between our access to our minds and our access to others’ minds. Philosophers in the literature tend to focus on the asymmetry between our access to our mental states and our access to those mental states of others that are not shared by us. What if a mental state can have multiple subjects? Is there still an asymmetry between our access to our mental states and our access to those mental states of others that are also ours? In this paper, I discuss the implications of a case of shared consciousness—the case of the Hogan twins—for asymmetry. I start by clarifying the notion of asymmetry. Here I develop a characterization of asymmetry and argue that it is preferable to the standard approaches in the literature. I then present the twins’ case and argue that it does not threaten asymmetry. I close by drawing some lessons.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Since there are no reports of shared unconscious mental states, in what follows I will mainly focus on shared consciousness.

  2. An exception is Kriegel (2017). Kriegel is primarily concerned with the link between consciousness and dignity. Central to Kriegel’s account is the notion of “phenomenal inviolability,” according to which “every experience can be experienced by only one person” (p. 131). Although Kriegel mentions that the twins’ case is the only known exception to “phenomenal inviolability,” where each can access the other’s experiences in the same way that the other can, he says little to defend his view on the twins’ case. As I will argue, even if the twins’ case is an exception to “phenomenal inviolability,” there is still an asymmetry between each’s access to her experiences and her access to the other’s experiences.

  3. In fact, even Ryle (2009) can accept ASYMMETRYe. On Ryle’s view, the difference between our access to our minds and our access to others’ minds is a difference in “the supplies of the requisite data” (p. 138). It is not just that we have more evidence about ourselves. We have certain sorts of evidence—such as memory and inner speech—that are unavailable to others. In the terminology to be introduced below, Ryle can be seen as an early proponent of the INTERNAL PROMPTING version of ASYMMETRYe.

  4. I should say that although philosophers in the literature tend to focus on immediate justification and inferential justification, JS allows that asymmetry consists in a difference in other kinds of justification.

  5. For a survey of how widespread IMMEDIACY is among philosophers, see Carruthers (2011, pp. 17–19).

  6. On Lawlor’s view, Katherine’s self-ascription is the product of an inference about the cause of her internal promptings—Lawlor calls this route to self-knowledge “causal self-interpretation” (p. 49)—and it is justified in so far as it is the best explanation of her internal promptings.

  7. Carruthers (2011) arguably endorses INTERNAL PROMPTING as far as attitudes are concerned, even though he does not use the term “internal prompting.”

  8. Unlike Lawlor and Wikforss, Cassam has much to say about our access to our internal promptings. For discussion, see Cassam (2014, pp. 163–166).

  9. Even Cassam, who is arguably the staunchest defender of INTERNAL PROMPTING, agrees that IMMEDIACY may be plausible when it comes to “simple feelings or sensations like nausea and pain” (2014, p. 164) and occurrent thoughts (2017).

  10. Some (Dretske, 1973; Green, 2010; Cassam, 2017) argue that although we can have perceptual access to others’ minds, such access is nevertheless inferential.

  11. Dretske and Cassam later revised their views in Dretske (1973) and Cassam (2017).

  12. These are different options. You can see that your mom is angry, or see her anger, only if she is angry, but you can see her as angry even if she is not angry. Assuming that seeing that p entails believing that p, you can see that your mom is angry only if you believe that she is angry, but you can see her anger without believing that she is angry.

  13. To avoid this problem, proponents of INTERNAL PROMPTING might retreat to the following position:

    INTERNAL PROMPTING*: You can have inferential justification to believe that you are in a mental state M from your internal promptings, but others cannot have inferential justification to believe that you are in M from their internal promptings.

    Unlike INTERNAL PROMPTING, INTERNAL PROMPTING* characterizes asymmetry negatively, leaving open how others have justification to believe that you are in M.

    Proponents of INTERNAL PROMPTING* need not deny that asymmetry holds in the anger case if you have immediate access to your mom’s anger. This is so because they are not committed to the view that you can only have inferential justification to believe that your mom is angry from your observation of her behavior. However, they will leave the asymmetry in the anger case unexplained. This is so because INTERNAL PROMPTING* foregrounds cases involving inferential justification and so cannot deal with cases involving immediate justification, including the anger case. Retreating to INTERNAL PROMPTING* is therefore not a promising move.

  14. I should say that the failure of the standard versions to accommodate cases where we have immediate access to others’ minds is not their only problem. Proponents of the standard versions usually hold that we only have behavioral evidence about others’ minds. However, while behavioral evidence is important, we should not overestimate its importance. We arguably have non-behavioral evidence about others’ minds. Consider the following case. Skimming through the latest summary of new articles in my journals sent by PhilPapers, I find that your partner has a forthcoming article in a top journal. Given my background information about how much you want your partner to get published, it seems that I have justification to believe that you are happy and do so without observing your behavior.

  15. Cochrane (2021) describes this case differently. He thinks that it is Tatiana who first feels the headache and it is Krista who reports “My sister has a headache.” But note that immediately after one twin reports “My sister has a headache,” their grandfather touches Krista, and the same voice reports “Don’t touch my sister” (Pyke, 2017, 12.24–12.28). It is more likely that it is Tatiana who makes these reports. So while I agree with Cochrane that it is hard to tell from the documentary, I will stick to my description of the case.

  16. In my usage, “experience” can denote parts of single encompassing conscious states of subjects at a time. One might instead use “experience” to denote those encompassing conscious states. On this line of thought, the twins’ case needs to be restated in terms of which parts of experiences are shared. For convenience, I will stick to my usage.

  17. For other interpretations of the twins’ case, see Langland-Hassan (2015) and Cochrane (2021).

  18. I assume that one has immediate justification from one’s pains to believe that one is in pain, and that the twins are no exception to this rule. I will come back to this below.

  19. Compare the case where the twins fall while sledding. Since Tatiana feels a pain in her bottom that hurts, she has justification from her pain to believe:

    HURT 1: I feel a pain in my bottom that hurts.

    When combined with LINK, Tatiana’s pain gives her justification to believe:

    HURT 2: Krista feels a pain in my bottom that hurts.

    Krista later reports that she felt it but it did not hurt. Krista’s testimony defeats Tatiana’s justification to believe HURT 2 without defeating Tatiana’s justification to believe LINK.

  20. What the nature of the sense of mineness is and whether there is such a sense are matters of controversy. For discussion, see the papers in the special issue edited by Farrell and McClelland (2017) and Guillot and García-Carpintero (forthcoming). For a survey of cases of loss of the sense of mineness, see Klein (2015).

  21. On Klein’s (2015) view, when the twins share an experience, only the twin in whose body the experience originates is aware of it as her own. Commenting on Krista’s ability to report what Tatiana has in her hand without seeing or touching it and to point precisely with her eyes covered to the spot on Tatiana’s body where she was being touched, Klein says:

    [Krista] can correctly attribute shared experience (e.g., feeling of possession, feeling of touch) to her sister (and Tatiana can do the same). That is, the twins correctly ascribe occurrent mental states to the person in whom the states originated. [Krista] does not say “I have a toy bird” or that “I have been touched”; rather, she says that Tatiana has the toy bird and Tatiana has been touched (p. 367).

    Klein only cites Dominus (2011). But, as we saw, Pyke’s (2014; 2017) documentaries show that the twins ascribe shared experiences to themselves even when the experiences do not originate in their bodies. So it seems more plausible that when they share an experience, each is aware of it as her own, whether or not it originates in her body.

References

  • Agar, N. (2013). Truly human enhancement: A philosophical defense of limits. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, P. A. (1989). Content and self-knowledge. Philosophical Topics, 17(1), 5–26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2005). Introspection. Philosophical Topics, 33(1), 79–104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, T. (2021). Personal identity and impersonal ethics. In J. McMahan, T. Campbell, J. Goodrich, & K. Ramakrishnan (Eds.), Principles and persons: The legacy of Derek Parfit (pp. 55–84). Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2011). The opacity of mind: An integrative theory of self-knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cassam, Q. (2007). The possibility of knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cassam, Q. (2014). Self-knowledge for humans. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassam, Q. (2017). What asymmetry? Knowledge of self, knowledge of others, and the inferentialist challenge. Synthese, 194(3), 723–741

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cochrane, T. (2021). A case of shared consciousness. Synthese, 199(1), 1019–1037

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1987). Knowing one’s own mind. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 60(3): 441–458

  • Dominus, S. (2011). Could conjoined twins share a mind? The New York Times Magazine. Retrieved 11 July 2021 from https://www.nytimes.com/2011/05/29/magazine/could-conjoined-twins-share-a-mind.html

  • Douglas, T. (2013). Human enhancement and supra-personal moral status. Philosophical Studies, 162(3), 473–497

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1969). Seeing and knowing. London: Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1973). Perception and other minds. Noûs, 7(1), 34–44

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farrell, J., & McClelland, T. (Eds.). (2017). Consciousness and inner awareness. Special issue of Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 8(1): 1–180

  • Green, M. (2010). Perceiving emotions. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 84(1), 45–61

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guillot, M., & García-Carpintero, M. (Eds.). (forthcoming). The sense of mineness. Oxford: Oxford University Press

  • Hedden, B. (2019). Rationality and synchronic identity. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 97(3), 544–558

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hershenov, D. B. (2013). Who doesn’t have a problem of too many thinkers? American Philosophical Quarterly, 50(2), 203–208

    Google Scholar 

  • Javier-Castellanos, A. A. (2021). Should the number of overlapping experiencers count? Erkenntnis. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-021-00427-4

  • Klein, S. B. (2015). The feeling of personal ownership of one’s mental states: A conceptual argument and empirical evidence for an essential, but underappreciated, mechanism of mind. Psychology of Consciousness: Theory Research and Practice, 2(4), 355–376

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2017). Dignity and the phenomenology of recognition-respect. In J. Drummond, & S. Rinofner-Kreid (Eds.), Emotional experiences: Ethical and social significance (pp. 121–136). New York: Rowman & Littlefield

    Google Scholar 

  • Langland-Hassan, P. (2015). Introspective misidentification. Philosophical Studies, 172(7), 1737–1758

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawlor, K. (2009). Knowing what one wants. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79(1), 47–75

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1982). Criteria, defeasibility, and knowledge. Proceedings of the British Academy, 68, 455–479

  • McNeill, W. (2012). On seeing that someone is angry. European Journal of Philosophy, 20(4), 575–597

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. (2017). What combination problem?. In G. Brüntrup, & L. Jaskolla (Eds.), Panpsychism: Contemporary perspectives (pp. 215–228). New York: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran, R. (2001). Authority and estrangement: An essay on self-knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Pryor. J. (2014). There is immediate justification. In M. Steup, J. Turri, & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (2nd ed., pp. 202–222). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Pyke, J. (2014). Twin life: Sharing mind and body. Twin Life Productions in association with Canadian Broadcasting Company

  • Pyke, J. (2017). Inseparable: Ten years joined at the head. Curious Features in association with Canadian Broadcasting Company

  • Roelofs, L. (2019). Combining minds: How to think about composite subjectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (2009). The concept of mind (60th anniversary edition). New York: Routledge

  • Schechter, E. (2018). Self-consciousness and ‘split’ brains: The minds’ I. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. (2010). Seeing other people. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81(3), 731–748

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spaulding, S. (2015). On direct social perception. Consciousness and Cognition, 36, 472–482

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Westfall, M. (2021). Other minds are neither seen nor inferred. Synthese, 198(12), 11977–11997

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wikforss, Å. (2019). Knowledge, belief, and the asymmetry thesis. In A. Avramides & M. Parrott (Eds.), Knowing other minds (pp.41–62). Oxford: Oxford University Press

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Shaun Nichols, Derk Pereboom, Nico Silins, and two anonymous referees for their comments on earlier versions of this paper.

Funding

No funding was received to assist with the preparation of this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Shao-Pu Kang.

Ethics declarations

Competing interests:

The authors have no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kang, SP. Shared consciousness and asymmetry. Synthese 200, 413 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03890-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03890-w

Navigation