Skip to main content
Log in

The harms of ignoring the social nature of science

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I argue that philosophers of science have an obligation to recognize and engage with the social nature of the sciences they assess if those sciences are morally relevant. Morally-relevant science is science that has the potential to risk harm to humans, non-humans, or the environment. My argument and the approach I develop are informed by an analysis of the philosophy of biology literature on the criticism of evolutionary psychology (EP), the study of the evolution of human psychology and behaviour. From this literature, I tease out two different methods of scientific critique. The first I call the “truth-detectional” approach. Those who take this approach are first and foremost concerned about the truth of EP claims as that truth can be determined by evidence. The second I call the “social-dimensional” approach. Those who take this approach talk about the production and truth of EP claims but within a social framework. On this account, the legitimacy and perceived legitimacy of EP claims are not separate from the institutional and social processes and values that lend to their production. I show that the truth-detectional approach risks harms to society and to the philosophy of science, but that the social-dimensional approach avoids these harms. Philosophers of science, therefore, should take a social-dimensional approach to the assessment of morally-relevant science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Because the normative thrust of my argument imposes obligations on philosophers of science for how they ought to conduct their research, I limit the scope of my argument to morally-relevant science. When harm is at issue, the minimal obligations I impose are justified. However, when harm is not on the table, the obligations seem inappropriate.

  2. Despite Gould not being a philosopher by profession, I think these particular works of his are ideal for my analysis. Gould’s criticisms of EP are nothing short of philosophical and they are familiar works in philosophy of biology. What’s more, Gould has taken a more social-dimensional approach in other works (e.g., Gould 1996). This demonstrates nicely that the two approaches I discuss in this paper are methods and need not be identified with a particular philosopher’s whole corpus of work.

  3. Reverse engineering is when an evolutionary psychologist “attempts to reconstruct the mind’s design from an analysis of the problems the mind must have evolved to solve” (Buller 2005, p. 92).

  4. Historical evidence in the context of EP would require information about “the sort of environmental ‘problem’ [human] cognitive mechanisms are responding to, the phenotypic and genotypic variation present, the structure of the relevant social groups, the gene flow between them, and other population parameters” (Richardson 2007, p. 84).

  5. However, see Douglas (2013) who marks a distinction between “cognitive” and “epistemic” values.

  6. On this he mentions Thornhill and Palmer (2001) theory of rape and how some see it to justify rape and “give support to rapists” (36).

  7. Psychology journals include: Personality Processes and Individual Differences,Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Behavioral and Brain Sciences. Interdisciplinary journals include: Human Nature, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences.

  8. For example, one or more of the four largest EP labs in the United States (i.e., Evolutionary Psychology Lab, co-directed by Todd A. Shackelford & Viviana A. Weeks-Shackelford; The Buss Lab, directed by David Buss; Center for Evolutionary Psychology, co-directed by Leda Cosmides and John Tooby; Evolution and Human Behaviour Laboratory, directed by Michael McCullough) have received funding for their research from, among others, the following major agencies: National Institute of Mental Health, National Institute of Health, National Science Foundation, Hogg Foundation, Gordon P. Getty Trust, John Templeton Foundation, Air Force Office of Scientific Research, The Fetzer Institute.

  9. Thank you very much to an anonymous reviewer for their insights on this discussion.

  10. I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this particular worry.

  11. Thank you to the anonymous reviewer who pointed out this particular challenge for the social-dimensional approach. It is in fact quite relevant to very near future work of mine in which I will be engaging sciences that are both epistemically more sophisticated and socially less harmful than evolutionary psychology.

  12. For discussions from philosophers who have dealt (in different ways) with this problem of balancing epistemic and social considerations in science analysis see, Brigandt (2015), Brown (2013), Douglas (2009), Kitcher (1985), Kourany (2010), Solomon (2001).

References

  • Baker, A. (2013). “Simplicity,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (fall edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/simplicity/.

  • Barkow, J. H., Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (Eds.). (1995). The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birke, L. (1986). Women, feminism and biology: The feminist challenge. Sussex: Wheatsheaf Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bluhm, R. (2013a). Self-fulfilling prophecies: The influence of gender stereotypes on functional neuroimaging research on emotion. Hypatia, 28(4), 870–886.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bluhm, R. (2013b). New research, old problems: Methodological and ethical issues in fMRI research examining sex/gender differences in emotion processing. Neuroethics, 6(2), 319–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. (2015). Social values influence the adequacy conditions of scientific theories: Beyond inductive risk. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 45(3), 326–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, M. J. (2013). Values in science beyond underdetermination and inductive risk. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 829–839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buller, D. (2005). Adapting minds: Evolutionary psychology and the persistent quest for human nature. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buss, D. (2008). Evolutionary psychology: The new science of the mind (3rd ed.). Boston: Pearson Education Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buss, D. M., & Schmitt, D. P. (1993). Sexual strategies theory: an evolutionary perspective on human mating. Psychological Review, 100(2), 204–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buss, D. M., & Schmitt, D. P. (2011). Evolutionary psychology and feminism. Sex Roles, 64(9–10), 768–787.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2009). Science, policy, and the value free ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2013). The value of cognitive values. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 796–806.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (2001). Human nature and the limits of science. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (2012). Processes of life: Essays in the philosophy of biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Eagly, A. H., & Wood, W. (1999). The origins of sex differences in human behavior: Evolved dispositions versus social roles. American Psychologist, 54(6), 408–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fausto-Sterling, A. (2000). Beyond difference: Feminism and evolutionary psychology. In H. Rose & S. Rose (Eds.), Poor Alas Darwin. New York: Harmony Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fausto-Sterling, A., Gowaty, P., & Zuk, M. (1997). Evolutionary psychology and Darwinian feminism. Feminist Studies, 14, 402–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, C. (2011). Feminist engagement with evolutionary psychology. Hypatia, 27(1), 52–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, C., & Plaisance, K. S. (2010). Socially relevant philosophy of science: an introduction. Synthese, 177(3), 301–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, M., Chang, R. S., & Garcia, J. L. (2013). Introduction. In M. Fisher, J. Garcia, & R. Sokol Chang (Eds.), Evolution’s empress: Darwinian perspectives on the nature of women (pp. 1–16). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gannett, L. (2010). Questions asked and unasked: How by worrying less about the ‘really real’ philosophers of science might better contribute to debates about genetics and race. Synthese, 177(3), 363–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gannon, L. (2002). A critique of evolutionary psychology. Psychology, Evolution & Gender, 4(2), 173–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1999). Adaptationism and the power of selection. Biology and Philosophy, 14, 181–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1997a). Darwinian fundamentalism. The New York Review of Books, 44, 34–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1997b). Evolution: The pleasures of pluralism. New York Review of Books, 44(11), 47–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J., & Lewontin, R. C. (1979). The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 205(1161), 581–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grosz, E. (1994). Sexual difference and the problem of essentialism. In N. Schor & E. Weed (Eds.), The Essential Difference (pp. 82–97). Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hankinson Nelson, L., & Nelson, J. (Eds.). (1996). Feminism, science, and the philosophy of science. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, D. J. (1989). Primate visions: Gender, race, and nature in the world of modern science. Abingdon: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H., Dupré, J., & Wylie, A. (Eds.). (2007). Value-free science? Ideals and illusions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katikireddi, S. V., & Valles, S. A. (2015). Coupled ethical–epistemic analysis of public health research and practice: Categorizing variables to improve population health and equity. American Journal of Public Health, 105(1), e36–e42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, E. F. (1985). Reflections on gender and science. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1985). Vaulting ambition: Sociobiology and the quest for human nature. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2001). Science, truth, and democracy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kourany, J. A. (2003). A philosophy of science for the twenty-first century. Philosophy of Science, 70(1), 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kourany, J. A. (2010). Philosophy of science after feminism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, E. (2001). Science gone astray: Evolution and rape. Michigan Law Review, 99(6), 1536–1559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, E. (2003). Violence against science: Rape and evolution. In C. B. Travis (Ed.), Evolution, Gender, and Rape (pp. 363–382). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, E. A., & Feldman, M. W. (2002). Evolutionary psychology: A view from evolutionary biology. Psychological Inquiry, 13(2), 150–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (1990). Science as social knowledge: Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1996). Cognitive and non-cognitive values in science: Rethinking the dichotomy. In Lynn Hankinson Nelson & Jack Nelson (Eds.), Feminism, science, and the philosophy of science (pp. 39–58). Boston: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (2002). The fate of knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (2013). Studying human behavior: How scientists investigate aggression and sexuality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., & Wolters, G. (Eds.). (2004). Science, values, and objectivity. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meynell, L. (2012). Evolutionary psychology, ethology, and essentialism (because what they don’t know can hurt us). Hypatia, 27(1), 3–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, J. (2010). In favour of a Millian proposal to reform biomedical research. Synthese, 177(3), 427–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, R. (2007). Evolutionary psychology as maladaptive psychology. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, S. S. (2010). Feminist philosophy of science: History, contributions, and challenges. Synthese, 177(3), 337–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, S. S. (2013). Sex itself: The search for male and female in the human genome. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rose, H., & Rose, S. (Eds.). (2000). Alas poor Darwin: Arguments against evolutionary psychology. New York City: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosser, S. V. (1997). Possible implications of feminist theories for the study of evolution. In P. Gowaty (Ed.), Feminism and evolutionary biology: Boundaries, intersections and frontiers (pp. 21–41). Berlin: Springer Science & Business Media.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shackelford, T. K., & Liddle, J. R. (2014). Understanding the mind from an evolutionary perspective: An overview of evolutionary psychology. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 5(3), 247–260.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shrader-Frechette, K. (2010). Conceptual analysis and special-interest science: Toxicology and the case of Edward Calabrese. Synthese, 177(3), 449–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2001). Social empiricism. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sork, V. L. (1997). Quantitative genetics, feminism, and evolutionary theories of gender Differences. In P. Gowaty (Ed.), Feminism and evolutionary biology: Boundaries intersections and frontiers (pp. 86–115). Berlin: Springer Science & Business Media.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (1995). The adapted mind. Biology and Philosophy, 10, 365–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2012). The evolved apprentice: How evolution made humans unique. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thornhill, R., & Palmer, C. T. (2001). A natural history of rape: Biological bases of sexual coercion. Cambridge: MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Travis, C. B. (2003). Talking evolution and selling difference. In Cheryl Brown Travis (Ed.), Evolution, gender, and rape (pp. 363–382). Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Trivers, R. (1972). Parental investment and sexual selection. In B. Campbell (Ed.), Sexual selection and the descent of man: 1871–1971 (pp. 136–179). Chicago: Aldine.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuana, N. (2010). Leading with ethics, aiming for policy: New opportunities for philosophy of science. Synthese, 177(3), 471–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuana, N. (2013). Embedding philosophers in the practices of science: Bringing humanities to the sciences. Synthese, 190(11), 1955–1973.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thank you very much to Carla Fehr, Ingo Brigandt, and members of the University of Waterloo FemLab (Alexandra Kraushaar, Kathryn Plaisance, Jamie Sewell, Jay Michaud, Sandra DeVries, Teresa Branch-Smith) for comments on earlier drafts. This research was supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sara Weaver.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Weaver, S. The harms of ignoring the social nature of science. Synthese 196, 355–375 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1479-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1479-8

Keywords

Navigation