Skip to main content
Log in

Discursive habits: a representationalist re-reading of teleosemiotics

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Enactivism has influentially argued that the traditional intellectualist ‘act-content’ model of intentionality is insufficient both phenomenologically and naturalistically, and minds are built from world-involving bodily habits—thus, knowledge should be regarded as more of a skilled performance than an informational encoding. Radical enactivists have assumed that this insight must entail non-representationalism concerning at least basic minds. But what if it could be shown that representation is itself a form of skilled performance? I sketch the outline of such an account from the perspective of Peirce’s pragmatist semiotics, which theorises signs as habits of associating specific cues with appropriate acts and schemas of ensuing experience. Within this framework, I argue, a naturalistic account of propositional structure can be constructed which transcends the symbolic—and in some instances even the linguistic—sphere, and offers new insights regarding the Information Processing Challenge, and the Hard Problem of Content.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. ‘Commodified’ is of course an economic metaphor. But it is arguably not out of place—and has previously been explicitly mobilised—in these philosophical debates. For example: “…information is a prime commodity, and when it is used in biological theorizing it is granted a kind of atomistic autonomy as it moves from place to place, is gathered, stored, imprinted, and translated…” (Oyama, 2000, p. 1, cited in Hutto, 2011a, p. 50).

  2. They were being challenged even earlier in the pragmatist tradition, which it appears that Ryle may have covertly drawn on (Legg & Black, 2020).

  3. See (Thompson, 2007, pp. 128–129) for a useful overview.

  4. It should be noted that a somewhat more complex definitional picture of content is offered in (Hutto, 2011a, p. 54), where he appears to sketch more of a family resemblance account: “Content, it seems, is a bit like Christmas: it can come without truth conditions, without concepts, without intensionality (with an ‘s’), without semantics, without mentality….”.

  5. It’s worth emphasising that not all enactivists are anti-representationalist. Others hold that representation survives in modified form, but must be understood as fundamentally ‘action-oriented’ (Clark, 2015, 2016; Noë 2004; Wheeler, 2005). This fundamental disagreement has led to a series of “representation wars” (Clark, 2015). My focus here, however, is on the anti-representationalist position of radical enactivism.

  6. The qualifier ‘skilled’ is important here, because otherwise the concept of ‘performance’ might seem too mechanical, basic or repetitive to constitute a form of intelligence. I am grateful to an anonymous referee for this point.

  7. There is an interesting lineage in the background here—not irrelevant to this paper—insofar as Millikan was a student of Charles Morris, an early interpreter of Peirce’s semiotics for mainstream philosophy. Nöth argues, however, that both the scope of her semantics and her understanding of its teleology, were considerably narrower than Peirce’s (Nöth, 2014, pp. 186–188). This will be discussed further below in Sects. 5 and 6.

  8. See also (Hutto, 2011a, p. 59).

  9. References to Peirce’s Collected Papers are formatted as ‘CP’ followed by the book and remark number, as per convention in Peirce scholarship. I have added the date of Peirce’s authorship where possible.

  10. A particularly comprehensive and clear early account is (Hookway, 1985).

  11. An honourable exception here is (Fanaya, 2020). Although Fanaya does fine work connecting Peirce’s pragmatic account of meaning with enactivism, through emphasising their mutual “embodied dynamicism”, and resulting mind–body continuity, she does not explicitly analyse a hypothetical conditional structure as I do here. She does also push back against anti-representationalist tendencies in enactivism, although her target is autopoietic enactivism, rather than the radical enactivism discussed here.

  12. Peirce’s terminology for this most basic distinction in his semiotics underwent significant evolution across his lifetime—from early days where he used ‘representation’ to mean ‘sign’ (as above) and ‘sign’ to mean ‘index’, to 1902 where he used ‘sign’ to designate specifically human semiosis, to 1905–1906 where he used ‘representation’ to mean ‘any sign not an index’. His understanding of representation also increasingly expanded into a broader metaphysical account of ‘mediation’ (Nöth, 2011). But despite these terminological shifts, Peirce’s claim that signification is an irreducibly triadic relation, and his distinction between iconic, indexical and symbolic functioning are remarkably stable throughout his career.

  13. For a systematic overview of this fundamental triad in Peirce’s sign theory, see (Liszka, 1996).

  14. For insightful commentary on Peirce’s deployment of this metaphor in his philosophical system, see (Hookway, 2002, 2012).

  15. For a discussion of the implications of this claim within formal logic, see (Legg, 2012).

  16. Again, these ideas are discussed further in (Legg & Black, 2020).

  17. It’s worth noting that Stjernfelt goes on to criticise some of Hurford’s work as psychologistic in the hard-fought sense of Frege and Peirce—for instance where Hurford states that the “…logico-linguistic enterprise is essentially psychological” (Hurford, 2007, p. 124, cited in Stjernfelt, 2014, p. 127).

  18. Other relevant sources include (Gładziejewski & Miłkowski, 2017; O’Brien & Opie, 2015; Shea, 2014).

  19. I believe this quote puts to rest the two major objections which Segundo-Ortin and Hutto present as an explicit counter-argument to Williams and Colling’s piece—that icons do not inherently represent what they are taken to represent, and that they do not play a casual role in cognition in virtue of their content (Segundo-Ortin & Hutto, 2021, pp. S9–S10).

References

  • Alborn, T. (1989). Peirce’s evolutionary logic: Continuity, indeterminacy, and the natural order. Transactions of the Charles s. Peirce Society, 25(1), 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruineberg, J., Chemero, A., & Rietveld, E. (2019). General ecological information supports engagement with affordances for ‘higher’ cognition. Synthese, 196(12), 5231–5251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, W. (2019). Skilled action. Philosophy Compass, 14(11), e12631.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2015). Predicting peace: The end of the representation wars. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND 7:R. MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2016). Surfing uncertainty: Prediction, action, and the embodied mind. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fanaya, P. F. (2020). Autopoietic enactivism: Action and representation re-examined under Peirce’s light. Synthese (forthcoming).

  • Gallagher, S., & Miyahara, K. (2012). Neo-pragmatism and enactive intentionality. In Action, perception and the brain (pp. 117–146). Palgrave Macmillan.

  • Gallagher, S., & Aguda, B. (2020). Anchoring know-how: Action, affordance and anticipation. Journal of Consciousness Studies (forthcoming).

  • Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist interventions: Rethinking the mind. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gładziejewski, P., & Miłkowski, M. (2017). Structural representations: Causally relevant and different from detectors. Biology and Philosophy, 32(3), 337–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1996). Spencer and Dewey on life and mind. In M. Boden (Ed.), The philosophy of artificial life (pp. 314–331). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hookway, C. (1985). Peirce. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hookway, C. (2002). ‘…A sort of composite photograph’: Pragmatism, ideas, and schematism. Transactions of the Charles s. Peirce Society, 38(1/2), 29–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hookway, C. (2012). The pragmatic maxim: Essays on Peirce and pragmatism. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hurford, J. (2007). The origin of meaning. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. (2011a). Philosophy of mind’s new lease on life: Autopoietic enactivism meets teleosemiotics. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 18(5–6), 44–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. (2011b). Enactivism: Why be radical? Sehen Und Handeln, 1, 21–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. (2015). Overly enactive imagination? Radically re-imagining imagining. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 53, 68–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2017). Evolving enactivism: Basic minds meet content. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Robertson, I. (2020). Clarifying the character of habits: Understanding what and how they explain. In F. Caruna & I. Testa (Eds.), Habit: Pragmatist approaches from cognitive neurosciences to social sciences. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Satne, G. (2015). The natural origins of content. Philosophia, 43(3), 521–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Legg, C., & Black, J. (2020). What is intelligence for? A Peircean pragmatist response to the knowing-how, knowing-that debate. Erkenntnis (forthcoming).

  • Legg, C. (2008). The problem of the essential icon. American Philosophical Quarterly, 45(3), 207–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Legg, C. (2012). The hardness of the iconic must: Can Peirce’s existential graphs assist modal epistemology? Philosophia Mathematica, 20(1), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liszka, J. J. (1996). A general introduction to the semiotic of Charles Sanders Peirce. Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miyahara, K. (2011). Neo-pragmatic intentionality and enactive perception: A compromise between extended and enactive minds. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 10(4), 499–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nöth, W. (2011). From representation to thirdness and representamen to medium: Evolution of Peircean key terms and topics. Transactions of the Charles s. Peirce Society, 47(4), 445–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nöth, W. (2014). The growth of signs. Σημειωτκή-Sign Systems Studies, 42(2–3), 172–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, G., & Opie, J. (2015). Intentionality lite or analog content? Philosophia, 43(3), 723–729.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1998). in N. Houser, & C. Kloesel (Eds.), Essential Peirce, vol. 2: Selected philosophical writings (1893–1913). Indiana University Press.

  • Peirce, C. S. (1931–1958). in C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss, & A. Burks (Eds.), Collected papers, 8 vols. Harvard.

  • Rosenthal, S. (1982). Meaning as habit: Some systematic implications of Peirce’s pragmatism. The Monist, 65(2), 230–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, S. (1994). Charles Peirce’s pragmatic pluralism. SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1946). Knowing how and knowing that. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 46, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Segundo-Ortin, M., & Hutto, D. (2021). Similarity-based cognition: Radical enactivism meets cognitive neuroscience. Synthese, 198(Suppl 1), S5–S32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea, N. (2014). Exploitable isomorphism and structural representation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 114(2ii), 123–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt, F. (2014). Natural propositions: The actuality of Peirce’s doctrine of dicisigns. Docent Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt, F. (2015). Dicisigns. Synthese, 192(4), 1019–1054.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt, F. (2016). Dicisigns and habits: Implicit propositions and habit-taking in Peirce’s pragmatism. In D. West & M. Anderson (Eds.), Consensus on Peirce’s concept of habit: Before and beyond consciousness (pp. 241–262). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology and the Sciences of Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (1997). Cognition’s coming home: The reunion of life and mind. In P. Husbands & I. Harvey (Eds.), Proceedings of the 4th European conference on artificial life (pp. 10–19). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the cognitive world: The next step. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, D., & Colling, L. (2018). From symbols to icons: The return of resemblance in the cognitive neuroscience revolution. Synthese, 195(5), 1941–1967.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, M. (2002). Six views of embodied cognition. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 9(4), 625–636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Catherine Legg.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

In formulating the ideas of this paper, I’m indebted to workshops and discussions with Katsunori Miyahara, Glenda Satne, Ian Robertson, Daniel Hutto, Shaun Gallagher, Jack Reynolds, Marilyn Stendera and Ross Pain.

This article belongs to the topical collection "Minds in Skilled Performance", edited by Katsunori Miyahara, Ian Robertson and Michael Kirchhof.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Legg, C. Discursive habits: a representationalist re-reading of teleosemiotics. Synthese 199, 14751–14768 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03442-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03442-8

Keywords

Navigation