Skip to main content
Log in

If consciousness causes collapse, the zombie argument fails

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many non-physicalists, including Chalmers, hold that the zombie argument succeeds in rejecting the physicalist view of consciousness. Some non-physicalists, including, again, Chalmers, hold that quantum collapse interactionism (QCI), i.e., the idea that non-physical consciousness causes collapse of the wave function in phenomena such as quantum measurement, is a viable interactionist solution for the problem of the relationship between the physical world and the non-physical consciousness. In this paper, I argue that if QCI is true, the zombie argument fails. In particular, I show that if QCI is true, a zombie world physically identical to our world is impossible because there is at least one law of nature, a fundamental law of physics in particular, that exist only in the zombie world but not in our world. This shows that philosophers like Chalmers are committing an error in endorsing the zombie argument and QCI at the same time.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Different versions of the zombie argument can be found in the literature—for an extensive list, see (Kirk 2015). Here, I focus on Chalmers (1996, pp. 94–99, 2003, pp. 105–106, 2010).

  2. There are several proposals about the relationship between consciousness and quantum physics. Two interesting summaries reflecting the diversity of these proposals can be found in Atmanspacher (2017) and Pylkkänen (2018). It should be mentioned that some of these proposals are physicalist. Penrose (1989, 1994), for instance, aims to explain consciousness in terms of quantum physics in general and collapse of the wave function in particular.

  3. It should be mentioned that not all interpretations of quantum mechanics are “collapse interpretations.” For instance, Everett’s many-worlds interpretation and Bohm’s hidden variables interpretation do not embrace collapse. Moreover, QCI is only one of the collapse interpretations—and not a very popular one (Schlosshauer et al. 2013). For instance, Ghirardi–Rimini–Weber (GRW) theory of spontaneous collapse is also a collapse interpretation but consciousness plays no role in it.

  4. The physical correlates of consciousness (PCC) in a zombie is the part of her brain that if she was her human twin, her consciousness would nomologically supervene on it.

  5. Woodward (2005, pp. 208–209), for instance, argues that “Nothing can travel faster than the speed of light” is not a causal explanation for the subluminal speed of an electron (cf. Skow 2014, pp. 455–457).

  6. As noted by many, whether or not a claim receives confirmation from evidence is always sensitive to the background beliefs (see, for instance, Lange 2000, p. 112; Sober 1988, p. 19). If we adopt representationalism, zombies cannot have beliefs because beliefs are some kind of mental state. Therefore, they cannot really confirm their beliefs. But since, ex hypothesi, zombie’s behavior perfectly resembles their human counterparts, here I adopt the dispositionalist view of belief according to which beliefs should be understood in terms of behavioral dispositions. For more on this distinction, see Schwitzgebel (2019).

  7. The example is from Lange (2017, p. 6).

  8. It is worth mentioning that some hold that even in the course of our world’s history, laws of nature change and evolve (Peirce 1891; Smolin 2013).

References

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1983). What is a law of nature?. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Atmanspacher, H. (2017). Quantum approaches to brain and mind. In S. Schneider & M. Velmans (Eds.), The Blackwell companion to consciousness (pp. 298–313). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (1998). Philosophy of science. London: UCL Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2018). Searching for non-causal explanations in a sea of causes. In A. Reutlinger & J. Saatsi (Eds.), Explanation beyond causation: Philosophical perspectives on non-causal explanations (pp. 141–163). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1999). Materialism and the metaphysics of modality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 59(2), 473–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2003). Consciousness and its place in nature. In S. P. Stich & T. A. Warfield (Eds.), Blackwell guide to the philosophy of mind (pp. 102–142). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2004). Imagination, indexicality, and intensions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 68(1), 182–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2010). The two-dimensional argument against materialism. In The character of consciousness (pp. 141–205). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Chalmers, D. J., & McQueen, K. J. (forthcoming). Consciousness and the collapse of the wave functions. In S. Gao (Ed.), Consciousness and quantum mechanic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Dretske, F. I. (1977). Laws of nature. Philosophy of Science, 44(2), 248–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1986). What Mary didn’t know. The Journal of Philosophy, 83(5), 291–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirk, R. (2015). Zombies. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (summer 2015.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved October 26, 2017, from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/zombies/.

  • Lange, M. (2000). Natural laws in scientific practice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2017). Because without cause: Non-causal explanation in science and mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (Ed.). (1986). Causal explanation. In Philosophical papers (Vol. 2, pp. 214–240). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Loewer, B. (1996). Humean supervenience. Philosophical Topics, 24(1), 101–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • London, F., & Bauer, E. (1983). The theory of observation in quantum mechanics. In J. A. Wheeler & W. H. Zurek (Eds.), Quantum theory and measurement (pp. 217–259). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1891). The architecture of theories. The Monist, 1(2), 161–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1989). The emperor’s new mind: Concerning computers, minds, and the laws of physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1994). Shadows of the mind: A search for the missing science of consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (2001). Knowledge, possibility, and consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (2012). Return of the zombies? In S. Gozzano & C. S. Hill (Eds.), New perspectives on type identity: The mental and the physical (pp. 251–263). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pylkkänen, P. (2018). Quantum theories of consciousness. In R. J. Gennaro & P. Pylkkänen (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of consciousness (pp. 216–231). New York: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schlosshauer, M. (2007). Decoherence and the quantum-to-classical transition. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlosshauer, M., Kofler, J., & Zeilinger, A. (2013). A snapshot of foundational attitudes toward quantum mechanics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44(3), 222–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2019). Belief. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (fall 2019.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved December 3, 2019, from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/belief/.

  • Skow, B. (2014). Are there non-causal explanations (of particular events)? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65(3), 445–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smolin, L. (2013). Time reborn: From the crisis in physics to the future of the universe. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1988). Confirmation and law-likeness. The Philosophical Review, 97(1), 93–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stapp, H. (2001). Quantum theory and the role of mind in nature. Foundations of Physics, 31(10), 1465–1499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stapp, H. (2007). Quantum mechanical theories of consciousness. In S. Schneider & M. Velmans (Eds.), The Blackwell companion to consciousness (pp. 300–312). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tononi, G. (2008). Consciousness as integrated information: A provisional manifesto. The Biological Bulletin, 215(3), 216–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tononi, G., Boly, M., Massimini, M., & Koch, C. (2016). Integrated information theory: From consciousness to its physical substrate. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 17(7), 450–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (1977). The nature of laws. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 7(4), 667–698.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (1987). Causation: A realist approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann, J. (2018). Mathematical foundations of quantum mechanics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. P. (1961). Remarks on the mind-body question. In I. J. Good (Ed.), The scientist speculates (pp. 168–181). London: Basic Books.  

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. P. (1964). Two kinds of reality. The Monist, 48(2), 248–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2005). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2018). Some varieties of non-causal explanation. In A. Reutlinger & J. Saatsi (Eds.), Explanation beyond causation: Philosophical perspectives on non-causal explanations (pp. 117–138). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgment

I am grateful to Andrew Brenner, Joshua Barthuly, Liz Jackson, Sebastian Murgueitio Ramirez, Jeff Speaks, and the anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments and suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mousa Mohammadian.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mohammadian, M. If consciousness causes collapse, the zombie argument fails. Synthese 199, 1599–1615 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02828-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02828-4

Keywords

Navigation