Skip to main content
Log in

In defence of Higher-Level Plural Logic: drawing conclusions from natural language

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Plural Logic is an extension of First-Order Logic which has, as well as singular terms and quantifiers, their plural counterparts. Analogously, Higher-Level Plural Logic is an extension of Plural Logic which has, as well as plural terms and quantifiers, higher-level plural ones. Roughly speaking, higher-level plurals stand to plurals like plurals stand to singulars; they are pluralised plurals. Allegedly, Higher-Level Plural Logic enjoys the expressive power of a simple type theory while committing us to nothing more than the austere ontology of First-Order Logic. Were this true, Higher-Level Plural Logic would be a useful tool, with various applications in philosophy and linguistics. However, while the notions of plural reference and quantification enjoy widespread acceptance today, their higher-level counterparts have been received with a lot of scepticism. In this paper, I argue for the legitimacy of Higher-Level Plural Logic by providing evidence to the effect that natural languages contain higher-level plural expressions and showing that it is likely that they do so in an indispensable manner. Since the arguments I put forward are of the same sort advocates of Plural Logic have employed to defend their position, I conclude that the commonly held view that Plural Logic is legitimate, but not so its higher-level plural extensions is untenable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, Black (1971) uses it to support his eliminativist view about sets, Boolos (1984), Boolos (1985) and Uzquiano (2003) use it in the framework of an eliminativist view of classes and Hossack (2000) uses it in an eliminative project about complex objects. Moreover, a notable eliminativist project that employs plurals is that of Lewis (1991). He endorses a theory of sets where set membership is reduced to singleton-set membership plus mereological fusion of singletons and where polyadic relations are reduced to plural reference to ordered pairs. Thus his aim is not to eliminate sets altogether, but rather to replace the (in his view) mysterious notion of set membership with a stock of allegedly more transparent notions.

  2. See, for instance, Boccuni (2011, 2013).

  3. For a survey of the philosophical debate on plurals and a description of a simple logic of plurals, see Linnebo (2017).

  4. For instance, Rayo (2006) and Oliver and Smiley (2016).

  5. I will occasionally speak of ‘pluralities’ in this paper. However, note that I will use the term ‘plurality’ as a convenient shorthand for ‘objects’. This is common practice in this debate and is necessary due to the expressive limitations of English.

  6. Even though they ultimately argue against the claim that the higher-level plural reading carries a substantial advantage.

  7. For instance, one could assume the existence of ordered pairs, but this would be at odds with the purpose of the neo-Fregean programme by not only presupposing the existence of a plethora of entities without providing a further story as to why this is legitimate, but also by presupposing the existence of entities which are suspiciously set-theoretic in nature. Another option would be to use a pairing function, but this strategy would be problematic too, since the existence of a pairing function makes specific demands on the size of one’s background ontology, as argued by Shapiro and Weir (2000).

  8. The idea would be to express a definition analogous to that of, for instance, Hausdorff as follows:

    \(\langle a, b\rangle := ((a,1),(b,2))\), where ((a, 1), (b, 2)) is meant to represent a second-level plurality which consists of the plurality of a and 1, on the one hand, and the plurality of b and 2, on the other. See Grimau (2018, Chap. 7) for a proposal along these lines.

  9. We find this scepticism explicitly expressed, for instance, in Simons (1982), Lewis (1991), Uzquiano (2004), Rumfitt (2005), McKay (2006) and Ben-Yami (2013).

  10. In the literature on PL it is often assumed that singular reference is a limiting case of plural reference, since plural terms may happen to denote a single thing. On this basis, formal plural terms are often interpreted as possibly denoting a single thing. In this article, for the sake of simplicity, I will not adhere to this assumption at the formal level. For us, a plural term will denote more than one thing and thus will serve to regiment the natural language phenomenon of strict plural reference. Moreover, Oliver and Smiley (2016) further liberalise the notion by allowing formal plural terms to fail to denote. Since allowing for vacuous reference would also significantly complicate the formalism and none of my arguments hinge on this choice, I discard this possibility as well.

  11. This has been endorsed in Landman (1989a, b) and Schwarzschild (1996).

  12. Properties can be seen as collectivising entities in the sense that they gather together all of their instances. One such proposal can be found in Florio (2010).

  13. This line can be found in Link (1983, 1998).

  14. A survey can be found in Florio (2014).

  15. This criticism is raised, for instance, in Shapiro (1991, pp. 225–226) and Shapiro (1993, pp. 471–472).

  16. See, for example, Boolos (1984, p. 65).

  17. This argument can be found in Boolos (1984, pp. 65–66) and Uzquiano (2003, p. 68).

  18. This line of defence can be found, for example, in Lewis (1991, p. 68), but note that this argument relies on the further assumption that the all-encompassing domain is not indefinitely extensible (see Rayo and Uzquiano (2006, pp. 4–6) for an overview of this topic).

  19. The idea that higher-level plurals are the result of iterating semantic pluralisation is expressed by Hazen (1997, p. 247) and Linnebo and Nicolas (2008, p. 186), among others.

  20. See Linnebo (2006) for a development of this view with respect to type theory.

  21. Even though I do not have a strong preference for either option, I take the typed route since it captures better the intuition that the ascent from the singular to the plural and from the basic plural to higher levels is a matter of expressive rather than ontological expansion.

  22. I limit the hierarchy to finite levels for simplicity.

  23. Note that we do not have any mechanism of complex term formation, such as a rule to form definite descriptions out of non-logical predicates or to form lists out of terms. Although these would allow HLPL to regiment natural language more accurately (and thus might be necessary for applications of HLPL in natural language or ordinary reasoning analysis), I leave them out for the sake of simplicity, since nothing that I discuss in this article turns on the availability or lack thereof of these complex terms. (see Oliver and Smiley (2016) for a language which allows for definite description formation).

  24. I will remain neutral as to the specific nature of these entities, since this issue is irrelevant in the present context.

  25. The ordered triples acting as models are not ordinary ones: they require that some of their members be pluralities. However, this is unproblematic in light of the fact that we can code these unorthodox ordered pairs using techniques already available to us, as shown in Linnebo and Rayo (2012, pp. 304–306).

  26. In this article I rule out the possibility of referring to mixed higher-level pluralities, that is, pluralities consisting of, say, a single individual on the one hand and a first-level plurality on the other (intuitively the denotation of e.g. Rafa Nadal and the Williams sisters). Given that none of the arguments put forward in the present article depend on this and keeping in mind that they could be accounted for by complicating the formalism (i.e. adopting a logic analogous to cumulative type theory; see Linnebo and Rayo (2012) for details), I leave mixed higher-level pluralities aside.

  27. An \(x^{k}\)-variant of s is an assignment that only differs from s at most in what it assigns to \(x^{k}\).

  28. Yi (2006, pp. 262–264) and Oliver and Smiley (2016, Chap. 13).

  29. Authors have used different terminology to refer to higher-level plurals. These are some of the terms that have been used in the literature: ‘perplurals’ (Hazen 1997; McKay 2006), ‘pluplurals’ (Rosen and Dorr 2002; Simons 2016), ‘plurally plurals’ (Hossack 2000; McKay 2006; Rumfitt 2005; Uzquiano 2004), ‘hyperplurals’ (Cotnoir 2013), ‘superplurals’ (Oliver and Smiley 2016; Rayo 2006).

  30. See Ben-Yami (2013, pp. 82–83), Rumfitt (2005, p. 13) and Simons (1982, pp. 192–193) for some sceptical reactions. Note that Simons seems to have recently retracted this view, as can be seen in Simons (2016).

  31. Rayo only claims that English, in particular, does not contain such devices.

  32. See Rayo (2006, p. 227) for an endorsement of this approach. This position would be akin to the view endorsed in Williamson (2003, p. 459) with respect to higher-order logic.

  33. In its set-theoretic version, a cover of a set a (such as the denotation of a plural term, under set-theoretic singularism) is a set of non-empty subsets of a, where every member of a belongs to some such subset. In its sum-based version, a cover of a sum s (such as the denotation of a plural term, under sum-based singularism) is a set of sums whose fusion is s.

  34. Although neither Gillon nor Schwarzschild endorse their semantics in the context of HLPL, Linnebo and Nicolas (2008) note its potential relevance for the present topic.

  35. In this article I will mostly be using the expression ‘group’ in its non-technical informal sense. Whenever I use it in the sense just described, I will make it explicit.

  36. I use commas (possibly followed by a conjunction) in order to indicate where one nested list ends and another one begins. This rather artificial notation is more naturally captured by intonation in spoken language.

  37. According to this understanding of lists, nested lists of plurals would be third-level plurals. E.g. the cat lovers and their cats, and the dog lovers and their dogs.

  38. See Oliver and Smiley (2016, Chap. 8), who call them ‘plurally exhaustive descriptions’.

  39. The notion of pseudo-singularity comes from Oliver and Smiley’s work on plurals. See Oliver and Smiley (2016, pp. 305–306).

  40. Some languages only display the anaphoric form of plural override. For instance, in French and Latvian that is the only way in which we find the phenomenon.

  41. I am grateful to an anonymous referee for this example and, more generally, for pointing out this issue.

  42. For arguments in favour of the atomicity of the reference of group nouns like pair or team see also Barker (1992), Link (1984), Landman (1989a), Schwarzschild (1996) and Winter (2002).

  43. This was also noted, although not specifically in relation with HLPL, by Jespersen (1924, p. 189).

  44. For instance, Corbett (2000) talks of ‘semantically composing plural on plural’.

  45. Ben-Yami (2013, pp. 85–86) raises the objection that ‘the translations of the Icelandic phrases in fact disagree with the use Linnebo would like to make of them’. This is because they do make use of an expression like pair. However, this objection appears to put the cart before the horse. English translations cannot play the role Ben-Yami intends them to play here, since they cannot help us identify a non-English expression as higher-level plural, given the expressive limitations of English. If this were a valid criterion of identification, the outcome of the investigation would be decided from the start.

  46. According to Hurford (2003), Estonian is ‘to a large extent’ similar to Finnish in this respect. I focus on Finnish for simplicity.

  47. While the following examples were reported in Appleyard (1987, p. 252), they were originally recorded a whole century before, in Reinisch (1884). Appleyard reports that even though in his study he found similar forms, they had evolved into mere alternative first-level plural forms. It would not be surprising if the distinction had been lost today.

  48. In this example, the first plural suffix (e) is irregular and the second one () is regular.

  49. I wish to thank an anonymous referee for pointing this out to me.

  50. See Black (1971, p. 633) for one such proposal.

  51. This has been proposed by McKay (2006, p. 138).

  52. To see that this reading is available imagine (6) as being uttered in a context in which some lecturers met to discuss the results of the final evaluation, while some students met to plan an end-of-the-year party, and the person who utters (6) is explaining why the lecturers complained that the students were too loud.

  53. This is reported in Quine (1950, sec. 38).

  54. See Boolos (1984, p. 57, fn7) for details.

  55. And see also the discussion of pseudo-singularity in general in Sect. 5.1.1.

  56. An analogous example is given in Linnebo and Nicolas (2008) and I follow their discussion. However, they do not tackle the issue of non-set-sized denotations.

  57. In what follows, I use ‘group’ in its technical sense.

  58. See Ben-Yami (2013, p. 89).

  59. An analogous example was originally proposed in Linnebo and Nicolas (2008).

  60. See Oliver and Smiley (2016, Chap. 10) for more details on these two analyses of lists.

  61. Moreover, the data involving failures of substitutivity is compatible with articulation falling on the side of the semantic value of the terms which have it (and a fortiori with treating them as referring expressions). I believe more needs to be said to justify placing articulation outside of their semantic interpretation.

  62. See Ben-Yami (2013, p. 97).

  63. See, for instance, Resnik (1988, p. 77).

  64. Naturally, the possibility of endorsing PL for reasons not considered in this article cannot be ruled out, but, to the best of my knowledge, the main reasons appealed to in the literature in defence of PL have been examined.

References

  • Acquaviva, P. (2008). Lexical plurals: A morphosemantic approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Appleyard, D. L. (1987). A grammatical sketch of Khamtanga-I. Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies, University of London, 50(2), 241–266.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker, C. (1992). Group terms in English: Representing groups as atoms. Journal of Semantics, 9(1), 69–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Yami, H. (2013). Higher-level plurals versus articulated reference, and an elaboration of salva veritate. Dialectica, 67(1), 81–102.

    Google Scholar 

  • Black, M. (1971). The elusiveness of sets. Review of Metaphysics, 24(4), 614–636.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boccuni, F. (2011). On the consistency of a plural theory of Frege’s Grundgesetze. Studia Logica, 97(3), 329–345.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boccuni, F. (2013). Plural logicism. Erkenntnis, 78(5), 1051–1067.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boolos, G. (1984). To be is to be a value of a variable (or to be some values of some variables). Journal of Philosophy, 81(8), 430–449.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boolos, G. (1985). Nominalist platonism. Philosophical Review, 94(3), 327–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corbett, G. G. (2000). Number. Cambridge textbooks in linguistics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cotnoir, A. J. (2013). Composition as general identity. In K. Bennett & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 8, p. 294-322). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Florio, S. (2010). The semantics of plurals: A defense of singularism. Ph.D. thesis, Ohio State University.

  • Florio, S. (2014). Semantics and the plural conception of reality. Philosophers’ Imprint, 14(22), 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Florio, S., & Nicolas, D. (2015). Plural logic and sensitivity to order. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 93(3), 444–464.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillon, B. S. (1987). The readings of plural noun phrases in English. Linguistics and Philosophy, 10(2), 199–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillon, B. S. (1992). Towards a common semantics for English count and mass nouns. Linguistics and Philosophy, 15(6), 597–639.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimau, B. (2018). From plurals to superplurals: In defence of higher-level plural logic. Ph.D. thesis, Universty of Glasgow.

  • Hazen, A. P. (1997). Relations in Lewis’ framework without atoms. Analysis, 57(4), 243–248.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hewitt, S. (2012). The logic of finite order. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 53(3), 297–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hossack, K. (2000). Plurals and complexes. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 51(3), 411–443.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurford, J.R. (2003). The interaction between numerals and nouns. In Noun Phrase Structure in the Languages of Europe, Volume 20-7 of Empirical Approaches to Language Typology.

  • Jespersen, O. (1924). The philosophy of grammar. Crows Nest: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landman, F. (1989a). Groups, I. Linguistics and Philosophy, 12(5), 559–605.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landman, F. (1989b). Groups, II. Linguistics and Philosophy, 12(6), 723–744.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1991). Parts of classes. New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Link, G. (1983). The logical analysis of plurals and mass terms: A lattice-theoretic approach. In P. Portner & B. H. Partee (Eds.), Formal semantics—The essential readings (pp. 127–147). New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Link, G. (1984). Hydras: On the logic of relative clause constructions with multiple heads. In F. Landman & F. Veltman (Eds.), Varieties of formal semantics: Proceedings of the fourth Amsterdam colloquium. Dordrecht: Foris Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Link, G. (1998). Ten years of research on plurals—Where do we stand? (pp. 19–54). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnebo, O. (2003). Plural quantification exposed. Noûs, 37(1), 71–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnebo, O. (2006). Sets, properties, and unrestricted quantification. In G. Uzquiano & A. Rayo (Eds.), Absolute generality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnebo, O. (2017). Plural quantification. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford: The Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnebo, O., & Nicolas, D. (2008). Superplurals in English. Analysis, 68, 186–197.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnebo, O., & Rayo, A. (2012). Hierarchies ontological and ideological. Mind, 121(482), 269–308.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKay, T. J. (2006). Plural predication. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nicolas, D. (2008). Mass nouns and plural logic. Linguistics and philosophy, 31(2), 211–244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver, A., & Smiley, T. (2016). Plural logic: 2nd edition, revised and enlarged (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1950). Methods of logic. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rayo, A. (2006). Beyond plurals. In A. Rayo & G. Uzquiano (Eds.), Absolute generality (pp. 220–54). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rayo, A., & Uzquiano, G. (2006). Absolute generality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinisch, L. (1884). Die Chamirsprache in Abessinien. New York: Gerold.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, M. D. (1988). Second-order logic still wild. Journal of Philosophy, 85(2), 75–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G., & Dorr, C. (2002). Composition as a fiction. In R. Gale (Ed.), The Blackwell companion to metaphysics (pp. 151–174). New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumfitt, I. (2005). Plural terms : Another variety of reference? In J. L. Bermúdez (Ed.), Thought, reference, and experience: Themes from the philosophy of gareth evans (pp. 84–123). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzschild, R. (1996). Pluralities. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (1991). Foundations without foundationalism: A case for second-order logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (1993). Modality and ontology. Mind, 102(407), 455–481.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S., & Weir, A. (2000). ‘Neo-logicist’ logic is not epistemically innocent. Philosophia mathematica, 8(2), 160–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, P. (1982). Number and manifolds. In B. Smith (Ed.), Parts and moments: Studies in logic and formal ontology (pp. 160–98). Berlin: Philosophia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simons, P. (2016). The ontology and logic of higher-order multitudes (pp. 55–69). Oxford: Oxford University Pres.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uzquiano, G. (2003). Plural quantification and classes. Philosophia Mathematica, 11(1), 67–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uzquiano, G. (2004). Plurals and simples. The Monist, 87(3), 429–451.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Vries, H. (2017). Two kinds of distributivity. Natural Language Semantics, 25(2), 173–197.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2003). Everything. Philosophical Perspectives, 17(1), 415–465.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winter, Y. (2002). Atoms and sets: A characterization of semantic number. Linguistic Inquiry, 33(3), 493–505.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yi, B. (2005). The logic and meaning of plurals. Part I. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 34(5–6), 459–506.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yi, B. (2006). The logic and meaning of plurals. Part II. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 35(3), 239–288.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper profited from feedback by Joan Bertran-San Millán, Stefan Krämer, Stephan Leuenberger, Øystein Linnebo and Adam Rieger, and by audiences in Glasgow, Leeds, Madrid and Prague. Moreover, I wish to especially thank Michele Palmira and Bruno Whittle, whose comments led to a substantial improvement of the manuscript. Finally, I am grateful to the anonymous referees who reviewed this work for their thorough and insightful feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Berta Grimau.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

The research for this paper was funded by the Grant AH/L503915/1 of the Arts and Humanities Research Council and the Grant GA18-00113S of the Czech Science Foundation.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Grimau, B. In defence of Higher-Level Plural Logic: drawing conclusions from natural language. Synthese 198, 5253–5280 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02399-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02399-z

Keywords

Navigation