Skip to main content
Log in

A puzzle for epistemic WAMs

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In recent literature, a very popular position about the normativity of assertion claims that standards for epistemically proper assertion vary with practical context, while standards for knowledge do not. This paper shows this claim is strongly incompatible with the received value-theoretic view regarding the relationship between the axiological and the deontic: one of the two has to go.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Crucially, the results of this paper only concern SA in its epistemic incarnation.

  2. The term was coined by Fantl and McGrath (2012).

  3. The locus classicus for the defence of the necessity claim involved in KNA is Williamson (2000). For support for the sufficiency claim, see Simion (2016).

  4. SA also comes in more than one variety; first there are people thinking that assertion is governed by one norm which stipulates that the appropriate amount of warrant for proper assertion varies with contextual features (e.g. Brown 2010; Gerken 2012; Goldberg 2015; McKinnon 2013; Rescorla 2009). Another way to be a sensitivist about assertion is to stipulate several norms governing assertion, depending on the context (e.g. Greenough 2011; Levin 2008; Stone 2007). The subtle differences between the above views are, however, to a large extent, irrelevant for now (but see the next section for refinements). That is because this paper dwells at a higher level of generality: what I am concerned with is the claim that epistemically proper assertability varies with practical stakes, no matter what triggers the variation in propriety in question. Insofar as these authors stand by this claim, they are the proper target of this paper.

  5. Strictly speaking, there are two ways one can pull a WAM: one can place the source of context sensitivity at the level of the epistemic norm itself (SA), or, to the contrary, defend a fixed norm and argue that pragmatic, Gricean considerations influence propriety in context (e.g. Rysiew 2001). This paper is only concerned with the first incarnation thereof.

  6. It is fair to say that defenders of SA go on separate ways when it comes to listing the relevant contextual determiners; that is, for some of them, practical concerns figure higher on the list (e.g. Gerken 2012), while others (e.g. Goldberg 2015) focus more on non-practical context sensitivity.

  7. For support of AC: for a good general overview of the relevant literature in value theory, see, for instance, Schroeder (2012); for champions of the teleological direction of explanation, see e.g. Moore (1993), Portmore (2005). Sidgwick (1907) and Slote (1989). For the deontological direction, see e.g. Scanlon (1998) Ewing (1947), Rabinowicz and Rönnow-Rasmussen (2004).

  8. Note, also, that the argument can be run in a parallel fashion for a justification goal (and the results are likely to coincide with the results for the knowledge goal, insofar as what is meant is knowledge-level justification). Also, see below for a discussion of what is the case on the assumption of an epistemic goal that itself varies with practical stakes, such as ‘providing actionable information’.

  9. Note that prominent defenders of CA (e.g. Goldberg 2015) explicitly support generating testimonial knowledge as the main epistemic role of assertion.

  10. Jessica Brown and Sandy Goldberg (in personal communication) suggested the WAM-er might want to take this route.

  11. See, e.g. Williamson (2000) and Simion et al. (2016).

  12. Many thanks to an anonymous referee for pressing me on this point.

  13. On Greenough’s (2011) view, for instance, knowledge is the minimal threshold for permissible assertion.

  14. Mikkel Gerken (p.c.) suggested this might be the way he might want to go about this issue.

  15. See Williamson (2005) for an account along these lines. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pressing me on this.

  16. See e.g. Williamson (2000) and Simion et al. (2016).

References

  • Brown, J. (2010). Knowledge and assertion. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81, 549–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • David, M. (2005). Truth as the primary epistemic goal: A working hypothesis. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy (pp. 296–312). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (2002). Assertion, knowledge, and context. Philosophical Review, 111, 167–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ewing, A. C. (1947). The definition of good. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fantl, J., & McGrath, M. (2012). Arguing for shifty epistemology. In J. Brown & M. Gerken (Eds.), Knowledge ascriptions (pp. 55–74). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gerken, M. (2012). Discursive justification and skepticism. Synthese, 189, 373–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, S. (2015). Assertion: The philosophical significance of a speech act. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, P. J. (2012). Epistemic entitlement. Nous, 46(3), 449–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenough, P. (2011). Truth-relativism, norm-relativism, and assertion. In J. Brown & H. Cappelen (Eds.), Assertion: New philosophical essays. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, J. (2008). Assertion, practical reason, and pragmatic theories of knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76, 359–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinnon, R. (2013). The supportive reasons norm of assertion. American Philosophical Quarterly, 50, 121–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1993) [1903]. Principia ethica (revised ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Portmore, D. (2005). Combining teleological ethics with evaluator relativism: A promising result. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 86, 95–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabinowicz, W., & Rönnow-Rasmussen, T. (2004). The strike of the demon: On fitting pro-attitudes and value. Ethics, 114, 391–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescorla, M. (2009). Assertion and its constitutive norms. Philosophy & Phenomenological Research, 79, 98–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rysiew, P. (2001). The context-sensitivity of knowledge attributions. Noûs, 35(4), 477–514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2012). Value theory. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.),The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy(summer 2012 edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2012/entries/value-theory/.

  • Sidgwick, H. (1907). The methods of ethics (7th ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simion, M. (2016). Assertion: Knowledge is enough. Synthese, 193(10), 3041–3056.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simion, M., Kelp, C., & Ghijsen, H. (2016). Norms of belief. Philosophical Issues, 26(1), 375–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slote, M. (1989). Beyond optimizing. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stone, J. (2007). Contextualism and warranted assertion. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 88, 92–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2005). Contextualism, subject-sensitive invariantism and knowledge of knowledge. The Philosophical Quarterly, 55(219), 213–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Many thanks to Jessica Brown, Mikkel Gerken, Sandy Goldberg, Patrick Greenough, Chris Kelp and two anonymous referees for Synthese for very helpful comments on this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mona Simion.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Simion, M. A puzzle for epistemic WAMs. Synthese 196, 4679–4689 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1681-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1681-3

Keywords

Navigation