Skip to main content
Log in

Logic as a methodological discipline

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This essay offers a conception of logic by which logic may be considered to be exceptional among the sciences on the backdrop of a naturalistic outlook. The conception of logic focused on emphasises the traditional role of logic as a methodology for the sciences, which distinguishes it from other sciences that are not methodological. On the proposed conception, the methodological aims of logic drive its definitions and principles, rather than the description of scientific phenomena. The notion of a methodological discipline is explained as a relation between disciplines or practices. Logic serves as a methodological discipline with respect to any theoretical practice, and this generality, as well as logic’s reflexive nature, distinguish it from other methodological disciplines. Finally, the evolution of model theory is taken as a case study, with a focus on its methodological role. Following recent work by John Baldwin and Juliette Kennedy, we look at model theory from its inception in the mid-twentieth century as a foundational endeavour until developments at the end of the century, where the classification of theories has taken centre-stage.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Though we might consider here a broad conception of science, as any organised area of inquiry or body of truths [this, arguably, is Frege’s use of the term “science”, see Frege (1979, p. 168) and Rossberg and Shapiro 2021].

  2. This is not to say that none of the views of logic expressed by Frege are accepted by anti-exceptionalists, e.g., that the generality of logic is its defining feature is accepted by Williamson. See also Rossberg and Shapiro (2021) for anti-exceptionalist proclamations made by Frege.

  3. The same may be true about the apriority and analyticity of logic, but I leave that issue aside.

  4. Recall that “science” here and for Frege is used with the broadest meaning, see f.n. 1.

  5. For example, see Carnap’s description of the aims of The Logical Syntax of Language (Carnap 1934/1937) as instrumental:

    The aim of logical syntax is to provide a system of concepts, a language, by the help of which the results of logical analysis will be exactly formuable... the logic of science is nothing other than the logical syntax of the language of science (p. xiii)

    The logic of science (logical methodology) is nothing else than the syntax of the logic of science. (p. 7)

  6. A notable example is Gila Sher, who offers the following thesis in her recent book:

    Thesis 1: Function (Task) of Logic

    Logic’s task is to develop a method of inference which is both highly general and has an especially strong modal force. More specifically, its task is to develop a method for constructing inferences that transmit truth from sentences to sentences with an especially strong modal force and regardless of field of knowledge. ((Sher 2016, p. 255), boldface added).

    Sher is a proponent of foundational holism, by which knowledge is grounded in reality, but there need not be a strict ordering for grounding. So logic’s methodological role is separated from traditional foundationalism, an approach shared by contemporary model-theorists, as we’ll see in Sect. 4.

  7. For example, while Carnap and Tarski define logical properties and relations with respect to linguistic expressions, for Frege, and these days, Williamson, Sher and Maddy, logic is not primarily metalinguistic. But the disputes on whether logic operates on the level of linguistic expression or of mental content is an ancient one, see for example Adamson and Key (2015).

  8. See also Rossberg and Shapiro (2021), who contrast Priest’s methods with those of contemporary linguistics.

  9. Hjortland and Martin write that according to their account, “logical theories are ultimately chosen for their ability to make successful predictions. Such predictions include claims about which informal proofs mathematicians will find acceptable, and which arguments certain “reliable reasoners” will judge acceptable.” (Martin and Hjortland 2020).

    Later on they note that “in suggesting that logical theories appeal to judgements regarding arguments, the current proposal opens up the possibility that a priori evidence does indeed play a role within logical theory choice” (ibid). Now one might question whether a theory based on the collection of judgments elicited from selected subjects, using whatever method of survey available (as opposed to an armchair activity), might thus be a priori. Compare soliciting judgments from mathematicians on the truth of mathematical theorems: while this may be a reliable procedure for determining theoremhood, the type of justification that would base the apriority of mathematics would be the proofs of these theorems themselves. (See Malmgren 2006, who argues against the claim that there is a priori knowledge by testimony, and whose arguments apply to the present case as well.)

  10. Priest is an exception in basing logic on norms for correct reasoning, see also Sect. 3.

  11. In this way anti-exceptionalists rule out customary locutions in logical theories such as “from... infer...” or “from... one may infer...”. I thank Ran Lanzet for this comment.

  12. This issue was recently discussed by Sebastian Lutz, according to whom: “Since the sciences rely on language conventions whenever they go beyond observational claims, most entities and properties referred to by scientific theories (for instance momentum) are introduced rather than discovered” (Lutz 2020).

  13. For a rigorous presentation on the application of logical systems, see Avron (1994).

  14. Carnap (1962) distinguishes between the task of the logician (in that case, the inductive logician)—to calculate the value of a confirmation function, and the methodologist is in charge of applications of inductive logic. Here I take a wider view of the methodologist’s role: it includes both the logician’s theoretical work and its application (in this I follow Nola and Sankey 2014, pp. 30f).

  15. While at the first level we may have non-methodological disciplines, the methodological disciplines may not be neatly divided into levels higher up.

  16. Here I should emphasise that I am setting foundational issues aside, so that by logic applying to itself we do not commit to a vicious regress. The blacksmith’s first production might be manufactured using unforged steel or a steel-free device, and tools made out of forged steel can be manufactured and put into use at some point nonetheless. We don’t have the artifactual tools from the start, but this doesn’t mean that they appear ex nihilo–we use more rudimentary tools to forge the first instances (for details and discussion see Peregrin and Svoboda 2017). Notwithstanding, for the limitations of logic applying to itself in theoretical decisions such as choice of logic, see Woods (2019).

  17. Model-theoretic semantics is used in abundance in the Montagovian tradition in formal semantics (Montague 1974; Westerståhl 1989; Chierchia and McConnell-Ginet 1990; Heim and Kratzer 1998). For an overview of model theory in computer science, see Makowsky (1995). For an overview of the applications of model theory in philosophy, see Button and Walsh (2018).

  18. Tarski juxtaposes logical and geometrical notions already in Lindenbaum and Tarski (1935), but there syntactic aspects are prominent.

  19. Baldwin discusses the nature of classification and definition in Baldwin (2018, ch. 13). For a brief discussion on the philosophical aspects of classification, see also Button and Walsh (2018).

References

  • Adamson, P., & Key, A. (2015). Philosophy of language in the medieval Arabic tradition. Linguistic Meaning: New Essays in the History of the Philosophy of Language), Ch. 4, 74–99.

  • Avron, A. (1994). What is a logical system? In D. Gabbay (Ed.), What is a logical system? (pp. 217–238). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin, J. T. (2018). Model theory and the philosophy of mathematical practice: Formalization without foundationalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bobzien, S. (2020). Ancient Logic. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2020 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/logic-ancient/

  • Broome, J. (1999). Normative requirements. Ratio, 12(4), 398–419.

    Google Scholar 

  • Button, T., & Walsh, S. (2018). Philosophy and model theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1934/1937). The logical syntax of language. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

  • Carnap, R. (1950). Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4, 20–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1962). Logical foundations of probability (2nd ed.). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1967) The logical structure of the world, George, R.A. (tran.), Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

  • Chierchia, G., & McConnell-Ginet, S. (1990). Meaning and grammar. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic structures. The Hague: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1967). Truth and meaning. Synthese, 17(3), 304–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (2008). Semantics for natural languages. In S. Nuccetelli & G. Seay (Eds.), Philosophy of language: The central topics (pp. 57–63). Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2015). What is logical validity? In C. Caret & O. Hjortland (Eds.), Foundations of logical consequence (pp. 33–70). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franks, C. (2009). The autonomy of mathematical knowledge: Hilbert’s program revisited. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1897). Logic. In Posthumous writings. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1915). My basic logical insights. Posthumous writings (pp. 251–252). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1956). The thought: A logical inquiry. Mind, 65(259), 289–311.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1967). Begriffsschrift. In J. van Heijenoort (Ed.), From Frege to Gödel (pp. 1–82). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1979). Posthumous writings. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1980). The foundations of arithmetic: A logico-mathematical enquiry into the concept of number. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldfarb, W. (2010). Frege’s conception of logic. In The Cambridge companion to Frege. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack, S. (1995). Science is neither sacred nor a confidence trick. Foundations of Science, 1(3), 323–335.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1972). Deep structure as logical form. In D. Davidson & G. Harman (Eds.), Semantics of natural language (pp. 25–47). Dordrecht-Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1984). Logic and reasoning. Synthese, 60, 107–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1986). Change in view: Principles of reasoning. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I., & Kratzer, A. (1998). Semantics in generative grammar. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hjortland, O. T. (2017). Anti-exceptionalism about logic. Philosophical Studies, 174(3), 631–658.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hjortland, O. T. (2019). What counts as evidence for a logical theory? The Australasian Journal of Logic, 16(7), 250–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hlobil, U. (2020). Limits of abductivism about logic. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12707.

  • Hodges, W. (2018). A short history of model theory. In T. Button & S. Walsh (Eds.), Philosophy and model theory (pp. 439–476). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hrushovski, E. (1996). The Mordell-Lang conjecture for function fields. Journal of the American mathematical society, 9(3), 667–690.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, J. (2021). Gödel, Tarski and the lure of natural language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kneale, W., & Kneale, M. (1962). The development of logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1990). Normative naturalism. Philosophy of Science, 57(1), 44–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindenbaum, A., & Tarski, A. (1935). On the limitations of the means of expression of deductive theories. In J. Corcoran (Ed.), Logic, semantics, metamathematics (pp. 384–392). Indianapolis: Hackett (1983).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lutz, S. (2020). Armchair philosophy naturalized. Synthese, 197(3), 1099–1125.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2002). Frege, Kant, and the logic in logicism. The Philosophical Review, 111(1), 25–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2004). Inwhat sense (if any) is logic normative for thought? Manuscript. https://johnmacfarlane.net/normativity_of_logic.pdf

  • Maddy, P. (2002). A naturalistic look at logic. In Proceedings and addresses of the American Philosophical Association, Vol. 76, pp. 61–90.

  • Maddy, P. (2014). A second philosophy of logic. In P. Rush (Ed.), The metaphysics of logic (pp. 93–108). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makowsky, J. (1995). The impact of model theory on theoretical computer science. In Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics (Vol. 134, pp. 239–262). Elsevier.

  • Malmgren, A.-S. (2006). Is there a priori knowledge by testimony? The Philosophical Review, 115(2), 199–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manders, K. L. (1987). Logic and conceptual relationships in mathematics. In Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics (Vol. 122, pp. 193–211). Elsevier.

  • Martin, B., & Hjortland, O. T. (2020). Logical predictivism. Journal of Philosophical Logic,. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-020-09566-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1974). Formal philosophy (R. Thomason, Ed.). New Haven: Yale University Press.

  • Nola, R., & Sankey, H. (2014). Theories of scientific method: An introduction. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peregrin, J., & Svoboda, V. (2017). Reflective equilibrium and the principles of logical analysis: Understanding the laws of logic. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2006). Doubt truth to be a liar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2016). Logical disputes and the a priori. Princípios: Revista de Filosofia., 23(40), 29–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Carnap and logical truth. Synthese, 12(4), 350–374.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Epistemology naturalized. Ontological relativity and other essays (pp. 69–90). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. (2001). Brandom on modality, normativity and intentionality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63(3), 611–623.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rossberg, M. & Shapiro, S. (2021). Logic and science: science and logic. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03076-w

  • Russell, G. (2020). Logic isn’t normative. Inquiry, 63(3–4), 371–388.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelah, S. (2009). Classification theory for abstract elementary classes. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (2016). Epistemic friction. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stei, E. (2020). Non-normative logical pluralism and the revenge of the normativity objection. The Philosophical Quarterly, 70(278), 162–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinberger, F. (2017). Frege and Carnap on the normativity of logic. Synthese, 194(1), 143–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinberger, F. (2019). Three ways in which logic might be normative. The Journal of Philosophy, 116(1), 5–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. (1936). On the concept of logical consequence. In J. Corcoran (Ed.), Logic, semantics, metamathematics (pp. 409–420). Indianapolis: Hackett (1983).

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. (1941). Introduction to logic and to the methodology of the deductive sciences. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. (1956). Fundamental concepts of the methodology of the deductive sciences. Logic, semantics, metamathematics (pp. 60–109). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. (1956a). Fundamental concepts of the methodology of the deductive sciences. Logic, semantics, metamathematics (pp. 30–37). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. (1956b). On definable sets of real numbers. Logic, semantics, metamathematics (pp. 110–142). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. (1986). What are logical notions? History and Philosophy of Logic, 7(2), 143–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Benthem, J. J. (2008). Logic and reasoning: Do the facts matter? Studia Logica, 88(1), 67–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van den Dries, L. (1998). Tame topology and o-minimal structures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westerståhl, D. (1989). Quantifiers in formal and natural languages. In Handbook of philosophical logic, Vol IV (pp. 1–131). Springer.

  • Williamson, T. (2017). Semantic paradoxes and abductive methodology. Reflections on the Liar, Ch. 13, 325–346.

  • Woods, J. (2019). Logical partisanhood. Philosophical Studies, 176(5), 1203–1224.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yaghmaie, A. (2017). How to characterise pure and applied science. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 31(2), 133–149.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gil Sagi.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This article belongs to the topical collection “Anti-Exceptionalism about Logic”, edited by Ben Martin, Maria Paola Sforza Fogliani, and Filippo Ferrari.

This paper was presented to the London Group for Formal Philosophy and the Jerusalem Working Group in Logic. I’d like to thank the members of both groups for a useful discussion. I’d also like to thank the following for helpful comments: Tim Button, Rea Golan, Balthasar Grabmayr, Catherine Herfeld, David Kashtan, Juliette Kennedy, Arnon Keren, Aviv Keren, Ran Lanzet, Talia Leven, Carlo Nicolai, Filippos Papagiannopoulos, Lavinia Picollo, Carl Posy, Daniel Statman and Florian Steinberger.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sagi, G. Logic as a methodological discipline. Synthese 199, 9725–9749 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03223-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03223-3

Keywords

Navigation