Skip to main content
Log in

Dynamics in risk taking with a low-probability hazard

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The experiment reported in this paper identifies the effects of experience on revealed attitudes toward risk. Subjects in the experiment encountered an uncertain risk of experiencing a negative income shock over multiple periods and were able to purchase insurance at the start of each period. Subjects engaged in greater risk taking, insuring less frequently, when faced with the same risk over multiple periods. Subjects weighted experienced outcomes proportionately, in a manner consistent with rational Bayesian inference and contrary to the theory that individuals exhibit recency bias. On the other hand, subjects assigned a greater weight to outcomes that directly impacted their earnings compared to observed outcomes that had no effect on income. Unexplained autocorrelation across subjects’ choices suggests that inertia also plays an important role in repeated risk settings. I explore the relevance of these findings to public policy aimed at influencing market outcomes in the presence of infrequent environmental hazards.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The term “Matched Property” was used to emphasize the fact that subjects would be matched with the same property for 50 decision periods, in contrast with the One-shot round, where the property, and associated risk, changed for each decision period.

  2. Which sequence the subject encountered in the Repeat round was varied between subjects, so that no subject encountered the same sequence in both One-shot and Repeat rounds.

  3. There is, however, substantial evidence that people weight probabilities idiosyncratically (Tversky & Kahneman 1992) and behave differently when risk is ambiguously described (Ellsberg 1961). Nevertheless, these tendencies are better understood as manifestations of preference or perception rather than a reflection of incomplete information.

  4. Shafran estimates a similar model using subjects’ decisions in a repeated risk task. A key difference in his model is that the memory parameter weights the effects of both prior outcomes and prior choices, whereas the memory parameter expressed in Eqs. 4 and 5 weights only prior outcomes. The weighting of prior choices represents the persistence of choice inertia effects, which I model in Section 3.2.6.

  5. One can also reframe the example so that choosing to insure at t = 1 imparts a positive inertia effect on the probability of insuring at t = 2. The probability of insuring at t = 2 would then be p q(1 + δ). The same comparison with respect to p still obtains because lower probability risks now imply diminished chances of receiving positive inertia from insuring at time 1.

  6. Subjects in the low premium treatment completed only 45 periods in the dynamic round and did not complete a post-experiment survey.

  7. Note that the regression including the survey variables has fewer observations and does not control for the insurance premium. The reason for this is that surveys were not added to the experiment until after low premium treatment was completed, so no survey data are available for the 23 subjects who encountered the low premium.

  8. The details of this method are discussed in Section 8.7 of Train (2009).

  9. Shafran does report structural estimates for an adaptive learning model, but not for a strictly Bayesian one.

References

  • Anderson, L.R., & Holt, C.A. (1997). Information cascades in the laboratory. American Economic Review, 87(5), 847–862.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andersson, H. (2011). Perception of own death risk: An assessment of road-traffic mortality risk. Risk Analysis, 31(7), 1069–1082.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asparouhova, E., Hertzel, M., Lemmon, M. (2009). Inference from streaks in random outcomes: Experimental evidence on beliefs in regime shifting and the law of small numbers. Management Science, 55(11), 1766–1782.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Atreya, A., Ferreira, S., Michel-Kerjan, E. (2015). What drives households to buy flood insurance? New evidence from Georgia. Ecological Economics, 117, 153–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barron, G., & Erev, I. (2003). Small feedback-based decisions and their limited correspondence to description-based decisions. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 16(3), 215–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bin, O., & Landry, C.E. (2013). Changes in implicit flood risk premiums: Empirical evidence from the housing market. Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 65(3), 361–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Breman, A. (2011). Give more tomorrow: Two field experiments on altruism and intertemporal choice. Journal of Public Economics, 95(11), 1349–1357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Browne, M.J., & Hoyt, R.E. (2000). The demand for flood insurance: Empirical evidence. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 20(3), 291–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Browne, M.J., Knoller, C., Richter, A. (2015). Behavioral bias and the demand for bicycle and flood insurance. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 50(2), 141–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cai, J., de Janvry, A., Sadoulet, E. (2016). Subsidy policies with learning from stochastic experiences. Working Paper.

  • Davis, L. (2004). The effect of health risk on housing values: Evidence from a cancer cluster. The American Economic Review, 94(5), 1693–1704.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dixon, L.S., Turner, S., Clancy, N., Seabury, S.A., Overton, A. (2006). The national flood insurance program’s market penetration rate: Estimates and policy implications. RAND, Santa Monica CA.

  • Ellsberg, D. (1961). Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75(4), 643–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Erev, I., & Haruvy, E. (2013). Learning and the economics of small decisions. The Handbook of Experimental Economics, 2.

  • Erev, I., Ert, E., Roth, A.E., Haruvy, E., Herzog, S.M., Hau, R., Hertwig, R., Stewart, T., West, R., Lebiere, C. (2010). A choice prediction competition: Choices from experience and from description. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 23(1), 15–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, J. (2014). Learning about an infrequent event: Evidence from flood insurance take-up in the United States. American Economic Journal: Applied Economics, 6(3), 206–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ganderton, P.T., Brookshire, D.S., McKee, M., Stewart, S., Thurston, H. (2000). Buying insurance for disaster-type risks: Experimental evidence. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 20(3), 271–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilovich, T., Vallone, R., Tversky, A. (1985). The hot hand in basketball: On the misperception of random sequences. Cognitive Psychology, 17(3), 295–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hau, R., Pleskac, T.J., Kiefer, J., Hertwig, R. (2008). The description–experience gap in risky choice: The role of sample size and experienced probabilities. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 21(5), 493–518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hertwig, R., & Erev, I. (2009). The description–experience gap in risky choice. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13(12), 517–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hertwig, R., Barron, G., Weber, E.U., Erev, I. (2004). Decisions from experience and the effect of rare events in risky choice. Psychological Science, 15(8), 534–539.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jessup, R.K., Bishara, A.J., Busemeyer, J.R. (2008). Feedback produces divergence from prospect theory in descriptive choice. Psychological Science, 19(10), 1015–1022.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, E.J., Hershey, J., Meszaros, J., Kunreuther, H. (1993). Framing, probability distortions, and insurance decisions. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 7 (1), 35–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47(2), 263–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J.L., Thaler, R.H. (1991). Anomalies: The endowment effect, loss aversion, and status quo bias. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 5(1), 193–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kellens, W., Terpstra, T., De Maeyer, P. (2013). Perception and communication of flood risks: A systematic review of empirical research. Risk Analysis, 33(1), 24–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kousky, C. (2017). Disasters as learning experiences or disasters as policy opportunities? Examining flood insurance purchases after hurricanes. Risk Analysis, 37(3), 517–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kousky, C., & Michel-Kerjan, E. (2015). Examining flood insurance claims in the United States: Six key findings. Journal of Risk and Insurance, 84(3), 819–850.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kunreuther, H.C., & Michel-Kerjan, E.O. (2009). At war with the weather: Managing large-scale risks in a new era of catastrophes. MIT Press.

  • Kunreuther, H., & Pauly, M. (2006). Rules rather than discretion: Lessons from Hurricane Katrina. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 33(1-2), 101–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kunreuther, H., & Slovic, P. (1978). Economics, psychology, and protective behavior. American Economic Review, 68(2), 64–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laury, S.K., McInnes, M.M., Swarthout, J.T. (2009). Insurance decisions for low-probability losses. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 39(1), 17–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, R.J. (2012). Failing to learn from experience about catastrophes: The case of hurricane preparedness. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 45(1), 25–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michel-Kerjan, E.O., & Kousky, C. (2010). Come rain or shine: Evidence on flood insurance purchases in Florida. Journal of Risk and Insurance, 77(2), 369–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michel-Kerjan, E., & Kunreuther, H. (2011). Redesigning flood insurance. Science, 333(6041), 408–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nevo, I., & Erev, I. (2012). On surprise, change, and the effect of recent outcomes. Frontiers in Psychology, 3, 1–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Donoghue, T., & Rabin, M. (1999). Doing it now or later. American Economic Review, 89(1), 103–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Offerman, T.J.S., & Sonnemans, J.H. (2001). Is the quadratic scoring rule behaviorally incentive compatible? CREED Working Paper.

  • Palm, R., & Hodgson, M.E. (1992). After a California earthquake: Attitude and behavior change. University of Chicago Press.

  • Pielke, R.A. Jr, & Downton, M.W. (2000). Precipitation and damaging floods: Trends in the United States, 1932–97. Journal of Climate, 13(20), 3625–3637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabin, M. (2002). Inference by believers in the law of small numbers. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 117(3), 775–816.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shafran, A.P. (2011). Self-protection against repeated low probability risks. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 42(3), 263–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shavell, S. (2014). A general rationale for a governmental role in the relief of large risks. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 49(3), 213–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slovic, P., Fischhoff, B., Lichtenstein, S., Corrigan, B., Combs, B. (1977). Preference for insuring against probable small losses: Insurance implications. Journal of Risk and Insurance, 44(2), 237–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R.H., & Benartzi, S. (2004). Save more tomorrow: Using behavioral economics to increase employee saving. Journal of Political Economy, 112(S1), S164–S187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toplak, M.E., West, R.F., Stanovich, K.E. (2011). The cognitive reflection test as a predictor of performance on heuristics-and-biases tasks. Memory & Cognition, 39(7), 1275–1289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Train, K.E. (2009). Discrete choice methods with simulation. Cambridge University Press.

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Science, 185(4157), 1124–1131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5(4), 297–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Boven, L., & Loewenstein, G. (2005). Empathy gaps in emotional perspective taking. Other minds: how humans bridge the divide between self and others. New York: Guilford Press.

  • Viscusi, W.K, & O’Connor, C. J. (1984). Adaptive responses to chemical labeling: Are workers Bayesian decision makers? The American Economic Review, 74(5), 942–956.

    Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi, W.K, & Zeckhauser, R. J. (2015). The relative weights of direct and indirect experiences in the formation of environmental risk beliefs. Risk Analysis, 35 (2), 318–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Volkman-Wise, J. (2015). Representativeness and managing catastrophe risk. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 51(3), 267–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Josh Tasoff, Monica Capra, Paul Zak, Thomas Kniesner, Margaret Walls, and Peiran Jiao for discussion and valuable input. Insightful comments from Kip Viscusi, Justin Gallagher and an anonymous referee helped shape the final version of the paper. I would also like to thank Michael McBride and the ESSL staff for assisting with sessions run at UC Irvine. Institutional Review Board approval was obtained from Claremont Graduate University (CGU) [IRB #2251].

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrew Royal.

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

(PDF 1.15 MB)

Appendices

Appendix A: Additional Tables & Figures

Table 5 Predetermined disaster sequences

Appendix B: Selected screenshots

(See Online Appendix for full instrument.)

Fig. 3
figure 3

Example of One-shot round decision screen

Fig. 4
figure 4

Example of repeated choice round decision screen

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Royal, A. Dynamics in risk taking with a low-probability hazard. J Risk Uncertain 55, 41–69 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-017-9263-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-017-9263-1

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation