Skip to main content
Log in

Exit & isolation: Rousseau’s state of nature

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Game theory has proven useful in clarifying Hobbes’s argument that the state of nature will inevitably devolve into a state of war. Mathematically-leaning philosophers, however, have paid little attention to Rousseau’s depiction of the state of nature as a peaceful, asocial state of solitary wanderers. This paper articulates Rousseau’s critique of Hobbes in formal terms, which pinpoints two crucial issues in Hobbes’s account: the lack of an exit option and an unrealistic depiction of human nature. Building upon recent game-theoretic treatments of Hobbes, we first construct a model that incorporates Rousseau’s criticisms by permitting an exit option and (partly) endogenizing human preferences and capacities. Second, we draw out the implications of Rousseau’s analysis for the question of political authority, which cannot be answered, as Hobbes believed, by invoking a hypothetical state of nature.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. All citations to Hobbes’s (1994 [1651]) Leviathan (henceforth L).

  2. We follow Michael Huemer’s understanding of political authority as “the hypothesized moral property in virtue of which governments may coerce people in certain ways not permitted to anyone else and in virtue of which citizens must obey governments in situations in which they would not be obligated to obey anyone else” (2013, p. 5).

  3. For more careful formulations of Hobbes’s use of the state of nature for elucidating the justification of the state, see Schmidtz (1990, 95-96) and Vanderschraaf (2018, pp. 198-199).

  4. Henceforth, the Second Discourse will be abbreviated SD followed by the page number. Rousseau’s (2001) Social Contract (hercefort SC) shows the book and the chapter numbers. Translations are ours.

  5. The vague notion of “human nature” is understood here to denote preferences and capacities. For Rousseau, human nature, understood as preferences and capacities, is highly plastic. It responds to, and shapes, the environment in which human beings exist and interact.

  6. See D’Agostino et al. (2021) and Schaefer (2021).

  7. For interpretations that employ the one-shot PD, see Rawls (1999, p. 238) and Gauthier (1969, pp. 79–80).

  8. For detailed arguments against modeling the state of nature as both a finite and infinite iteration of PD, see Moehler (2009, pp. 304–307), Chung (2015), and Schaefer and Sohn (forthcoming).

  9. The symbol “≻” denotes a strict preference relation, often represented by the letter P.

  10. For a good summary, see Barrett (2020, 337-339); Schaefer and Sohn (forthcoming).

  11. Some notice that Hobbes has a more violent definition of war: “for a WAR consisteth not in battle only, or the act of fighting, but in a tract of time wherein the will to contend by battle is sufficiently known” (L 13:8). In this case, a state in which everyone cooperates with one another, but they are willing to fight with each other if the conditions change would be characterized as a state of war. Yet, in such a state, there might be industry, culture, arts, letters, etc.; even if minor events could trigger brutal war. It seems then that Hobbes uses two different definitions of war. One includes active violence; one only requires potential violence. We follow the former in this paper; the latter makes the state of war come cheap, in the sense that most civilizations in the world could be described as being in a state of war even if they live under a government.

  12. The expression “laying low” comes from Kavka (1986, p. 111).

  13. Albert Hirschman (1978, pp. 90–91) correctly notices the importance of this passage for his theory of exit. Crucial to Rousseau’s state of nature is that it assumes an exit option.

  14. For more examples, see Hirschman (1978).

  15. The outcome Isolation is actually several outcomes. It comprises any outcome where Player 1 chooses X at her first information set.

  16. The new symbol “∼” represents the indifference relation. x ∼ y if and only if x is weakly preferred to y (xRy) and vice versa (yRx).

  17. This proposition corresponds to Proposition 1.1 in the Appendix. For a formal statement and proof of this proposition, see Appendix, Sect. 1.

  18. For proof that this is, indeed, an equilibrium for low values of α, see Proposition 1.2 in Appendix.

  19. The justification for Rousseau’s revisionary account of human nature is discussed at greater length in Sect. 2.4.

  20. Rousseau thus adopts the assumption of robustness and abandons that of dependence.

  21. In the state of nature, Hobbes claims, “every man is enemy of every man [… and] men live without other security than what their own strength and their own invention shall furnish them withal” (L 13:9).

  22. And yet, Rousseau’s conjectures are inspired by actual cases of human beings that have been raised by animals: the kid of Hesse raised by wolves (found in 1344), the kid of Lithuania raised by bears (found in 1694), the kid of Hanover, and children of the Pyrenees in the eighteenth century. See SD 170n.

  23. This quote seems to be the basis of Hirschman’s (1978) reflection on the importance of exit for Rousseau.

  24. The impulse to spread into such environments results from human population growth, since otherwise less naturally fertile environments would lack appeal. As population expands, in other words, the marginal productivity of isolated hunting/gathering falls below that of more social modes, such as collective hunting and agriculture. For a formalization of this model, see Douglass North (1981, p. 75).

  25. The passage inspired the game referred to as a “stag hunt,” see Binmore (1994, pp. 120–121) and Skyrms (2003).

  26. A more complete analysis is undertaken in the Appendix, Sect. 3.

  27. See the Appendix, Proposition 2.1, for a formal proof of this claim.

  28. For a formalization and proof of this claim, as well as the claims in the following paragraph, see Proposition 2.2 in the Appendix.

  29. This claim is based on Propositions 1.1 and 2.2 in Appendix.

  30. See Proposition 2.2 and Sect. 3 in Appendix for a formal statement and proof of this claim.

  31. Alternatively, ⍴ can also represent the likelihood that a player has had extensive social interactions in the past. This alternative interpretation does not alter the logic of the model.

  32. Both simplifying assumptions are relaxed in the Appendix, Sect. 3. The logic of unraveling remains similar, but the full analysis considers s1 = EC and also endogenizes α. Put simply, by raising the average αi, socialization has a dual, mutually reinforcing effect on cooperation: it simultaneously makes Player 2 more likely to cooperate when moderate, while also making Player 1 more likely to cooperate upon entering. If the process of autocatalytic socialization continues to raise the average level of αi as ⍴ increases, then Rousseau’s account is internally consistent.

  33. See Appendix Proposition 3.3 for a formal analysis of the content presented in this paragraph.

  34. See Appendix Proposition 3.3.

References

  • Barrett, J. (2020). Punishment and disagreement in the state of nature. Economics and Philosophy, 36, 334–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binmore, K. (1994). Game theory and the social contract: Volume 1, playing fair. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chung, H. (2015). Hobbes’s state of nature: A modern Bayesian game-theoretic analysis. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 1(3), 485–508.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Agostino, F., Gaus, G., & Thrasher, J. (2021). "Contemporary approaches to the social contract", The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter Edition). In: Edward N. Zalta (ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/contractarianism-contemporary/.

  • Gauthier, D. (1969). The logic of leviathan. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Hampton, J. (1986). Hobbes and the social contract tradition. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, J. (2017). The secret of our success: How culture is driving human evolution, domesticating our species, and making us smarter. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirschman, A. O. (1978). Exit, voice, and the state. World Politics, 31(1), 90–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, T. (1994). Leviathan, edited by E. Curley. Hackett.

  • Huemer, M. (2013). The problem of political authority: An examination of the right to coerce and the duty to obey. Palgrave-Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kavka, G. S. (1983). Hobbes’s war of all against all. Ethics, 93(2), 291–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kavka, G. S. (1986). Hobbesian moral and political theory. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moehler, M. (2009). Why Hobbes’ state of nature is best modelled by an assurance game. Utilitas, 21(3), 297–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • North, D. (1981). Structure and change in economic history. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice (Revised Edition). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Rousseau, J.-J. (1971). Discours sur l’Origine et les Fondements de l’Inégalité parmi les Hommes. GF Flammarion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, J.-J. (2001). Du Contrat Social. GF Flammarion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaefer, A. (2021). Rationality, uncertainty, and unanimity: An epistemic critique of contractarianism. Economics and Philosophy, 37, 82–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaefer, A., & Sohn, J. Forthcoming. Unraveling into war: Trust and social preferences in Hobbes’s state of nature. Economics and Philosophy: 1–35.

  • Schmidtz, D. (1990). Justifying the state. Ethics, 1010(1), 89–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (2003). The stag hunt and the evolution of social structure. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vanderschraaf, P. (2006). War or peace: A dynamical analysis of anarchy. Economics and Philosophy, 22, 243–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanderschraaf, P. (2018). Strategic justice: Conventions and problems of balancing divergent interests. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors are thankful to the editors of this volume and two anonymous reviewers, whose acute comments and useful guidance were fundamental for improving this paper substantially. We also thank Jacob Barrett, Matt Jeffers, Otto Lehto, Alexandra Oprea, David Schmidtz, Peter Vanderschraaf, and Matt Zwolinski for their help and support during the writing of this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mario I. Juarez-Garcia.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Supplementary Information

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

Supplementary file1 (PDF 224 kb)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Juarez-Garcia, M.I., Schaefer, A. Exit & isolation: Rousseau’s state of nature. Synthese 200, 252 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03736-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03736-5

Keywords

Navigation