Skip to main content
Log in

Free choice reasons

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I extend theories of nonmonotonic reasoning to account for reasons allowing free choice. My approach works with a wide variety of approaches to nonmonotonic reasoning and explains the connection between reasons for kinds of action and reasons for actions or subkinds falling under them. I use an Anderson–Kanger reduction of reason statements, identifying key principles in the logic of reasons.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. To avoid commitments about the metaphysical nature of reasons (see, e.g., Alvarez 2010, 2016; Hyman 2015), we might say more cautiously that reasons are specified by premises of practical reasoning.

  2. This problem appears originally in Aristotle, who speaks “of the man who, though exceedingly hungry and thirsty, and both equally, yet being equidistant from food and drink, is therefore bound to stay where he is” (De Caelo II 13 295b32–35; Buridan comments on this passage in his unpublished Expositio Textus De Caelo, where his example concerns a dog (Rescher 1959, p. 154)). A version of the puzzle reappears in al-Ghazali, who summarizes the position of “the philosophers” (primarily Avicenna): “Indeed, if in front of a thirsty person there are two glasses of water that are similar in every respect in relation to his purpose [of wanting to drink], it would be impossible for him to take either\(\ldots \)” (Al-Ghazali 2000, I, 41, pp. 32–39). It appears most poetically in Dante: “Between two foods alike in appetite, and like afar, a free man, I suppose, would starve before either of them he would bite” (Paradiso III, Canto IV, quoted in Rescher 1959, p. 152). The fabled donkey first appears in the writings of Buridan’s critics.

  3. Mill’s formulation suggests another way to understand the distinction between perfect and imperfect obligations, as narrow-scope and wide-scope obligations, respectively. Where x is some person or action, perfect obligations have the form \(\exists x OA(x)\), and imperfect obligations have the form \(O \exists x A(x)\) (with no commitment to \( \exists x OA(x)\)). Assuming constant domains, \(\exists x OA(x)\) implies \(O \exists x A(x)\). But the reverse does not hold. So, the situation described can recur for any de dicto obligation, whether or not it would traditionally be considered imperfect.

  4. Jonathan Dancy suggested the idea of applying Prichard’s question to reasons. The example is Buridan’s: “Debeo tibi denarium” (1977, p. 83).

  5. In speech, we would normally express the thoughts leading to the puzzle by using emphasis: I have no reason to give you Blackie. This is not equivalent to the sentence without emphasis, for it sets up a contrast class (Rooth 1992).

  6. Where the disjunction represents different epistemic possibilities rather than freedom to choose, in contrast, the disjunction or existential quantifier has wide scope. We can read I have reason to give you Blackie or Tawny—I’m not sure which as (I have reason to give you Blackie) or (I have reason to give you Tawny). Fox (2012, 2015) makes an analogous point with respect to imperatives; compare the two readings of Buy some teak or mahoganywhichever you prefer as opposed to whichever is in stock. See also Kaufmann (2012).

  7. This framing ignores a limitation of Horty’s system, which relies on the default logic of Reiter (1980); a default such as \(A \rightarrow B\) never appears as the conclusion of an argument. Gelfond et al. (1991) and Brewka (1992) have investigated expanding default logic to allow defaults to be derived from other defaults. As Horty’s system stands, the equivalent point would be that, in a default theory with the single default \(A \rightarrow (B \vee C)\), the defaults \(A \rightarrow B\) and \(A \rightarrow C\) would be inadmissible; they could enlarge the set of consequences.

  8. Assume for the sake of simplicity that each object in the domain has a constant in the language designating it.

  9. Note that material implication and counterfactual conditionals violate (38)a, b, and c and so are not suitable candidates for this connective.

  10. The most attractive accounts of nonmonotonic reasoning for my purpose are therefore based on pivotal valuation accounts (e.g., circumscription (McCarthy 1980; Lifschitz 1994), KLM (Kraus et al. 1990), or commonsense entailment (Asher 1995; Morreau 1997a)), since they automatically satisfy (40)b (Makinson 2005). Disjunctive Antecedents can however be added to theories based on pivotal rule accounts such as default logic (Reiter 1980; Horty 2012) or theories using maxfamily operations (Makinson and Torre 2000).

  11. I am again abstracting away from a limitation of Horty’s system, since default logic, as Reiter and Horty develop it, is purely sentential. A natural quantificational extension, however, would make \(\forall x (A \leadsto B)\) and \(A \leadsto \forall x B\) equivalent, where x is not free in A.

  12. It might seem more faithful to Cicero’s words to interpret him as saying something higher-order, familiar from Chisholm (1964), and interestingly elaborated in Rett (2016): If OA, then, for some B, B and B is a reason for A. On (41d), this becomes, if OA, then there is some B such that B and \(B | \!\!\!\approx A \leadsto \alpha \). But then, provided that \(OA, B | \!\!\!\approx A \leadsto \alpha \), OA defeasibly implies \(A \leadsto \alpha \). Presumably, if B is a reason for A, it doesn’t undermine A’s being a duty. Cutting out the intermediate step thus allows us to avoid higher-order quantification without any cost. I set aside here, incidentally, issues concerning the connection between reasons and motivational states. (See, e.g., Manne 2014).

  13. This would again require extending H to include embedded defaults, as in Brewka (1992).

  14. I am grateful to Jonathan Drake, Daniel Muñoz, and two anonymous referees for their comments on earlier drafts of this paper. I have learned much from Jonathan Dancy; his reading of Prichard in a seminar on practical space inspired the paper’s central idea. I am also grateful to conference participants at Washington University, especially, Jonathan Kvanvig, whose comments on my talk helped to shape the paper. Finally, I owe thanks to the Classical Theism Project for supporting this work.

References

  • Abusch, D. (2004). On the temporal composition of infinitives. In J. Guéron & J. Lecarme (Eds.), The syntax of time (pp. 27–53). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aczel, P., Israel, D., Katagiri, Y., & Peters, S. (Eds.). (1993). Situation theory and its applications (Vol. 3). Stanford: CSLI.

  • Al-Ghazali, I. (2000). The incoherence of the philosophers. (M. E. Marmura, Trans.). Provo: Brigham Young University Press.

  • Aloni, M. (2007). Free choice, modals and imperatives. Natural Language Semantics, 15, 65–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alonso-Ovalle, L. (2006). Disjunction in alternative semantics. Ph.D. thesis, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.

  • Alvarez, M. (2010). Kinds of reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Alvarez, M. (2016). Reasons for action, acting for reasons, and rationality. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-015-1005-9, (pp. 1-18).

  • Anderson, A. R. (1956). The formal analysis of normative systems. In N. Rescher (Ed.), The logic of decision and action (pp. 147–213). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, A. R. (1958). A reduction of deontic logic to alethic modal logic. Mind, 67, 100–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, A. R. (1967). Some nasty problems in the formal logic of ethics. Noûs, 1, 345–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, A. R., & Belnap, N. D. (1975). Entailment: The logic of relevance and necessity (Vol. I). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anglberger, A. J. J., Dong, H., & Roy, O. (2014). Open Reading without Free Choice. In F. Cariani, D. Grossi, J. Meheus, & X. Parent (Eds.), Deontic Logic and Normative Systems: 12th International Conference, DEON 2014, Ghent, Belgium, July 12–15, 2014: Proceedings (pp. 19–32). Heidelberg: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Anglberger, A. J. J., Gratzl, N., & Roy, Olivier. (2015). Obligation, free choice and the logic of weakest permission. Review of Symbolic Logic, 8(4), 807–827.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Antonelli, G. A. (2005). Grounded consequence for defeasible logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Åqvist, L. (1994). Deontic logic. In D. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic (Vol. II, pp. 605–714)., Extensions of classical logic Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arieli, O., & Avron, A. (1998). The value of the four values. Artificial Intelligence, 102(1), 97–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N. (1995). Commonsense entailment: A logic for some conditionals. In G. Crocco, L. Farinas del Cerro, & A. Hertzig (Eds.), Conditionals in artificial intelligence (pp. 103–145). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N., & Bonevac, D. (1996). Prima facie obligation. Studia Logica, 57, 19–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N., & Bonevac, D. (1997). Common sense obligation. In D. Nute (Ed.), Defeasible deontic logic (pp. 159–203). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N., & Morreau, M. (1991). Commonsense entailment: A modal, nonmonotonic theory of reasoning. In J. Mylopoulos and R. Reiter (Eds.), Proceedings of the Twelfth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence. San Mateo, Calif.: Morgan Kaufmann.

  • Asher, N., & Morreau, M. (1995). What some generic sentences mean. In J. Pelletier (Ed.), The generic book. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N. M., & Bonevac, D. (2005). Free choice permission is strong permission. Synthese, 145, 303–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barker, C. (2010). Free choice permission as resource-sensitive reasoning. Semantics and Pragmatics, 3, 1–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1983). Situations and attitudes. Cambridge: Bradford Books, MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belnap, N. D. (1977). A useful four-valued logic. In M. Dunn & G. Epstein (Eds.), Modern uses of multiple-valued logic (pp. 5–37). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bonevac, D. (1998). Against conditional obligation. Noûs, 32, 37–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonevac, D. (2016). Defaulting on reasons. Noûs, 50, 3. doi:10.1111/nous.12165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bresnan, J. (1972). Theory of complementation in english syntax. Ph.D. dissertation, MIT.

  • Brewka, G. (1992). A framework for cumulative default logics, Technical Report 92-042.

  • Brewka, G., Dix, J., & Konolige, K. (1997). Nonmonotonic reasoning. Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buridanus, J. (1977). Sophismata. Critical edition with an introduction by T. K. Scott. Stuttgart: Friedrich Frommann Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buridan, J. (2001). Summulae de Dialectica. (G. Klima, Trans.). New Haven: Yale University Press.

  • Cariani, F. (2017). Choice points for a modal theory of disjunction. Topoi, 36(1), 171–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chellas, B. (1980). Modal logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1964). The ethics of requirement. American Philosophical Quarterly, 1(2), 147–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chislenko, E. (2016). A solution for Buridan’s ass. Ethics, 126(2), 283–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (2004). Ethics without principles. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Devlin, K. (2006). Situation theory and situation semantics. In D. M. Gabbay & J. Woods (Eds.), Handbook of the history of logic, 7 (pp. 601–664). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dignum, F., Meyer, J.-J. C., & Wieringa, R. J. (1996). Free choice and contextually permitted actions. Studia Logica, 57(1), 193–220.

  • Duží, M., Jespersen, B., & Materna, P. (2010). Procedural semantics for hyperintensional logic: Foundations and applications for transparent intensional logic. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2012). Guide to Ground. In F. Correia & B. Schnieder (Eds.), 2012, Metaphysical grounding: Understanding the structure of reality (pp. 37–80). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2014). Truth-maker semantics for intuitionistic logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 43(2), 549–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (forthcoming). Truthmaker semantics. In The Blackwell philosophy of language handbook.

  • Fitting, M. (1992). Many-valued non-monotonic modal logics. In A. Nerode & M. Taitslin (Eds.), Logical foundations of computer science-Tver ’92 (pp. 139–150). Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (1978). Virtues and vices. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, C. (2012). Imperatives: A judgmental analysis. Handbook of Studia Logica, 100(4), 879–905.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, C. (2015). The semantics of imperatives. In S. Lappin & C. Fox (Eds.), Handbook of contemporary semantic theory (pp. 314–342). Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fusco, M. (2014). Free choice permission and the counterfactuals of pragmatics. Linguistics and Philosophy, 37(4), 275–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fusco, M. (2014). Factoring disjunction out of deontic modal puzzles. In F. Cariani, D. Grossi, J. Meheus, & X. Parent (Eds.), Deontic Logic and Normative Systems: 12th International Conference, DEON 2014, Ghent, Belgium, July 12–15, 2014: Proceedings (pp. 95–107). Heidelberg: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay, D. M. (1985). Theoretical foundations for non-monotonic reasoning in expert systems. In Logics and Models of Concurrent Systems, Volume 13 of the NATO ASI Series, (pp. 439–457).

  • Gelfond, M., Lifschitz, V., Przymusinska, H., & Truszczynski, M. (1991). Disjunctive defaults. In Proceedings of the Second International Conference on Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning: (pp. 230–237).

  • Geurts, B. (2005). Entertaining alternatives: Disjunctions as modals. Natural Language Semantics, 13, 383–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginsberg, M. L. (1987). Multi-valued logics. In M. L. Ginsberg (Ed.), Readings in nonmonotonic reasoning (pp. 251–258). Los Altos, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginsberg, M. L. (1988). Multivalued logics: A uniform approach to reasoning in AI. Computer Intelligence, 4, 256–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginzburg, J. (2012). The interactive stance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Givón, T. (1994). Irrealis and the subjunctive. Studies in Language, 18(2), 265–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (1998). On the logic of nonmonotonic conditionals and conditional probabilities: Predicate logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 27(1), 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horty, J. (1997). Nonmonotonic foundations for deontic logic. Nute, 1997, 17–44.

  • Horty, J. (2012). Reasons as defaults. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hyman, J. (2015). Action, knowledge, and will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, J. A. W. (1973). Free choice permission. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 74, 57–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kanger, S. (1971). 1957, 1971, New foundations for ethical theory. In R. Hilpinen (Ed.), Deontic logic: Introductory and systematic readings (pp. 36–58). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaufmann, M. (2012). Interpreting imperatives. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kearns, S., & Star, D. (2008). Reasons: Explanations or evidence? Ethics, 118, 31–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kearns, S., & Star, D. (2009). Reasons as evidence. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics 4 (pp. 215–42). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kleene, S. C. (1951). Introduction to metamathematics. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koons, R. C. (2000). Realism regained. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koons, R. C. (2014). Defeasible reasoning. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reasoning-defeasible/.

  • Kraus, S., Lehmann, D., & Magidor, M. (1990). Nonmonotonic reasoning, preferential models, and cumulative logics. Artificial Intelligence, 44, 167–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (2012). Notes on Daakie (Port Vato): Sounds and modality. In Proceedings of AFLA 18 (2011). Cambridge: Harvard University. (pp. 46–65).

  • Krifka, M. (2016). Realis and Non-Realis Modalities in Daakie (Ambrym, Vanuatu). In Proceedings of SALT 26.

  • Kvanvig, J. (2005). Reasons and contrastive reasons. Certain Doubts, November 21, 2005, http://certaindoubts.com/reasons-and-contrastive-reasons/.

  • Kvanvig, J. (2006). Arbitrary actions and arbitrary beliefs. In Certain doubts, March 8, 2006, http://certaindoubts.com/arbitrary-actions-and-arbitrary-beliefs/.

  • Lifschitz, V. (1989). Benchmark problems for formal nonmonotonic reasoning. In M. Reinfrank, J. de Kleer, M. L. Ginsberg, & E. Sandewall (Eds.), Non-monotonic reasoning (pp. 202–219). Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lifschitz, V. (1994). Circumscription. In D. Gabbay, C. Hogger, and J. Robinson (Eds.) Handbook of logic in artificial intelligence and logic programming. Volume 3: Nonmonotonic reasoning and uncertain reasoning. Oxford: Clarendon.

  • Lord, E., & Maguire, B. (Eds.). (2016). Weighing reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makinson, D. (2005). Bridges from classical to nonmonotonic logic. London: King’s College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makinson, D., & van der Torre, L. (2000). Input/output logics. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 29, 383–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manne, K. (2014). Internalism about reasons: Sad but true? Philosophical Studies, 167(1), 89–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markovits, J. (2014). Moral reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, J. (1980). Circumscription–A form of non-monotonic reasoning. Artificial Intelligence, 13, 27–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1861). Utilitarianism. London: Parker, Son and Bourn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morreau, M. (1997a). Fainthearted conditionals. The Journal of Philosophy, 94(4), 187–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morreau, M. (1997b). Reasons to think and act. Nute, 1997, 139–158.

  • O’Neill, O. (1996). Towards justice and virtue: A constructive account of practical reasoning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Portner, P. (1992). Situation Theory and the semantics of propositional expressions. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Massachusetts at Amherst.

  • Portner, P. (1997). The semantics of mood, complementation, and conversational force. Natural Language Semantics, 5, 167–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prichard, H. A. (1932). Duty and Ignorance of Fact. Proceedings of the British Academy, reprinted in J. MacAdam (Ed.), H. A. Prichard: Moral Writings. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002, (pp. 84–101).

  • Priest, G. (2008). An introduction to non-classical logic: From if to is. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1956). Quantifiers and propositional attitudes. The Journal of Philosophy, 53(5), 177–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rainbolt, G. (2000). Perfect and imperfect obligations. Philosophical Studies, 98, 233–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reiter, R. (1980). A logic for default reasoning. Artificial Intelligence, 13, 81–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1959). Choice without preference: A study of the history and of the logic of the problem of ‘Buridan’s ass. Kant-Studien, 51, 142–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1968). Many-valued logic. D. Reidel: D. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rett, J. (2016). On a shared property of deontic and epistemic modals. In N. Charlow & M. Chrisman (Eds.), Deontic modality (pp. 200–229). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rooth, M. (1992). A theory of focus interpretation. Natural Language Semantics, 1(1), 75–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Santorio, P. (forthcoming). Alternatives and truthmakers in conditional semantics.

  • Seligman, J., & Moss, L. S. (2011). Situation theory. In J. F. A. K. van Benthem & A. ter Meulen (Eds.), Handbook of logic and language (pp. 253–328). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Setiya, K. (2014). What is a reason to act? Philosophical studies, 167, 221–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snedegar, J. (2013). Contrastive reasons. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Southern California.

  • Snedegar, J. (2014). Contrastive reasons and promotion. Ethics, 125(1), 39–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snedegar, J. (2017). Contrastive reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • von Wright, G. H. (1951). Deontic logic. Mind, 60, 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S. (1950). Reason in ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wurmbrand, S. (2014). Tense and aspect in english infinitives. Linguistic Inquiry, 45(3), 403–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmermann, T. E. (2000). Free choice disjunction and epistemic possibility. Natural Language Semantics, 8, 255–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel Bonevac.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bonevac, D. Free choice reasons. Synthese 196, 735–760 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1540-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1540-7

Keywords

Navigation