Skip to main content
Log in

Divine hiddenness and the opiate of the people

  • Article
  • Published:
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The problem of divine hiddenness has become one of the most prominent arguments for atheism in the current philosophy of religion literature. Schellenberg (Divine hiddenness and human reason 1993), one of the problem’s prominent advocates, holds that the only way to prevent completely the occurrence of nonresistant nonbelief would be for God to have granted all of us a constant awareness of Him (or at least a constant availability of such awareness) from the moment we achieved the age of reason. Now, if that were the case, we might be faced with a difficult obstacle to the development of a proper, meaningful relationship with God: namely, since the experience of God would be so unutterably wonderful (at least for some), we could be at risk of coming to commune with God not from love of Him but for the amazing experience that that communion involves. In other words, given that mystical union with infinite perfection is, qua experience, inconceivably better than that of any drug, we might come to treat God as something analogous to a powerful narcotic, seeking the experience for the pleasure of the experience more than from any devotion. Since God wants to foster genuinely meaningful relationship with Him, He rightly delays granting us such awareness of Himself, even though that leaves open the risk that nonresistant nonbelief could arise.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See for instance (St. Athanasius (1892), chaps. 11–15), St. Augustine (1993, pp. 106–118), (St. John Chrysostom (1889), homilies 2 and 4–8), (St. Gregory Nazianzus (1894), oration 28, chap. 12), and (Origen (1885), book 3, chap. 1).

  2. See for instance Hick (1981), Mesle (1988), McKim (1990), Penelhum (1983), O’Hear (1984), and Morris (1992).

  3. It is worth noting that while Keller rejects traditional theism, he is open to alternative models of God (specifically, process theology) and employs the problem of divine hiddenness more in support of that alternative model rather than atheism per se.

  4. We see here an analogue with the problem of evil, where Schellenberg’s formulation is akin to the logical problem of evil, and the others to the evidential problem.

  5. See Aijaz and Weidler (2007), Azadegan (2013a, b), Azadegan (Forthcoming), Cullison (2010), Cuneo (2013), Dumsday (2010a, b, 2012a, b, 2013), Dumsday (Forthcoming), Evans (2006, 2010), Henry (2001, 2008), Howard-Snyder (1996), King (2008, 2013), Marsh (2008), McBrayer and Swenson (2012), McCreary (2010), McKim (2001), Moser (2007, 2008)), Murray (2002), Oakes (2008), O’Connell (2013), Poston and Dougherty (2007), Rea (2009), Swinburne (1998, 2004), van Inwagen (2002, 2006), Tucker (2008), and Weidler and Aijaz (2013).

  6. Significant contributions include Cordry (2008), Lovering (2004), Maitzen (2008), Trakakis (2007), and Schellenberg (1996, 2005a, b, c, 2007a, b, 2008a, b, 2010, 2013).

  7. King (2008, 2013) reply to the hiddenness argument involves a critical examination of the claim (supported by Schellenberg (2007a, p. 206)), that an infinite God could without difficulty reveal Himself precisely as God to finite creatures, and that in a rationally indubitable fashion. King’s is an important line of response; however, for for the sake of argument I will here assume it is unsound, that God is able so to reveal Himself to us.

  8. See for instance Ware (1984, p. 266): “Hell is not so much a place where God imprisons man, as a place where man, by misusing his free will, chooses to imprison himself. And even in Hell the wicked are not deprived of the love of God, but by their own choice they experience as suffering what the saints experience as joy. ‘The love of God will be an intolerable torment for those who have not acquired it within themselves’.” The quote Ware employs is from Lossky (1957, p. 234).

  9. The recognition of something like this point seems to be present in one of Hinduism’s principal scriptures, the Bhagavad-Gita. There, when Arjuna asks Krishna (who at the time of the request was in his human form) to reveal himself to him (Arjuna) in his divine glory, Krishna complies with the request. Arjuna is so overwhelmed and terrified that he soon begs Krishna to return to his human form (Johnson translation, 1994, p. 53): “I rejoice that I have seen what has never before been seen, but my mind is unhinged with fear. O god, show me that other form again. Be merciful, lord of gods, home of the world”. And this is a reaction undergone by a righteous person, Arjuna—imagine if a wicked individual had seen Krishna in all his glory? My thanks to an anonymous referee for drawing my attention to this example.

  10. Though that idea in turn gives rise to worries concerning moral autonomy. Could one continue freely to choose between good and while constantly aware of an Almighty Judge looking over one’s shoulder (or even while having such awareness always available at a moment’s notice)? This sort of concern is raised by Kant (1956, p. 152, 1978, p. 123), and developed further by Swinburne (1998, pp. 203–210, 2004, pp. 267–272) and Murray (2002). For some replies see Lovering (2004) and Schellenberg (1993, chap. 5, 2005b, pp. 292–296; 2007a, pp. 210–218).

  11. I refer here to the standard division employed in discussions of the problem of evil between defences (the provision of reasons why God might conceivably allow some state of affairs) vs. theodicies (the provision of reasons why God actually allows some state of affairs). The burden of proof is lighter on the former.

  12. Or one might argue that anything less than the ineffably ecstatic experiences of the great mystics could not possibly be an experience of God Himself, but must instead be merely a wonderful experience caused by God. In other words, one might claim that there is a metaphysical impossibility involved in the notion of God’s ‘moderating’ an actual direct encounter with Him. I won’t pursue this option here.

  13. This general idea is of course familiar from Hick’s (1981) soul-making theodicy in the context of the problem of evil.

References

  • Aijaz, I., & Weidler, M. (2007). Some critical reflections on the hiddenness argument. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 61, 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Azadegan, E. (Forthcoming). Divine love and the argument from divine hiddenness. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion.

  • Azadegan, E. (2013a). Divine hiddenness and human sin: The noetic effect of sin. Journal of Reformed Theology, 7, 69–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Azadegan, E. (2013b). ‘Ibn’ arabi on the problem of divine hiddenness. Journal of the Muhyiddin Ibn Arabi Society, 53, 49–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cordry, B. (2008). Divine hiddenness and belief de re. Religious Studies, 45, 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cullison, A. (2010). Two solutions to the problem of divine hiddenness. American Philosophical Quarterly, 47, 119–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cuneo, T. (2013). Another look at divine hiddenness. Religious Studies, 49, 151–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drange, T. (1993). The argument from non-belief. Religious Studies, 29, 417–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drange, T. (1998). Nonbelief and evil: An argument for the nonexistence of god. New York: Amherst Prometheus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dumsday, T. (Forthcoming). Divine hiddennes and divine humility, Sophia: International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Metaphysical Theology and Ethics.

  • Dumsday, T. (2010a). Divine hiddenness free-will, and the victims of wrongdoing. Faith and Philosophy, 27, 423–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dumsday, T. (2010b). Divine hiddenness and the responsibility argument. Philosophia Christi, 12, 357–371.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dumsday, T. (2012a). Divine hiddenness as divine mercy. Religious Studies, 48, 183–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dumsday, T. (2012b). Divine hiddenness and creaturely resentment. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 72, 41–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dumsday, T. (2013). A thomistic response to the problem of divine hiddenness. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 87, 365–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, C. S. (2006). Can god be hidden and evident at the same time? Some Kierkegaardian reflections. Faith and Philosophy, 23, 241–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, C. S. (2010). Natural signs and knowledge of god: A new look at theistic arguments. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Henry, D. (2001). Does reasonable nonbelief exist? Faith and Philosophy, 18, 75–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henry, D. (2008). Reasonable doubts about reasonable nonbelief. Faith and Philosophy, 25, 276–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hick, J. (1981). Soul-making theodicy. In S. Davis (Ed.), Encountering Evil. Westminster: John Knox.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard-Snyder, D. (1996). The argument from divine hiddenness. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 26, 433–453.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, W. J. (trans.). (1994). The bhagavad gita. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Kant, I. (1956). Critique of practical reason, trans. L. Beck. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

  • Kant, I. (1978). Lectures on philosophical theology, trans. A. Wood and G. Clark. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

  • Keller, J. (1995). The hiddenness of god and the problem of evil. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 37, 13–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King, R. (2008). Obstacles to revelation: God and the reorientation of human reason. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, R. (2013). Divine self-testimony and the knowledge of god. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 74, 279–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lossky, V. (1957). The mystical theology of the eastern church. London: Jamse Clarke & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lovering, R. (2004). Divine hiddenness and inculpable ignorance, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 56, 89–107.

  • Maitzen, S. (2006). Divine hiddenness and the demographics of theism. Religious Studies, 42, 177–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maitzen, S. (2008). Does molinism explain the demographics of theism? Religious Studies, 44, 473–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marsh, J. (2008). Do the demographics of theistic belief disconfirm theism? A reply to Maitzen. Religious Studies, 44, 465–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McBrayer, J., & Swenson, P. (2012). Scepticism about the argument from divine hiddenness. Religious Studies, 48, 129–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCreary, M. (2010). Schellenberg on divine hiddenness and religious scepticism. Religious Studies, 46, 207–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKim, R. (1990). The hiddenness of god. Religious Studies, 26, 141–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKim, R. (2001). Religious ambiguity and religious diversity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mesle, C. R. (1988). Does god hide from us? John Hick and process theology on faith, freedom, and theodicy. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 24, 93–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morris, T. V. (1992). Making sense of it all: Pascal and the meaning of life. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moser, P. (2007). Divine hiddenness, death, and meaning. In P. Copan & C. Meister (Eds.), Philosophy of religion: Classic and contemporary issues. Oxford: Blackwel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moser, P. (2008). The elusive god: Reorienting religious epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Murray, M. (2002). Deus absconditus. In D. Howard-Snyder & P. Moser (Eds.), Divine hiddenness: New essays (pp. 62–82). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oakes, R. (2008). Life, death, and the hiddenness of god. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 64, 155–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Connell, J. (2013). Divine hiddenness: Would more miracles solve the problem? Heythrop Journal, 54, 261–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Hear, A. (1984). Experience, explanation, and faith. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Origen. (1885). De principiis, trans. F. Crombie. Buffalo, NY: Christian Literature Publishing Co.

  • Penelhum, T. (1983). God and skepticism. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Poston, T., & Dougherty, T. (2007). Divine hiddenness and the nature of belief. Religious Studies, 43, 183–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rea, M. (2009). Narrative, liturgy, and the hiddenness of god. In K. Timpe (Ed.), Metaphysics and god: Essays in honor of eleonore stump (pp. 76–96). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (1993). Divine hiddenness and human reason. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (1996). Response to Howard-Snyder. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 26, 455–462.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (2005a). The hiddenness argument revisited (I). Religious Studies, 41, 201–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (2005b). The hiddenness argument revisited (II). Religious Studies, 41, 287–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (2005c). On reasonable nonbelief and perfect love: Replies to Henry and Lehe. Faith and Philosophy, 22, 330–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (2007a). The wisdom to doubt: A justification of religious skepticism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (2007b). On not unnecessarily darkening the glass: A reply to poston and dougherty. Religious Studies, 43, 199–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (2008a). Response to Tucker on hiddenness. Religious Studies, 44, 289–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (2008b). Reply to Aijaz and Weidler on hiddenness. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 64, 135–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (2010). How to be an atheist and a sceptic too: Response to McCreary. Religious Studies, 46, 227–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (2013). Replies to my colleagues. Religious Studies, 49, 257–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spilka et al. (2003). The psychology of religion: An empirical approach. NY: Guilford.

  • St. Athanasius. (1892). On the Incarnation of the Word, trans. A. Robertson. Buffalo: Christian Literature Publishing Co.

  • St. Augustine. (1993). On Free Choice of the Will, trans. Thomas Williams. Indianapolis: Hackett.

  • St. Gregory Nazianzus. (1894). Orations, trans. C.G. Browne and J.E. Swallow. Buffalo, NY: Christian Literature Publishing Co.

  • St. John Chrysostom. (1889). Homilies on first Corinthians, trans. T. W. Chambers. Buffalo, NY: Christian Literature Publishing Co.

  • Swinburne, R. (1998). Providence and the problem of evil. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (2004). The existence of god. (2nd revised ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Trakakis, N. (2007). An epistemically distant god? A critique of John Hick’s response to the problem of divine hiddenness, Heythrop Journal, 48, 214–226.

  • Tucker, C. (2008). Divine hiddenness and the value of divine–creature relationships. Religious Studies, 44, 269–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (2002). Divine hiddenness: New essays. In D. Howard- Snyder & P. Moser (Eds.), What is the problem of the hiddenness of god? (pp. 24–32). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (2006). The problem of evil. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ware, T. (1984). The orthodox church (3rd revised ed.). London: Penguin.

  • Weidler, M., & Aijaz, I. (2013). Divine hiddenness and discrimination: A philosophical dilemma. Sophia, 52, 95–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

My sincere thanks to an anonymous referee for his/her helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Travis Dumsday.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dumsday, T. Divine hiddenness and the opiate of the people. Int J Philos Relig 76, 193–207 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-014-9457-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-014-9457-2

Keywords

Navigation