Skip to main content
Log in

The use of scientific methods and models in the philosophy of science

  • Published:
Scientometrics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

What is the relation between philosophy of science and the sciences? As Pradeu et al. (British Journal for the Philosophy of Science https://doi.org/10.1086/715518, 2021) and Khelfaoui et al. (Synthese 199:6219, 2021) recently show, part of this relation is constituted by “philosophy in science”: the use of philosophical methods to address questions in the sciences. But another part is what one might call “science in philosophy”: the use of methods drawn from the sciences to tackle philosophical questions. In this paper, we focus on one class of such methods and examine the role that model-based methods play within “science in philosophy”. To do this, we first build a bibliographic coupling network with Web of Science records of all papers published in philosophy of science journals from 2000 to 2020 (\(N=9217\)). After detecting the most prominent communities of papers in the network, we use a supervised classifier to identify all papers that use model-based methods. Drawing on work in cultural evolution, we also propose a model to represent the evolution of methods in each one of these communities. Finally, we measure the strength of cultural selection for model-based methods during the given time period by integrating model and data. Results indicate not only that model-based methods have had a significant presence in philosophy of science over the last two decades, but also that there is considerable variation in their use across communities. Results further indicate that some communities have experienced strong selection for the use of model-based methods but that other have not; we validate this finding with a logistic regression of paper methodology on publication year. We conclude by discussing some implications of our findings and suggest that model-based methods play an increasingly important role within “science in philosophy” in some but not all areas of philosophy of science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Ainsworth, P. (2011). Ontic structural realism and the principle of the identity of indiscernibles. Erkenntnis, 75(1), 67–84.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Alspector-Kelly, M. (2011). Why safety doesn’t save closure. Synthese, 183(2), 127–142.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Bangu, S. (2013). Indispensability and explanation. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64(2), 255–277.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, J. A. (2014). Description and the problem of priors. Erkenntnis, 79(6), 1343–1353.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Biddle, J. (2013). State of the field: Transient underdetermination and values in science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 44(1), 124–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blondel, V. D., Guillaume, J.-L., Lambiotte, R., & Lefebvre, E. (2008). Fast unfolding of communities in large networks. Journal of statistical mechanics: Theory and Experiment, 2008(10), P10008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2003). Horizontal models: From bakers to cats. Philosophy of Science, 70(3), 609–627.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Bolker, B. M. (2008). Ecological models and data in R. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonino, G., Maffezioli, P., Petrovich, E., & Tripodi, P. (2022). When philosophy (of science) meets formal methods: A citation analysis of early approaches between research fields. Synthese, 200(2), 177.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Boyack, K., Börner, K., & Klavans, R. (2009). Mapping the structure and evolution of chemistry research. Scientometrics, 79(1), 45–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bright, L. K. (2017). On fraud. Philosophical Studies, 174(2), 291–310.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Brössel, P. (2015). Keynes’s coefficient of dependence revisited. Erkenntnis, 80(3), 521–553.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. P. (2013). Policing epistemic communities. Episteme, 10(4), 403.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byron, J. M. (2007). Whence philosophy of biology? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58(3), 409–422.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chandrasekar, P. and Qian, K. (2016). The impact of data preprocessing on the performance of a naive bayes classifier. In 2016 IEEE 40th Annual Computer Software and Applications Conference (COMPSAC), volume 2, pp. 618–619. IEEE.

  • Clatterbuck, H. (2015). Drift beyond Wright-Fisher. Synthese, 192(11), 3487–3507.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Doppelt, G. (2005). Empirical success or explanatory success: What does current scientific realism need to explain? Philosophy of Science, 72(5), 1076–1087.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ducheyne, S. (2012). Scientific representations as limiting cases. Erkenntnis, 76(1), 73–89.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Eck, N. J., & Waltman, L. (2009). How to normalize cooccurrence data? An analysis of some well-known similarity measures. Journal of the American Society for Information Science and Technology, 60(8), 1635–1651.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fagan, M. B. (2012). The joint account of mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 79(4), 448–472.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, S. C., Knobe, J., Wheeler, G., & Woodcock, B. A. (2021). Changing use of formal methods in philosophy: Late 2000s vs. late 2010s. Synthese, 199, 14555.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., Nguyen, J., et al. (2020). Modelling nature: An opinionated introduction to scientific representation. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelfert, A. (2011). Mathematical formalisms in scientific practice: From denotation to model-based representation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 42(2), 272–286.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glänzel, W., & Thijs, B. (2017). Using hybrid methods and ‘core documents’ for the representation of clusters and topics: The astronomy dataset. Scientometrics, 111, 1071–1087.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E., & Stotz, K. (2008). Experimental philosophy of science. Philosophy Compass, 3(3), 507–521.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heesen, R. (2019). The credit incentive to be a maverick. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 76, 5–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopcroft, J., Khan, O., Kulis, B., & Selman, B. (2004). Tracking evolving communities in large linked networks. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 101(suppl–1), 5249–5253.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huang, L., Cai, Y., Zhao, E., Zhang, S., Shu, Y., & Fan, J. (2022). Measuring the interdisciplinarity of information and library science interactions using citation analysis and semantic analysis. Scientometrics, 127, 6733.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huggett, N., & Wüthrich, C. (2018). The (a) temporal emergence of spacetime. Philosophy of Science, 85(5), 1190–1203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karsdorp, F., Manjavacas, E., Fonteyn, L., & Kestemont, M. (2020). Classifying evolutionary forces in language change using neural networks. Evolutionary Human Sciences, 2, e50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kessler, M. M. (1963). Bibliographic coupling between scientific papers. American Documentation, 14(1), 10–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khelfaoui, M., Gingras, Y., Lemoine, M., & Pradeu, T. (2021). The visibility of philosophy of science in the sciences, 1980–2018. Synthese, 199, 6219.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2007). Experimental philosophy. Philosophy Compass, 2(1), 81–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kochiras, H. (2011). Gravity’s cause and substance counting: Contextualizing the problems. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 42(1), 167–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kulvicki, J. (2007). What is what it’s like? Introducing perceptual modes of presentation. Synthese, 156(2), 205–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leitgeb, H. (2013). Scientific philosophy, mathematical philosophy, and all that. Metaphilosophy, 44(3), 267–275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levins, R. (1966). The strategy of model building in population biology. American Scientist, 54(4), 421–431.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, P. J. (2007). Empty waves in Bohmian quantum mechanics. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58(4), 787–803.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2016). Experimental philosophy of science. A Companion to Experimental Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118661666.ch33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., & Cohen, K. (2012). An evidence-based study of the evolutionary behavioral sciences. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63(1), 177–226.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malaterre, C., Chartier, J.-F., & Pulizzotto, D. (2019). What is this thing called philosophy of science? A computational topic-modeling perspective, 1934–2015. HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science, 9(2), 215–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malaterre, C., Lareau, F., Pulizzotto, D., & St-Onge, J. (2021). Eight journals over eight decades: A computational topic-modeling approach to contemporary philosophy of science. Synthese, 199(1), 2883–2923.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Malaterre, C., Pulizzotto, D., & Lareau, F. (2020). Revisiting three decades of biology and philosophy: A computational topic-modeling perspective. Biology & Philosophy, 35(1), 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martini, C., & Pinto, M. F. (2017). Modeling the social organization of science. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 7(2), 221–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayo-Wilson, C., & Zollman, K. J. (2021). The computational philosophy: Simulation as a core philosophical method. Synthese, 199, 3647.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • McCallum, A., Nigam, K., et al. (1998). A comparison of event models for naive Bayes text classification. AAAI-98 Workshop on Learning for Text Categorization, 752(1), 41–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mizrahi, M. and Dickinson, M. (2020). Argumentation in philosophical practice: An empirical study. In Evidence, Persuasion & Diversity. Proceedings of OSSA 12, 3–6 June 2020.

  • Moretti, F. (2000). Conjectures on world literature. New Left Review, 1, 54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newberry, M. G., Ahern, C. A., Clark, R., & Plotkin, J. B. (2017). Detecting evolutionary forces in language change. Nature, 551(7679), 223–226.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noichl, M. (2021). Modeling the structure of recent philosophy. Synthese, 198(6), 5089–5100.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, C. (2019). The natural selection of conservative science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 76, 24–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oreskes, N., Stainforth, D. A., & Smith, L. A. (2010). Adaptation to global warming: Do climate models tell us what we need to know? Philosophy of Science, 77(5), 1012–1028.

    Google Scholar 

  • Overton, J. A. (2013). “Explain” in scientific discourse. Synthese, 190(8), 1383–1405.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pence, C. H., & Ramsey, G. (2018). How to do digital philosophy of science. Philosophy of Science, 85(5), 930–941.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pradeu, T., Lemoine, M., Khelfaoui, M., & Gingras, Y. (2021). Philosophy in science: Can philosophers of science permeate through science and produce scientific knowledge? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. https://doi.org/10.1086/715518

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, G. (2013). Organisms, traits, and population subdivisions: Two arguments against the causal conception of fitness? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64(3), 589–608.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, G., & De Block, A. (2017). Is cultural fitness hopelessly confused? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 68(2), 305–328.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, G., & De Block, A. (2021). The Dynamics of Science: Computational Frontiers in History and Philosophy of Science. Pittsburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Renne, B. (2008). Public and private communication are different: Results on relative expressivity. Synthese, 165(2), 225–245.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Romasanta, A. K. S., van der Sijde, P., & van Muijlwijk-Koezen, J. (2020). Innovation in pharmaceutical r &d: Mapping the research landscape. Scientometrics, 125, 1801–1832.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaw, J. R. (2013). De se belief and rational choice. Synthese, 190(3), 491–508.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Sindi, S. S., & Dale, R. (2016). Culturomics as a data playground for tests of selection: Mathematical approaches to detecting selection in word use. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 405, 140–149.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sprenger, J., & Hartmann, S. (2019). Bayesian philosophy of science. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2008). Fictions in science: Philosophical essays on modeling and idealization. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tanaka, M. M., Godfrey-Smith, P., & Kerr, B. (2020). The dual landscape model of adaptation and niche construction. Philosophy of Science, 87(3), 478–498.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Thicke, M. (2020). Evaluating formal models of science. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 51(2), 315–335.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thijs, B., Zhang, L., & Glänzel, W. (2015). Bibliographic coupling and hierarchical clustering for the validation and improvement of subject-classification schemes. Scientometrics, 105, 1453–1467.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tugby, M. (2021). Grounding theories of powers. Synthese, 198(12), 11187–11216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weatherall, J. O., O’Connor, C., & Bruner, J. P. (2020). How to beat science and influence people: Policymakers and propaganda in epistemic networks. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 71(4), 1157–1186.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Weingart, S. B. (2015). Finding the history and philosophy of science. Erkenntnis, 80(1), 201–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2007). Three kinds of idealization. The Journal of Philosophy, 104(12), 639–659.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2012). Simulation and similarity: Using models to understand the world. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M., & Muldoon, R. (2009). Epistemic landscapes and the division of cognitive labor. Philosophy of Science, 76(2), 225–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, G. (2013). Models, models, and models. Metaphilosophy, 44(3), 293–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wray, K. B. (2010). Philosophy of science: What are the key journals in the field? Erkenntnis, 72(3), 423–430.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wray, K. B., & Bornmann, L. (2015). Philosophy of science viewed through the lense of “referenced publication years spectroscopy”(RPYS). Scientometrics, 102, 1987–1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, S. (1931). Evolution in mendelian populations. Genetics, 16(2), 97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zollman, K. J. (2007). The communication structure of epistemic communities. Philosophy of Science, 74(5), 574–587.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zollman, K. J. (2018). The credit economy and the economic rationality of science. The Journal of Philosophy, 115(1), 5–33.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

A pre-print version of this paper is available at http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/20885/. Special thanks to Thomas Pradeu, Charles Pence, Kevin Zollman, and many others for very helpful feedback on earlier versions of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rafael Ventura.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

There is no conflict of interest to declare.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendices

Appendix 1: Naive Bayes classifier

To label papers with respect to their methodology, we used a multinomial naive Bayes classifier. Naive Bayes classifiers assign an item to a class by maximizing the following expression:

$$\begin{aligned} Pr(q_i|w_1,..., w_m) = \frac{ Pr(w_1,..., w_m|q_i) Pr(q_i)}{ Pr(w_1,..., w_m) } \quad , \end{aligned}$$
(1)

where \(Pr(q_i|w_1,..., w_m)\) is the probability of the item belonging to class \(q_i\) given that the item has features \(w_1,..., w_m\), \(Pr(q_i)\) is the unconditional probability of the class, and \(Pr(w_1,..., w_m)\) is the unconditional probability of the features. Items correspond to papers, classes correspond to the two types of methods that a paper might use (model-based method vs. no model-based method), and features correspond to the number of times that a word occurred in a paper’s abstract and the number of times that a last name appears in a paper’s reference section. These numbers are integers because words can appear any number of times in the abstract and last names can appear any number of times in the reference section.

Appendix 2: Wright-Fisher model

To build a model for the cultural evolution of methods in philosophy of science, we assumed that papers are chosen to reproduce in proportion to how many papers of each type were available in the previous year. The probability that an individual of a given type—say, papers that use model-based methods—will be chosen to reproduce is given by:

$$\begin{aligned} p = \frac{ i_{t} \cdot (1+s) }{ i_{t} \cdot (1+s) + j_{t}} \quad , \end{aligned}$$
(2)

where \(i_{t}\) is the number of papers of that type in generation t, \(j_{t} = N_{t} - i_{t}\) is the number of individuals of the other type, and s is the selection coefficient measuring the strength of selection. Generations correspond to publication years. The parameter s is positive when selection favors the focal type, negative when selection favors the non-focal type, and zero when selection does not favor any type.

Conversely, the probability that a paper of the other type—papers that do not use model-based methods—will be chosen to reproduce is given by:

$$\begin{aligned} q = \frac{ j_{t} }{ i_{t} \cdot (1+s) + j_{t}} \quad , \end{aligned}$$
(3)

where terms are defined as before.

Further, we assume that the population of papers grows over time because papers never leave the publication record. The probability that a population with \(i_{t}\) papers of a given type in generation t transitions to a population with \(i_{t+1}\) individuals of the same type in generation \(t+1\) is thus given by:

$$\begin{aligned} Pr(i_{t+1}|i_{t}) = { N_{t+1} - N_{t} \atopwithdelims ()i_{t+1} - i_{t} } \cdot p^{ i_{t+1} - i_{t} } \cdot q^{ j_{t+1} - j_{t} }, \end{aligned}$$
(4)

where \({ N_{t+1} - N_{t} \atopwithdelims ()i_{t+1} - i_{t} }\) is the number of combinations we can obtain by choosing \(i_{t+1} - i_{t}\) individuals of the focal type in a group of \(N_{t+1} - N_{t}\) individuals, \(p^{ i_{t+1}-i_{t} }\) is the probability that \(i_{t+1} - i_{t}\) individuals of the focal type will be chosen to enter the population, and \(q^{ j_{t+1}-j_{t} }\) is the probability that \(j_{t+1} - j_{t}\) individuals of the non-focal type will be chosen to enter the population. Expression (4) therefore gives the probability that a population with \(i_{t}\) papers of a given type will transition to a population with \(i_{t+1}\) individuals of the same type by growing from size \(N_{t}\) to size \(N_{t+1}\).

Appendix 3: Maximum-likelihood estimation

To estimate the strength of selection (s) for or against the use of model-based methods, we used the technique of maximum-likelihood estimation. That is, we take \(\hat{s}\) be the value that maximizes the following expression:

$$\begin{aligned} \hat{s} = \mathop {{\textrm{argmax}}}\limits _{s \in [-1,1]} \quad \sum _{t=2000}^{2020} log \left( Pr(i_{t+1}|i_{t}) \right) \quad , \end{aligned}$$
(5)

where \(\hat{s}\) is the maximum-likelihood estimate of selection for or against the use of model-based methods in a particular community, \(Pr(i_{t+1}|i_{t})\) is given by expression (4), and the sum is over the entire time period considered here—namely, from 2000 to 2020. Note that we take the log of \(Pr(i_{t+1}|i_{t})\) simply to facilitate computation, as values for \(Pr(i_{t+1}|i_{t})\) can be very small. Note also that equation (5) correspond to the estimate of selection for a particular community, so \(\hat{s}\) must be estimated separately for each community of papers.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ventura, R. The use of scientific methods and models in the philosophy of science. Scientometrics 129, 1255–1276 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11192-024-04931-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11192-024-04931-6

Keywords

Navigation