Skip to main content
Log in

Transitions in evolution: a formal analysis

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Evolutionary transitions in individuality (ETIs) are events during which individuals at a given level of organization (particles) interact to form higher-level entities (collectives) which are then recognized as new individuals at that level. ETIs are intimately related to levels of selection, which, following Okasha, can be approached from two different perspectives. One, referred to as ‘synchronic’, asks whether selection occurs at the collective level while the partitioning of particles into collectives is taken for granted. The other, referred to as ‘diachronic’, asks about the origins of the partitioning of particles into collectives. After having presented the two perspectives and a classical formalism used to deal with the levels-of-selection question in the literature, namely the multilevel version of the Price equation, I show that because this formalism treats the levels-of-selection question from a synchronic perspective, it is inadequate to explain ETIs. This is because a fundamental aspect of ETIs is the origin of collectives. From there, I develop a framework for levels of selection compatible with the diachronic perspective. This framework relies on the distinction between what I call, on the one hand, a ‘functional aggregative collective trait’, and on the other hand, a ‘functional non-aggregative collective trait’. After having presented this distinction, I implement it in the Price equation, leading to a new statistical partitioning of this equation which, I argue, represents a causal decomposition more relevant for ETIs. Finally, I exploit this partitioning to explain the critical stages of an ETI. In addition to its explanatory power, a measure of the degree of functional non-aggregativity could be used as a proxy for the degree of individuality of a collective.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The distinction between the synchronic and diachronic perspectives on the levels of selection was first drawn by Okasha (2006, pp. 220–225).

  2. Note that evolutionary biologists typically do not make the distinction between the synchronic and the diachronic approach. Rather, it is often implicit in the type of questions they ask.

  3. Okasha (2006, 2018) argues that the move from asking the levels-of-selection question from a synchronic to a diachronic perspective is a special case of a more general strategy in evolutionary biology which he calls the ‘strategy of endogenization,’ in which the values of variables that were initially taken for granted in a model (exogenous to the model), become progressively explained (endogenized) by other variables in the model. In the case of levels of selection, the ‘variable’ which is endogenized is the existence of collectives.

  4. The term ‘event’ should be understood here loosely in the sense that ETIs need not occur abruptly at a point in time. They might rather occur as a result of processes over a long period of time.

  5. There is a parallel here between the last of the six transitions and the literature on the holobiont—a macrobe and its microbial symbionts. Some have put forward the idea that the holobiont as opposed to the traditional organism—the macrobe without its symbionts—is the unit ‘seen’ by selection. Although in some specific cases holobionts might be regarded as units of selection, there are important problems with this idea. For an analysis see Bourrat and Griffiths (2018).

  6. Although I will sometimes refer to w and \(\omega \) as fitness, they are, strictly speaking, not ‘fitness,’ but absolute and relative reproductive output which, as such, are proxies for or measures of fitness.

  7. ‘Statistical aggregate’ simply means that a collective property is defined as a mean of the properties of its constituent particles.

  8. The character is attributed, rather than intrinsic, here, because nothing guarantees that in a non-collective context, the same particle-level character would be observed.

  9. For details see Frank (1998, pp. 13–15).

  10. Okasha (2006, p. 107) defends the idea that the collective level can be an autonomous level of selection and that this is consistent with the supervenience of the collective level on the particle level. The problem with this argument is that the expected fitness of a collective, following my assumptions, depends on the fitness of its particles, so that there exists a relation of dependence between collective and particle fitness. Similarly, Okasha (2016) discusses the problem of intervening on collective characters when they supervene on particle characters: intervening on one is impossible without, at the same time, intervening on the other, because they are two descriptions of the same material substrate. Such interventions as noted by Okasha (2016), are known in the literature as ‘fat-hand’ interventions (Scheines 2005). Okasha (2016, p. 450) proposes to solve this problem by the following convention: “when we consider hypothetically intervening on the supervenient variable we do not hold fixed the variables on which it supervenes, but rather alter them to preserve consistency.” This convention, although mathematically sound, is however inconsistent with the idea of supervenience. Unless there are good reasons to reject the supervenience of collective characters on particle characters, and I believe there are not, this convention cannot be justified. For other problems related to this convention see Birch (2017, pp. 92–93).

  11. Note, furthermore, that Damuth and Heisler (1988) are very explicit that MLS1 and MLS2 represent two perspectives on a given evolutionary process, not a factual distinction. When referring to the two approaches they claim (1988, pp. 410–411): “our point of view is that neither approach represents the multilevel selection process. Rather, both are aspects of any multilevel selection situation. Once one has decided to analyze a given situation in terms of multilevel selection processes both approaches are legitimate within that context and a choice has to be made depending upon what questions are of interest.” Additionally, the definition of fitness as number of particles (MLS1) and number of collectives (MLS2) produced after one generation does not correlate perfectly with selection. As is well known in life-history theory, number of offspring is not the only measure of fitness. The size of offspring, for instance, is often correlated to long term evolutionary success. Once these other factors are taken into consideration, the MLS1 and MLS2 distinction collapses. For more details see Bourrat (2016).

  12. Of course, taking a single collective character, there is no guarantee that it will depend on a single character of particles. It might depend on more than one particle character(s).

  13. Note that in real situations the two components might not occur temporally when generations are not discrete, and there might be some interaction between them.

  14. I will only consider the reproductive mode of multiplication in the reminder of the article. Note also that the notion of ‘phase’ I use here should not be understood temporally. They are conceptual phases so that the selection and response phases can occur at the same time, consistently with the point made in Footnote 13.

  15. The clause that the parts are taken independently is important. If they are not, then because of the existence of a relationship of mereological supervenience between the system and the properties of its parts, a system would always be aggregative. As we will see in the next section, this subtlety is at the heart of what distinguishes a functional aggregate from a statistical aggregate.

  16. Even this is controversial since some mass is transformed into energy during exothermic reactions.

  17. To illustrate my point, I assume that the weight each sculler has to carry is the same in each situation, which in reality is not the case. A boat for a single person is not four times lighter than a boat for four people. It is heavier than that.

  18. One might want to attribute a phenotype of 0 to all particles taken independently, but the phenotype would be undefined since there would be no contrast phenotype (that is a phenotype with a value different from 0) to compare this phenotype to when particles are taken independently.

  19. Note, however, that the procedure used to assess whether failure in non-aggregativity qua size scaling occurs will involve linearity, decomposition and recomposition, and intersubstitution.

  20. Note, however, that the use of fitness transfer and associated terms seem to have meant different things in the different venues Michod has published.

  21. There are also ambiguities associated with the notion of fitness applying over different timescales when switching from one level of organization to another (Bourrat 2015b, c).

  22. For details of the derivation see Okasha (2006, Chap. 1), who drew from the work of Queller (1992) and Rice (2004). See also Bourrat (2015a).

  23. Note also that the first term on the right-hand side of Eq. (4) has the same form as a well-known equation in quantitative genetics, namely the breeder’s equation (Falconer and Mackay 1996).

  24. It is still possible that in spite of a causal relationship from z to \(\omega \), it is a non-linear one in such a way that \(\beta _{wz}\) is nil. I will assume here that that is not the case. For a more careful analysis of the relationship between the Price equation and Lewontin’s three conditions see Okasha (2006, Chap. 1).

  25. Note, however, that this last problem is taken care of by our assumption that the collective character is a statistical aggregate of the particle character of its constituent particles.

  26. The point here is similar to the idea that the gene’s eye view does not describe a causal relationship between genes and phenotype, but merely accounts for it statistically. This idea is known as the ‘book keeping objection’ to the gene’s eye view (see Okasha 2006, p. 158ff, for a review of the literature on the book keeping objection). I should add that the distinction between statistical and functional aggregativity resonates with the distinction between statistical and physiological epistasis (also known as gene-gene interaction) sometimes made by quantitative geneticists (Goodnight 1988; Wade 2016; Wolf et al. 2000). Physiological epistasis corresponds to the notion of functional non-aggregativity: in spite of a high level of functional epistasis for a character, that is to say that the character would not be expressed in the absence of, or by the knocking out of, one of the alleles contributing to the organisms’ character, the effect might be considered as statistically additive in a population.

  27. They might be correlated in specific cases, but not in the general case.

  28. More accurrately it represents the particle contribution of the collective-level response to the particle contribtution of collective-level selection, which is a bit cumbersome and hence the reason why I use ‘particle response to particle-level selection’. Mutatis mutandis the same can be said for the other three response to selection terms.

  29. Note however that when there is no variation in the aggregative component of particles between the collectives but there is some within each collective or when the correlation between collective fitness and the aggregative component is nil but there are differences in fitness between particles of a collective, the term \(\mathrm{Cov}(\varOmega _k, A_k)\) will be nil. This might be interpreted as a lack particle-level selection which seems wrong since there could exist differences in fitness between the particles with different aggregative components of a collective. Mutatis mutandis, the same will be true with the non-aggregative component of the collective-level character. That said, a situation in which all the collectives have the same aggregative (or non-aggregative) component, although possible, is rather artificial. In general, if there is variation within collectives, we can expect that this will translate into variation between collectives. Nevertheless, perhaps ways to address this potential worry—although this would require a careful assessment—would be either to apply the aggregative/non-aggregative distinction in the single-level version of the Price equation at the level of the particle rather than the collective level, or to apply it to the hierarchical version of the Price equation as opposed to the single-level version at the collective level. In this latter case, one would essentially have to insert Eq. (20) recursively in the transmission bias term of Eq. (20). In both cases, one could assess whether each component of particle-character is correlated with particle fitness (either globally or within each collective depending on the option chosen). Having flagged up this potential worry and provided possible directions to address it, I leave a full analysis for future work.

  30. This, of course, relies on the assumption that the population is infinitely large. In a population with a finite size, the number and frequency of interactions of particles will always be limited.

  31. The trait must be the same at both levels, and consequently for the different types of particles, even if they belong to different species. This poses some practical problems which, in many cases, can be overcome by standardizing the particle-level trait.

  32. Although under some particular ecological conditions sharp separations between collectives might arise for free.

  33. Such traits are typically called ‘emergent’, a term I find too vague. These traits are simply not easily definable at the particle level, rather than emergent.

References

  • Ariew, A., & Lewontin, R. C. (2004). The confusions of fitness. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55(2), 347–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baum, D. A., & Baum, B. (2014). An inside-out origin for the eukaryotic cell. BMC Biology, 12(1), 76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birch, J. (2017). The philosophy of social evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Black, A. J., Bourrat, P., & Rainey, P. B. (2019). Ecological scaffolding and the evolution of individuality: The transition from cells to multicellular life. bioRxiv p. 656660. https://doi.org/10.1101/656660.

  • Bouchard, F. (2008). Causal processes, fitness, and the differential persistence of lineages. Philosophy of Science, 75(5), 560–570.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouchard, F. (2010). Symbiosis, lateral function transfer and the (many) saplings of life. Biology & Philosophy, 25(4), 623–641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouchard, F. (2011). Darwinism without populations: A more inclusive understanding of the “Survival of the Fittest”. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 42(1), 106–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouchard, F. (2018). Symbiosis, transient biological individuality, and evolutionary processes. In D. J. Nicholson & J. Dupré (Eds.), Everything flows: Towards a processual philosophy of biology (pp. 186–198). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bouchard, F., & Huneman, P. (Eds.). (2013). From groups to individuals: Evolution and emerging individuality. Vienna Series in Theoretical Biology Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

  • Bourke, A. F. (2011). Principles of social evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bourrat, P. (2014). From survivors to replicators: Evolution by natural selection revisited. Biology & Philosophy, 29(4), 517–538.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourrat, P. (2015a). How to read ‘Heritability’ in the recipe approach to natural selection. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 66(4), 883–903.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourrat, P. (2015b). Levels of selection are artefacts of different fitness temporal measures. Ratio, 28(1), 40–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourrat, P. (2015c). Levels, time and fitness in evolutionary transitions in individuality. Philosophy & Theory in Biology,. https://doi.org/10.3998/ptb.6959004.0007.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourrat, P. (2016). Generalizing contextual analysis. Acta Biotheoretica, 64(2), 197–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourrat, P., & Griffiths, P. E. (2018). Multispecies individuals. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-018-0194-1.

  • Bourrat, P. (in press). Evolutionary transitions in heritability and individuality. Theory in Biosciences. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12064-019-00294-2.

  • Buss, L. W. (1987). The evolution of individuality. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calcott, B., & Sterelny, K. (Eds.). (2011). The major transitions in evolution revisited., Vienna Series in Theoretical Biology Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Clarke, E. (2014). Origins of evolutionary transitions. Journal of Biosciences, 39(2), 303–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, E. (2016). A levels-of-selection approach to evolutionary individuality. Biology & Philosophy, 31(6), 893–911.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corning, P. (2003). Nature’s magic: Synergy in evolution and the fate of humankind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Corning, P. (2010). Holistic Darwinism: Synergy, cybernetics, and the bioeconomics of evolution. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damuth, J., & Heisler, I. L. (1988). Alternative formulations of multilevel selection. Biology and Philosophy, 3(4), 407–430. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00647962.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1976). The selfish gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donlan, R. M. (2002). Biofilms: Microbial life on surfaces. Emerging Infectious Diseases, 8(9), 881–890.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dugatkin, L. A., & Reeves, H. K. (1994). Behavioral ecology and levels of selection: Dissolving the group selection controversy. Advances in the Study of Behavior, 23, 101–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earnshaw, E. (2015). Group selection and contextual analysis. Synthese, 192(1), 305–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falconer, D. S., & Mackay, T. F. (1996). Introduction to quantitative genetics (4th ed.). Essex: Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, S. A. (1998). Foundations of social evolution. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2008). Varieties of population structure and the levels of selection. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59(1), 25–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Darwinian populations and natural selection. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2011). Darwinian populations and transitions in individuality. In B. Calcott & K. Sterelny (Eds.), The major transitions in evolution revisited. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2015). Reproduction, symbiosis, and the eukaryotic cell. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 112(33), 10120–10125. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1421378112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P., & Kerr, B. (2013). Gestalt-switching and the evolutionary transitions. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64(1), 205–222. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axr051.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodnight, C. J. (1988). Epistasis and the effect of founder events on the additive genetic variance. Evolution, 42(3), 441–454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodnight, C. J., & Stevens, L. (1997). Experimental studies of group selection: What do they tell us about group selection in nature? The American Naturalist, 150, s59–s79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodnight, C. J., Schwartz, J. M., & Stevens, L. (1992). Contextual analysis of models of group selection, soft selection, hard selection and the evolution of altruism. American Naturalist, 140, 743–761.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer, J. (2000). The units of evolutionary transition. Selection, 1(1–3), 67–80. https://doi.org/10.1556/Select.1.2000.1-3.7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, W. D. (1975). Innate social aptitudes of man: An approach from evolutionary genetics. In R. Fox (Ed.), Biosocial anthropology (pp. 133–153). London: Malaby Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hammerschmidt, K., Rose, C. J., Kerr, B., & Rainey, P. B. (2014). Life cycles, fitness decoupling and the evolution of multicellularity. Nature, 515(7525), 75–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heisler, I. L., & Damuth, J. (1987). A method for analyzing selection in hierarchically structured populations. The American Naturalist, 130(4), 582–602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herron, M. D. (2016). Origins of multicellular complexity: Volvox and the volvocine algae. Molecular Ecology, 25(6), 1213–1223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herron, M. D., Zamani-Dahaj, S. A., & Ratcliff, W. C. (2018). Trait heritability in major transitions. BMC Biology, 16(1), 145. https://doi.org/10.1186/s12915-018-0612-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. L. (1980). Individuality and selection. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 11, 311–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (2016). Emergence: A philosophical account. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jeler, C. (2014). Is there such a thing as “group selection” in the contextual analysis framework? History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 36(4), 484–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, L. (1999). Levels of selection in evolution. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kerr, B., & Godfrey-Smith, P. (2002). Individualist and multi-level perspectives on selection in structured populations. Biology and Philosophy, 17, 477–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2005). Physicalism, or something near enough. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lande, R. (1979). Quantitative genetic analysis of multivariate evolution, applied to brain: Body size allometry. Evolution, 33(1), 402–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. C. (1970). The units of selection. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 1(1), 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. C. (1991). The structure and confirmation of evolution theory. Biology and Philosophy, 6(4), 461–466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mah, T. F. C., & O’Toole, G. A. (2001). Mechanisms of biofilm resistance to antimicrobial agents. Trends in Microbiology, 9(1), 34–39. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0966-842X(00)01913-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, W. F., Garg, S., & Zimorski, V. (2015). Endosymbiotic theories for eukaryote origin. Biological Sciences: Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2014.0330.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith, J., & Szathmary, E. (1995). The major transitions in evolution. New York, NY: OUP Oxford, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • McFall-Ngai, M. (2014). Divining the essence of symbiosis: Insights from the Squid-Vibrio model. PLoS Biology, 12(2), e1001,783.

  • Mcfall-Ngai, M. J. (1994). Animal-bacterial interactions in the early life history of marine invertebrates: The Euprymna scolopes/Vibrio fischeri symbiosis. Integrative and Comparative Biology, 34(4), 554–561.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michod, R. E. (1999). Darwinian dynamics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michod, R. E. (2005). On the transfer of fitness from the cell to the multicellular organism. Biology and Philosophy, 20, 967–987.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michod, R. E., & Roze, D. (1999). Cooperation and conflict in the evolution of individuality. III. Transitions in the unit of fitness. In C. L. Nehaniv (Ed.), Mathematical and computational biology: Computational morphogenesis, hierarchical complexity, and digital evolution (pp. 47–92). Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society.

  • Miyashiro, T., & Ruby, E. G. (2012). Shedding light on bioluminescence regulation in Vibrio fischeri. Molecular Microbiology, 84(5), 795–806.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nunney, L. (1985). Group selection, altruism, and structured-deme models. American Naturalist, 126, 212–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. (2006). Evolution and the levels of selection. New York, NY: Clarendon Press; Oxford University Press, Oxford: Oxford.

  • Okasha, S. (2016). The relation between Kin and multilevel selection: An approach using causal graphs. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 67(2), 435–470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. (2018). The strategy of endogenization in evolutionary biology. Synthese,. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1832-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S., & Paternotte, C. (2012). Group adaptation, formal darwinism and contextual analysis. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 25(6), 1127–1139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (2009). Causality: Models, reasoning, and inference (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Potts, M. (2002). Nostoc. In B. A. Whitton & M. Potts (Eds.), The ecology of cyanobacteria: Their diversity in time and space (pp. 465–504). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Prévost, J. (1961). Écologie Du Manchot Empereur Aptenodytes Forsteri Gray (Vol. 1291). Hermann.

  • Price, G. R. (1970). Selection and covariance. Nature, 227, 520–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price, G. R. (1972). Extension of covariance selection Mathematics. Annals of Human Genetics, 35, 485–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Queller, D. C. (1992). Quantitative genetics, inclusive fitness, and group selection. The American Naturalist, 139(3), 540–558.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rainey, P. B., & Kerr, B. (2010). Cheats as first propagules: A new hypothesis for the evolution of individuality during the transition from single cells to multicellularity. BioEssays, 32(10), 872–880.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rainey, P. B., & Rainey, K. (2003). Evolution of cooperation and conflict in experimental bacterial populations. Nature, 425, 72–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rice, S. H. (2004). Evolutionary theory: Mathematical and conceptual foundations. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rose, C. J., Hammerschmidt, K., & Rainey, P. B. (2019) Meta-population structure and the evolutionary transition to multicellularity. bioRxiv p 407163. https://doi.org/10.1101/407163.

  • Rosenberg, A., & Bouchard, F. (2010). Fitness. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy

  • Scheines, R. (2005). The similarity of causal inference in experimental and non-experimental studies. Philosophy of Science, 72(5), 927–940.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shelton, D. E., & Michod, R. E. (2014). Group selection and group adaptation during a major evolutionary transition: Insights from the evolution of multicellularity in the Volvocine Algae. Biological Theory, 9(4), 452–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1984). The nature of selection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E., & Wilson, D. S. (1994). A critical review of philosophical work on the units of selection problem. Philosophy of Science, 61(4), 534–555.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E., & Wilson, D. S. (1998). Unto others: The evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior (Vol. 218). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gestel, J., & Tarnita, C. E. (2017). On the origin of biological construction, with a focus on multicellularity. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1704631114.

  • Wade, M. J. (2016). Adaptation in metapopulations: How interaction changes evolution. University of Chicago Press.

  • Waters, C. M., & Bassler, B. L. (2005). Quorum sensing: Cell-to-cell communication in bacteria. Annual Review of Cell and Developmental Biology, 21(1), 319–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waters, K. C. (2011). Okasha’s Unintended argument for toolbox theorizing. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 82(1), 232–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West, S. A., Griffin, A. S., & Gardner, A. (2007). Social semantics: Altruism, cooperation, mutualism, strong reciprocity and group selection. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 20(2), 415–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G. C. (1966). Adaptation and natural selection: A critique of some current evolutionary thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D. S. (1975). A theory of group selection. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 72(1), 143–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D. S., & Wilson, E. O. (2007). Rethinking the theoretical foundation of sociobiology. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 82(4), 327–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A., & Barker, M. (2019). Biological individuals. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1986). Forms of aggregativity. Human nature and natural knowledge (pp. 259–291)., Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (2007). Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings: Piecewise approximations to reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, J. B., Brodie, E. D., & Wade, M. J. (2000). Epistasis and the evolutionary process. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolk, C. P. (1996). Heterocyst formation. Annual Review of Genetics, 30, 59–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am thankful to the Theory and Method in Biosciences group at the University of Sydney and two anonymous reviewers who provided useful feedback on previous versions of this manuscript. I am more particularly thankful to Stefan Gawronski who proofread the final manuscript. I also thank Katrin Hammerschmidt and Ellen Clarke for discussions on the topic. This research was supported by a Macquarie University Research Fellowship and a Large Grant from the John Templeton Foundation (Grant ID 60811).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pierrick Bourrat.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bourrat, P. Transitions in evolution: a formal analysis. Synthese 198, 3699–3731 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02307-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02307-5

Keywords

Navigation