Skip to main content
Log in

Epistemic harm and virtues of self-evaluation

  • S.I. : Knowledge and Justification, New Perspectives
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Miranda Fricker identifies a specific kind of epistemic harm that comes from assigning diminished credibility to others; when this is the result of identity prejudice it results in testimonial injustice. Fricker argues that this kind of injustice follows only from assigning diminished credibility to a person; assigning inflated credibility is never a testimonial injustice. In this paper I examine and expand arguments to the effect that assigning inflated credibility to one person can epistemically harm another. I extend this argument to self-evaluation. Psychological research on the overconfidence bias reveals ways in which we may systematically assign too much epistemic credibility to ourselves. However, our biases are not simple; they have a complex pattern revealed by the Dunning–Kruger effect. I will argue that we need to develop virtues of self-evaluation help counteract our self-bias. These virtues will be an important tool in helping us to avoid committing epistemic injustice to ourselves and to others.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Fricker (2007, p. 28).

  2. Fricker (2007, p. 25).

  3. Quoted in Fricker (2007, p. 88).

  4. Fricker (2007, pp. 20–21).

  5. Fricker (2007, pp. 19–20).

  6. Fricker (2007, p. 132).

  7. As Davis nicely illustrates with examples in her (2016).

  8. Note that I have shifted from Fricker’s terminology of “epistemic self-confidence” in the last paragraph to talking about self-assignment of credibility here and in the rest of the paper. While speaking of judging one’s own credibility may sound a bit odd, I want to highlight that we are making a judgment about the self and others and our relative abilities. There will, of course, be some differences in how we do this. We can doubt the sincerity of others, but rarely (absent cases of self-deception) doubt our own sincerity. Despite these differences, I think that it is reasonable to think about a judgement comparing the credibility of ourselves and others; this judgement is reflected in which position (our’s or the other’s) we end up believing.

  9. Guenther and Alicke (2010, p. 755).

  10. Alicke and Govorun (2005).

  11. Alicke and Govorun (2005, p. 87).

  12. Alicke (1985).

  13. Cross (1977).

  14. Alicke and Govorun (2005, p. 91).

  15. Ehrlinger et al. (2008).

  16. Kruger and Dunning (1999).

  17. Jones (2012).

  18. Dotson (2011). While Dotson focuses on ways that speakers might smother their testimony on the basis of perceived limitations in the hearer (that the hearer lacks the testimonial competence to appropriately receive the testimony), here we have an instance of smothering caused by the speaker inaccurately perceiving limitations in herself. (Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for suggesting this connection between lowered self-assessment and testimonial smothering.)

  19. Karen Jones (2012). She also calls this a “mutually reinforcing loop” in her (2002).

  20. Hazlett (2012, p. 220). While one could, in principle, have higher order attitudes to the beliefs of others, it is clear that Hazlett’s focus here is on higher order attitudes that take our own attitudes as their target.

  21. Whitcomb et al. (2015, p. 6).

  22. Whitcomb et al. make similar objections to what they call the Underestimation of Strengths view. (2015, p. 7) Both views of intellectual humility face this objection insofar as they do not dictate the affective or behavioral responses that one has to learning of one’s limitations.

  23. Whitcomb et al. (2015, p. 8).

  24. Whitcomb et al. (2015, p. 21).

  25. Whitcomb et al. (2015, p. 12).

  26. Daukas (2006, p. 111).

  27. Ballantyne (2015, p. 156).

  28. Fricker (2010), Anderson (2012).

  29. Daukas (2006, p. 121).

  30. Jones (2012, p. 248).

References

  • Alicke, M. (1985). Global self-evaluation as determined by the desirability and controllability of trait adjectives. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 49, 1621–1630.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alicke, M., & Govorun, O. (2005). The better-than-average effect. In M. Alicke, D. Dunning, & J. Kruger (Eds.), The self in social judgement (pp. 85–106). New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, E. (2012). Epistemic justice as a virtue of social institutions. Social Epistemology, 26(2), 163–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ballantyne, N. (2015). Debunking biased thinkers (including ourselves). Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 1(1), 141–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cross, K. P. (1977). Not can but will college teachers be improved? New Directions for Higher Education, 17, 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daukas, N. (2006). Epistemic trust and social location. Episteme, 3, 109–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, E. (2016). Typecasts, tokens, and spokespersons: A case for credibility excess as testimonial injustice. Hypatia, 31(3), 485–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dotson, K. (2011). Tracking epistemic violence, tracking practices of silencing. Hypatia, 26(2), 236–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunning, D. (2015). Cognitive habits of intellectual arrogance and humility. In Presentation at the thrive center for human development conference on intellectual humility. Available online at https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=P6HUFiyq7yo. Accessed 5 Aug 2017.

  • Ehrlinger, J., & Dunning, D. (2003). How chronic self-views influence (and potentially mislead) estimates of performance. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 84, 5–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ehrlinger, J., Johnson, K., Banner, M., Dunning, D., & Kruger, J. (2008). Why the unskilled are unaware: Further explorations of (absent) self-insight among the incompetent. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 105(1), 98–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, M. (2007). Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, M. (2010). Can there be institutional virtues? In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guenther, C. L., & Alicke, M. D. (2010). Deconstructing the better-than-average effect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 99(5), 755–770.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hazlett, A. (2012). Higher-order epistemic attitudes and intellectual humility. Episteme, 9, 205–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, K. (2002). The politics of credibility. In L. Antony & C. Witt (Eds.), A mind of one’s own: Feminist essays on reason and objectivity (2nd ed., pp. 154–176). Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, K. (2012). The politics of intellectual self-trust. Social Epistemology, 26(2), 237–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karatjas, A., & Webb, J. (2015). The role of gender in grade perception in chemistry courses. Journal of College Science Teaching, 45(2), 30–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaufman, J. C. (2012). Self estimates of general, crystallized, and fluid intelligences in an ethnically diverse population. Learning and Individual Differences, 22, 118–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kruger, J., & Dunning, D. (1999). Unskilled and unaware of it: How difficulties in recognizing one’s own incompetence lead to inflated self-assessments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 77(6), 121–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Medina, J. (2012). Epistemology of resistance: Gender and racial oppression, epistemic injustice, and resistant imaginations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pohlhaus, G. (2014). Discerning the primary epistemic harm in cases of testimonial injustice. Social Epistemology, 28(2), 99–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szymanowicz, A., & Furnham, A. (2011). Gender differences in self-estimates of general, mathematical, spatial and verbal intelligence: Four meta-analyses. Learning and Individual Differences, 21, 493–504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Stumm, S., Chamorro-Premuzic, T., & Furnham, A. (2009). Decomposing self-estimates of intelligence: Structure and gender differences across 12 nations. British Journal of Psychology, 100, 429–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whitcomb, D., Battaly, H., Baehr, J., & Howard-Snyder, D. (2015). Intellectual humility: Owning our limitations. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 91(1), 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

My thanks to the audiences at the Southeastern Epistemology Workshop at Florida State University and the Philosophy Department at Vanderbilt University for their comments on this paper. Thanks also to Matthew Jernberg and two anonymous reviewers for their thoughtful and careful feedback on earlier drafts of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sarah Wright.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Wright, S. Epistemic harm and virtues of self-evaluation. Synthese 198 (Suppl 7), 1691–1709 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01993-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01993-x

Keywords

Navigation