Skip to main content
Log in

Com-Posting Experimental Futures: Pragmatists Making (Odd)Kin with New Materialists

  • Published:
Studies in Philosophy and Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

We are not what we know but what we are willing to learn.

Mary Catherine Bateson.

Peripheral Visions.

Abstract

Here I craft a case for recognizing the roots and patterns that ground the possibility of contemporary com-posting—as outlined in Donna Haraway’s Staying with the Trouble—by New Materialists and critical pragmatists, especially those who are affected by the social injustices and ill-advised practices of today’s formal education. I explore both Spinozan Ethics and American pragmatism (and the ways each seems to be and mean more in their juxtaposition and interaction) in order to fashion a pattern that affects educational thought and action. That pattern of affect/affecting is one Haraway calls “attunement” (via Vinciane Despret), a state of co-relation that makes “unexpected feats possible.” My goal is to encourage those educational theorists who dwell in a critical pragmatist archive and those who dwell in a New Materialist archive to “make kin,” to learn to play string figures with a companion species, as they com-post educational possibility in a world(view) where agency is both more limited and more widely-distributed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, Braidotti understands agency as a practice of “transmuting negative passions into productive and sustainable praxis” (Braidotti 2012, p. 122). Karen Barad (2003) on the other hand understands agency as an ethics of accountability, being accountable for what is excluded and what is included in our discursive practices.

  2. These are as various as theorists of literacy and new media practices in educational settings (see for example, Leander, K., & Sheehy, M. 2014. Spatializing literacy research and practice. New York: Peter Lang. and those pursuing affect theory in every domain (see Gregg, M. & Seigworth, G. (Eds). 2010. The affect theory reader. Durham, NC: Duke University Press).

  3. The literature is large and growing as theorists both learn from and critique Foucault. Consider for example Dolphijn, R. & van der Tuin, I. 2013. New materialism: Interviews and cartographies. Open Humanities Press. Available at http://openhumanitiespress.org/books/download/Dolphijn-van-der-Tuin_2013_New-Materialism.pdf; or Lemke, T. 2015. New materialisms: Foucault and the ‘government of things.’ Theory, Culture and Society 32,4: 3–25. See also Olssen, M. (2006). Michel Foucault: Materialism and education. Herndon, VA: Paradigm Publishers.

  4. My thanks to an early, anonymous reader of this essay who explicitly pointed this out to me.

  5. The Camille Stories represent a set of Haraway’s own imaginings (or what she calls an “invitation to a collective speculative fabulation”) of possible futures, of what it might look like to live and die as “children of compost.” The stories trace human children (all Camilles) born a generation after one another and always in sympoetic relation to monarch butterflies and other critters. In these Camille Communities, humans and critters together nurture capacities to respond to the world that make their own survival and flourishing more likely. The result—the desired goal—is “multi-species environmental justice.” Because it matters what ideas we think with, the capacity to tell speculative stories of promise and possibility is critical to the practice of response-ability.

  6. Matthew Stewart, in The Courtier and the Heretic (2006), notes that Spinoza struggled with “how to be moral in a secular society and how to seek wisdom where nothing is certain (p. 310). He also says, “Historians have called [the 17th century] “the century of genius”; but informed opinion at the time generally held that it was an age of exceptional wickedness. If there is a single thread that runs through the rich and confusing tapestry of seventeenth-century life, it is that this was an age of transition – the time in which the theocratic order of the medieval era ceded to the secular order of modernity” (p. 15).

  7. Spinoza notes in Section I, Proposition 29 of Ethics that “in Nature, there is nothing contingent: all things have been caused by the necessity of the divine nature to exist and produce an effect in a certain way.” He references all “things”, not all persons.

  8. Note that he does not rule out affects in non-human bodies.

  9. In the Appendix to Part I, Spinoza considers why general opinion rejects his view of Nature’s God as the necessary cause of all that exists and occurs. He notes that “(1) all men are ignorant of the cause of things, and (2) all men want to seek their advantage and are conscious of wanting this.” We think ourselves free to act in line with conscious goals and labor under the illusion that our efforts are the direct cause of our effects. This is, he suggests, never actually the case.

  10. See, for instance, the work of Walt Whitman and Ralph Waldo Emerson.

  11. It is also Dewey’s (1922) contention that every instance of an emotion such as fear is “never twice the same” because the emotion is a function of transaction that involves distinctive elements of persons and context.

  12. I would argue that among classical pragmatists, those who were female (e.g. Addams, Gilman, Follett and Cooper) and those who were not white (e.g. DuBois, Locke and again, Cooper) also understood that the world did not work for all the way it worked for those who were white, male and ostensibly Christian.

  13. Materialism as a metaphysical stance can go much further to suggest that all experience can—and can only—be parsed in terms of matter and its interactions and properties. This view is not Haraway’s, nor is it the materialism of the pragmatist.

  14. Lovejoy (1922) cites Boyd Bode, a pragmatist philosopher of education: “We do not find body and object and consciousness, but only body and object. …The process of intelligence is some- thing that goes on, not in our mind, but in things. … Even abstract ideas do not compel the adoption of a peculiarly " spiritual " or " psychic " existence, in the form of unanalyzable meanings”.

  15. Note that Dewey does not privilege action over thought or vice versa but understands the interplay of action and thought as productive.

  16. I use the term “truly educational” in distinction from “merely educational” analogous to Galway Kinnell’s distinction between the truly and merely personal. The latter is individualistic and determined; the former is interactional, situated, particular and indeterminate.

References

  • Addams, Jane. 1902. Democracy and social ethics. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Addams, Jane. 1912. Twenty years at Hull House. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Addams, J. 1907. Newer ideals of peace. In American philosophies, An anthropology, ed. L. Harris, S. Pratt, and A. Waters, 389–404. Malten, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ahmed, S. 2003. The cultural politics of emotion. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ahmed, S. 2010. The promise of happiness, 29–51. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barad, K. 2003. Posthumanist performativity: Toward an understanding of how matter comes to matter. Signs 28: 3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barad, K. 2006. Posthuman, all too human: Towards a new process ontology. Culture & Society 23(7–8): 197–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berlant, L. 2011. Cruel optimism. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Braidotti, Rosi. 2002. Metamorphoses: Towards a materialist theory of becoming. Cambridge: Polity Press/Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braidotti, R. 2012. Nomadic theory. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braidotti, R. 2013. The posthuman. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, J. 1997. The psychic life of power: Theories in subjection, 84–105. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, Anna Julia. 1852/1998. A voice from the South: The voice of Anna Julia Cooper, 88–108. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

  • Daly, Mary. 1992. Outercourse: The bedazzling voyage. New York: HarperOne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dea, S. 2008. Firstness, evolution and the absolute in Peirce’s Spinoza. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 44(4): 603–628.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J., “A Theory of Emotion I: Emotional Attitudes” (1894/1972) and “A Theory of Emotion II: The Significance of Emotions” (1895/1972), in John Dewey: The Early Works, 18821898, vol. 4, ed. Jo Ann Boydston. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

  • Dewey, J. 1897/1972. My pedagogic creed. In The Early Works, 18821898, vol. 5, ed. Jo Ann Boydston. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

  • Dewey, J. 1910/1976. How we think. In John Dewey: The Middle Works, vol. 6, ed. Jo Ann Boydston. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

  • Dewey, J. 1916/1976. Democracy and education. In The middle works: vol. 9: 1916, ed. Jo Ann Boydston. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

  • Dewey, J., 1922/1980. Human nature and conduct. In John Dewey: The Middle Works, 18991924, vol. 14, ed. Jo Ann Boydston Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

  • DuBois, W.E.B. 1914/1975/2002. Does race antipathy serve any good purpose? In American philosophies: An anthropology, ed. L. Harris, S. Pratt, and A. Waters, 134–149. Malten: Blackwell.

  • DuBois, W.E.B. 1903/1989. The souls of black folk. New York: Penguin Books.

  • Follett, M.P. (2003). Prophet of management, ed. Pauline Graham. Boston: Harvard Business Press.

  • Gilman, C. 1912/2002. Our brains and what ails them. (Originally The Forerunner, 3, 1912). In American philosophies: An anthropology, ed. L. Harris, S. Pratt, and A. Waters, 122–133. Malten: Blackwell.

  • Glaude, E. 2007. In a shade of blue: Pragmatism and the politics of Black America, 17–46. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. 1978. Ways of worldmaking. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, Donna. 2016. Staying with the trouble: Making kin in the Chuthulucene. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hardt, M., and A. Negri. 2001. Empire. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hickman, L. 2007. Pragmatism as post-postmodernism: Lessons from John Dewey. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • James, William. 1979. The will to believe. In The works of William James, ed. F.H. Burkhardt, F. Bowers, and I.K. Skrupskelis, 13–33. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koopman, C. 2016. Unruly pluralism and inclusive tolerance: The normative contribution of Jamesian pragmatism to non-ideal theory. Political Studies Review 14(1): 27–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koopman, C. 2015. Pragmatism as transition: Historicity and hope in James, Dewey, and Rorty. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koopman, C. 2017. Contesting injustice: Why pragmatist political thought needs Du Bois. In Pragmatism and Justice, ed. Susan Dieleman, David Rondel, and Chris Voparil. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, A. 1942/2002. Cultural pluralism. In American philosophies: An anthropology, ed. L. Harris, S. Pratt, and A. Waters, 433–445. Malten: Blackwell.

  • Lovejoy, A.O. 1922. Pragmatism and the new materialism. Journal of Philosophy 19(1): 5–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Medina, J. 2011. The relevance of credibility excess in a proportional view of epistemic injustice: Differential epistemic authority and the social imaginary. Social Epistemology: A Journal of Knowledge, Culture and Policy 25(1): 15–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Medina, J. 2013. Introduction: Resistance, democratic sensibilities, and the cultivation of perplexity. The epistemology of resistance: Gender and racial oppression, epistemic injustice, and resistant imaginations, 3–26. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nadler, S. 2011. A book forged in hell: Spinoza’s scandalous treatise and the birth of the secular age. (Kindle iOS version). Retrieved from www.amazon.com.

  • Noddings, N. 1992. The challenge to care in schools. New York: Teachers College Press. Chapters 2 and 4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noddings, N. 2010. Moral education and caring. Theory and Research in Education 8(2): 145–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C.S. 1877. The fixation of belief. Popular Science Monthly 12: 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegfried, C.H. 1996. Pragmatism and feminism: Reweaving the social fabric. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, B. 1670/1862. Tractatus theologico-politicus. Translated by Robert Willis. London: Trubner & Co. https://en.wikisource.org/wiki/Theologico-Political_Treatise_1862.

  • Spinoza, B. 2017. Ethics demonstrated in geometrical order. Translated and edited by Jonathan Bennett. (Early Modern Texts). www.earlymoderntexts.com/assets/pds/spinoza1665.pdf.

  • Stewart, M. 2006. The courtier and the heretic: Leibniz, Spinoza, and the fate of God in the modern world. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, M. 2014. Nature’s God: The heretical origins of the American republic. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Townes, E. 2006. Womanist ethics and the cultural production of evil. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waks, L. 1998. Post-experimental pragmatism. Studies in Philosophy and Education 17(1): 17–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Barbara S. Stengel.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Stengel, B.S. Com-Posting Experimental Futures: Pragmatists Making (Odd)Kin with New Materialists. Stud Philos Educ 38, 7–29 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-018-9627-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-018-9627-2

Keywords

Navigation