Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

A new perspective on the relationship between metacognition and social cognition: metacognitive concepts as socio-cognitive tools

  • Folk Psychology: Pluralistic Approaches
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I defend an alternative to the two traditional accounts of the relationship between metacognition and social cognition: metacognition as primary versus social cognition as primary. These accounts have complementary explanatory vices and virtues. They also share a natural assumption: that interpretation in terms of mental states is “spectatorial”, aiming exclusively for an objective description of the mental facts about self and others. I argue that if one rejects this assumption in favor of the view that interpretation in terms of mental states also plays important regulative roles with respect to minds and behavior, a new and superior conception of the relationship between metacognition and social cognition comes into view. On this conception, person-level metacognitive concepts are socio-cognitive tools that shape us into better cognitive agents and more predictable cognitive objects, thereby enhancing our abilities at social coordination. Mastery of these metacognitive concepts relies on subpersonal, non-conceptual, procedural metacognition. This reconceptualization of the relationship between metacognition and social cognition combines the complementary explanatory virtues of the two traditional conceptions, while avoiding their complementary explanatory vices.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Although Moore does not think of this form of interpretation as “sub-personal”, but, rather, as an “unreflective and undemanding personal level” phenomenon. (personal communication).

  2. See McGeer (2015, p. 266, 271) for a similar point.

  3. I thank Richard Moore for the objection and the examples.

  4. What about MP? Recall that one of its main advantages over SP is that it does not require knowledge of generalizations linking mental states to their observable triggers and consequences. It is true that MP versions of SC do not succumb to this objection. However, they face another problem: given inter-individual cognitive and motivational variability, MP, on its own, cannot explain the reliability of interpretation. This is a problem because, if interpretation is not reliable, it is hard to see how it could perform descriptive and predictive functions. Of course, as many proponents of MP argue, perhaps there is sufficient inter-individual similarity to support reliable interpretation (Goldman 1989). However, the evidence from Barrett (2017) regarding emotions, and from Lillard (1998) and Vinden (1999) regarding cross-cultural variation, suggests that, to the extent that there is such inter-individual similarity, it is the product of regulative functions of interpretation.

  5. We see a similar dynamic in games and sports. By learning chess, one not only gains new tools for understanding and predicting other chess players, one also becomes easier to understand and predict by other chess players (McGeer 2015, pp. 261–262).

  6. For a congenial discussion, see McGeer (2015, pp. 265–267).

  7. For an anticipation of this idea, see Nietzsche (1881/1997, pp. 26–27).

  8. See McGeer (2015, pp. 261–267) for an insightful discussion of such “folk psychological know-how or expertise”.

  9. This is not to suggest that such socially inflected, procedural metacognition is sufficient for learning how to use words like “sad”. All language-learning requires, in addition, enormously complex socio-cognitive machinery that enables the kinds of pragmatic inferences by means of which language learners infer the intended messages of their interlocutors. Richard Moore, whom I thank for raising this point in response to an earlier draft, has argued (2017, 2018) that such Gricean mechanisms needn’t involve sophisticated metacognitive concepts, of the kind we use in person-level, reflective, and language-involving interpretation. For example, he argues that non-humans and human infants can engage in Gricean forms of communication without a concept of belief or the ability to attribute recursively nested mental states.

References

  • Andrews, K. (2008). It’s in your nature: A pluralistic folk psychology. Synthese, 165, 13–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, L. (2012). Emotions are real. Emotion, 12, 413–429.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, L. (2017). How emotions are made. New York: Houghton, Mifflin, Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butterfill, S., & Apperly, I. (2013). How to construct a minimal theory of mind. Mind and Language, 28, 606–637. https://doi.org/10.1111/mila.12036.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (1996). Simulation and self-knowledge: A defence of the theory-theory. In P. Carruthers & P. Smith (Eds.), Theories of theories of mind. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2009). How we know our own minds: The relationship between mindreading and metacognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, 121–182.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2011). The opacity of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Couchman, J., et al. (2009). Metacognition is prior. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32, 142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1984). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (2014). Intuition pumps and other tools for thinking. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1641/1993). Meditations on first philosophy. Indianapolis: Hackett.

  • Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauker, C. (2003). Words without meaning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geurts, B. (2019). Communication as commitment sharing: Speech acts, implicatures, common ground. Theoretical Linguistics, 45, 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1989). Interpretation psychologized. Mind and Language, 4, 161–185.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2006). Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Golombok & Fivush. (1994). Gender development. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Astington, J. (1988). Children’s understanding of representational change and its relation to the understanding of false belief and the appearance-reality distinction. Child Development, 59, 26–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. (1996). Words, thoughts, and theories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, R. (1986). Folk psychology as simulation. Mind and Language, 1, 158–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In P. Cole & J. Morgan (Eds.), Syntax and semantics 3: Speech acts (41–58).

  • Hacking, I. (1995). The looping effects of human kinds. In D. Sperber, D. Premack, & A. J. Premack (Eds.), Symposia of the Fyssen foundation. Causal cognition: A multidisciplinary debate (pp. 351–394). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1998). Mad travelers. Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2012). Resisting reality: Social construction and social critique. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1739/1978). A treatise of human nature. P. H. Nidditch (Ed.), 2nd Ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Hutto, D. (2008). Folk psychological narratives. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klucharev, V., Hytönen, K., Rijpkema, M., Smidts, A., & Fernández, G. (2009). Reinforcement learning signal predicts social conformity. Neuron, 61, 140–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornell, N., Son, L., & Terrace, H. (2007). Transfer of metacognitive skills and hint seeking in monkeys. Psychological Science, 18, 64–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langland-Hassan, P. (2014). Unwitting self-awareness? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 89, 719–726.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1969). Convention. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lillard, A. (1998). Ethnopsychologies: Cultural variations in theories of mind. Psychological Bulletin, 123, 3–32. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-2909.123.1.3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maibom, H. (2007). Social systems. Philosophical Psychology, 20, 557–578.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malle, B., Knobe, J., & Nelson, S. (2007). Actor-observer asymmetries in explanations of behavior: New answers to an old question. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 93, 491–514.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mameli, M. (2001). Mindreading, mindshaping, and evolution. Biology and Philosophy, 16, 597–628.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGeer, V. (1996). Is ‘self-knowledge’ an empirical problem? Renegotiating the space of philosophical explanation. Journal of Philosophy, 93, 483–515.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGeer, V. (2001). Psycho-practice, psycho-theory and the contrastive case of autism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, 109–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGeer, V. (2007). The regulative dimension of folk psychology. In D. Hutto & M. Ratcliffe (Eds.), Folk psychology reassessed. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGeer, V. (2015). Mind-making practices: The social infrastructure of self-knowing agency and responsibility. Philosophical Explorations, 18, 259–281. https://doi.org/10.1080/13869795.2015.1032331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, R. (2017). Gricean communication and cognitive development. The Philosophical Quarterly, 67, 303–326. https://doi.org/10.1093/pq/pqw049.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, R. (2018). Gricean communication, language development, and animal minds. Philosophy Compass. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morton, A. (2003). The importance of being understood. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2003). Mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (1881/1997). Daybreak: Thoughts on the prejudices of morality(2nd ed.). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nix, S., Perez-Felkner, L., & Thomas, K. (2015). Perceived mathematical ability under challenge: A longitudinal perspective on sex segregation among STEM degree fields. Frontiers in Psychology. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Proust, J. (2013). The philosophy of metacognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1948/2009). Human knowledge: Its scope and limits. London: Routledge Classics.

  • Scott-Phillips, T. (2015). Speaking our minds: Why human communication is different, and how language evolved to make it special. London: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1979). Expression and meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1, 253–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (2004). The stag hunt and the evolution of social structure. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (2002). Pragmatics, modularity, and mind-reading. Mind and Language, 17, 3–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2012). The evolved apprentice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vinden, P. (1999). Children’s understanding of mind and emotion: A multi-culture study. Cognition and Emotion, 13, 19–48. https://doi.org/10.1080/026999399379357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weiskopf, D. (2005). Mental mirroring as the origin of attributions. Mind and Language, 20, 495–520.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H. (1990). The child’s theory of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zawidzki, T. (2008). The function of folk psychology: Mind reading or mind shaping? Philosophical Explorations, 11(3), 193–210.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zawidzki, T. (2013). Mindshaping. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Richard Moore for extremely helpful, extensive comments on an earlier draft.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tadeusz W. Zawidzki.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Zawidzki, T.W. A new perspective on the relationship between metacognition and social cognition: metacognitive concepts as socio-cognitive tools. Synthese 198, 6573–6596 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02477-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02477-2

Keywords

Navigation