Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Uncivil Disobedience: Political Commitment and Violence

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Standard accounts of civil disobedience include nonviolence as a necessary condition. Here I argue that such accounts are mistaken and that civil disobedience can include violence in many aspects, primarily excepting violence directed at other persons. I base this argument on a novel understanding of civil disobedience: the special character of the practice comes from its combination of condemnation of a political practice with an expressed commitment to the political. The commitment to the political is a commitment to engaging with others as co-members in the on-going political project of living together. I show how such an understanding of civil disobedience is superior to the Rawlsian strain of thought, which focuses on fidelity to law. Rawls was concerned with civil disobedience solely in the context of overriding political obligation. The project of characterizing a contestatory political practice that can be distinguished and used in a wider variety of contexts than Rawls is concerned with, including under illegitimate regimes, beyond the nation-state, or on behalf of anarchism, requires a different understanding of civil disobedience.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Even this minimal characterization of violence has been challenged: Kimberley Brownlee notes that fencing is in some senses both violent and polite (2012, p. 22).

  2. I do not restrict the intention to changing ‘political’ practice because civil disobedience can aim to politicize something currently conceptualized as strictly private.

  3. See Brownlee (2012) for the most fully developed and insightful discussion of disobedience as an act of communication.

  4. See Sabl (2001) for a particularly informative discussion of Rawls’s notion of ‘near-just’ societies.

  5. For more along this line, see Scheuerman (2016).

  6. Similar points can be made about a variety of more robust understandings of the commitment to the political, including those that we could draw from the republican characterization of civil disobedience in Markovits (2005) or the deliberative democrat characterization in Smith (2011).

  7. Even if we disagree with Simmons’s characterization of the actual Thoreau, a slightly modified hypothetical Thoreau can demonstrate the case.

  8. Similar worries arise for views that appeal simply to principled objection (Smart 1978; Celikates 2016).

  9. Some proposed definitions strike me as implausible and skew the relevant discussion; for example, Morreall (1976, p. 38) claims that violence is conceptually only directed at persons and is necessarily related to rights claims. Similarly, German federal courts have misguidedly held that sitting in the street as an act of civil disobedience can be violent due to effects on drivers (Celikates 2016, pp. 41–42).

  10. Cf. May (2015, p. 68) arguing that any undermining of dignity is violent, so toppling a dictator’s statue is not violent per se, but stomping on it and denigrating it are violent. To be fair, May is not concerned with defining violence per se, but with defining a particularly robust kind of nonviolent political practice.

  11. This conflicts with a Rawlsian strain of the literature that rules out coercion, claiming that civil disobedience is only ever an attempt to persuade. This is, I think, historically inaccurate as well as a result of mistakenly restricting attention to the near-just context.

  12. Cf. Brownlee (2012, p. 20), Moraro (2007, p. 3) and Sabl (2001).

  13. Interestingly, this gestures towards a potential explanation of one of Chenoweth and Stephan’s findings, namely that nonviolent resistance was uniquely ineffective with respect to secession. Since secession is undertaken precisely on the premise of breaking apart a political community, it is difficult to express a commitment to the political in such cases.

  14. More precisely, the relevant distinction is between violence directed at persons and violence not directed at persons. This latter category includes more than property, for example including unowned elements of nature such as wild animals. I should note that nothing in my argument excludes violence towards animals from civil disobedience; although I think such violence is tactically unwise and most often unjustified, it does not seem to exclude any persons from the realm of the political, which is the only conceptual constraint that I rely upon.

  15. Individual actions must be evaluated within the broader context of a movement and in the Ferguson case much more than the police car burning occurred, as the pictures show, so for our purposes here I am making no claims about whether the overall evening constituted civil disobedience. Another misleading aspect of considering individual instances of law-breaking is that it obscures the group nature of civil disobedience (Arendt 1972).

References

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1972. Crises of the Republic. New York, NY: Harcourt Brace & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, Hugo. 1961. On civil disobedience. Journal of Philosophy 58: 653–665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brownlee, Kimberley. 2012. Conscience and conviction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bufacchi, Vittorio. 2005. Two concepts of violence. Political Studies Review 3: 193–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Celikates, Robin. 2016. Rethinking civil disobedience as a practice of contestation: Beyond the liberal paradigm. Constellations 23: 37–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chenoweth, Erica, and Maria J. Stephan. 2011. Why civil resistance works: The strategic logic of nonviolent conflict. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coady, C.A.J. 1986. The idea of violence. Journal of Applied Philosophy 3: 3–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Marshall. 1972. Liberalism and disobedience. Philosophy & Public Affairs 1: 283–314.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1985. Civil disobedience: Litmus test for the democratic constitutional state. Berkeley Journal of Sociology 30: 95–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lang, Berel. 1970. Civil disobedience and aonviolence: A distinction with a difference. Ethics 80: 156–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, David. 1998. Moral judgment, historical reality, and civil disobedience. Philosophy & Public Affairs 27: 31–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markovits, Daniel. 2005. Democratic disobedience. The Yale Law Journal 114: 1897–1952.

    Google Scholar 

  • May, Todd. 2015. Nonviolent resistance: A philosophical introduction. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moraro, Piero. 2007. Violent civil disobedience and willingness to accept punishment. Essays in Philosophy 8: 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morreall, John. 1976. The justifiability of violent civil disobedience. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 6: 35–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1999. A theory of justice. Revised edition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 2005. Political liberalism. Expanded edition. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 2009. The authority of law. 2nd edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sabl, Andrew. 2001. Looking forward to justice: Rawlsian civil disobedience and its non-Rawlsian lessons. The Journal of Political Philosophy 9: 307–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheuerman, William E. 2015. Recent theories of civil disobedience: An anti-legal turn? The Journal of Political Philosophy 23: 427–449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheuerman, William E. 2016. Civil disobedience in the shadows of postnationalization and privatization. Journal of International Political Theory 12: 237–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, William. 2011. Civil disobedience and the public sphere. The Journal of Political Philosophy 19: 145–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simmons, A. John. 2010. Disobedience and its objects. Boston University Law Review 90: 1805–1831.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, Brian. 1978. Defining civil disobedience. Inquiry 21: 249–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toler, Lindsay. 2014. 16 photos of Ferguson burning. Riverfront times. http://www.riverfronttimes.com/newsblog/2014/11/25/16-photos-of-ferguson-burning?page=2. Accessed 23 Oct 2016.

  • United States Department of Justice. 2015. Investigation of the Ferguson Police Department. https://www.justice.gov/sites/default/files/opa/press-releases/attachments/2015/03/04/ferguson_police_department_report.pdf. Accessed 23 Oct 2016.

  • Zinn, Howard. 1990. Law, justice and disobedience. Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics & Public Policy 5: 899–920.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to the participants in my Sommersemester 2016 graduate course on civil disobedience for challenging and enlightening discussions and to two anonymous reviewers at this journal for their valuable input.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to N. P. Adams.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Adams, N.P. Uncivil Disobedience: Political Commitment and Violence. Res Publica 24, 475–491 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-017-9367-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-017-9367-0

Keywords

Navigation