Skip to main content
Log in

Inquiry and the epistemic

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The zetetic turn in epistemology raises three questions about epistemic and zetetic norms. First, there is the relationship question: what is the relationship between epistemic and zetetic norms? Are some epistemic norms zetetic norms, or are epistemic and zetetic norms distinct? Second, there is the tension question: are traditional epistemic norms in tension with plausible zetetic norms? Third, there is the reaction question: how should theorists react to a tension between epistemic and zetetic norms? Drawing on an analogy to practical philosophy, I develop a focal point view to resolve these motivating questions. On the focal point view, traditional epistemic norms and zetetic norms answer different types of normative questions. There is nevertheless a familiar type of evaluative tension between traditional epistemic norms and zetetic norms, but this tension is an unavoidable feature of the normative landscape and not a sign that traditional epistemic norms need revision. But if traditional epistemic norms are not zetetic norms, then in what sense is zetetic epistemology a project for epistemologists? I conclude by articulating a sense in which some nontraditional epistemic norms are zetetic norms, and in which zetetic epistemology is an important part of the study of theoretical rationality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. While I accept that many traditional epistemic norms govern belief, I do not hold that all epistemic norms govern belief. See Sect. 7 for discussion.

  2. See Podgorski (2017) for a related view. The unity view is also one way to unpack the turn from substantive to procedural rationality in theories of bounded rationality (Simon 1976), although it is not the only unpacking.

  3. This point may require an argument depending on how the relevant reasons are specified. See for example Kiesewetter (2017).

  4. This is no longer obvious once ZIP is weakened to take into account the totality of an agent’s epistemic goals. Forming the false belief that she is loved may lead Boss to form a large number of related false beliefs at work, and throughout her life.

  5. See Cohen (2016a, 2016b), Conee (2016), Dotson (2019), Lyons (2016), and McGrath (2016) among others.

  6. Value-based approaches can also be adopted by nonconsequentialists (Sylvan 2020).

  7. Similarly, Nishi Shah (2003, 2006) argues that only epistemic reasons can be reasons for belief because the question of whether to believe p is transparent to whether p. But the question of whether and how to inquire into p is not transparent to whether p. Another prominent motivation for epistemic prioritarianism about belief is the claim that seeming non-epistemic reasons to believe that p are actually reasons to get oneself to believe that p (Way 2012). But this commits us to accepting many non-epistemic reasons for inquiry, insofar as the typical way in which we get ourselves to believe something is through inquiry.

References

  • Cohen, S. (2016a). Replies to my commentators. Inquiry, 59(7–8), 906–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (2016b). Theorizing about the epistemic. Inquiry, 59(7–8), 839–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E. (2016). The epistemic. Inquiry, 59(7–8), 858–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dotson, K. (2019). Tales from an apostate. Philosophical Issues, 29(1), 69–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Driver, J. (2001). Uneasy virtue. Cambridge: Cambridge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. (2000). The ethics of belief. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 60(3), 667–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R., & Conee, E. (1985). Evidentialism. Philosophical Studies, 48(1), 15–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2019a). Checking again. Philosophical Issues, 29(1), 84–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. The epistemic and the zetetic, forthcoming (a) in Philosophical Review.

  • Friedman, J. (2018). Junk beliefs and interest-driven epistemology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 97(3), 568–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2019b). Teleological epistemology. Philosophical Studies, 176(3), 673–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. Zetetic epistemology, forthcoming (b) in Reed, B. and Flowerree A.K. (eds.), Towards an expansive epistemology: norms, action, and the social sphere, Routledge.

  • Hall, R., & Johnson, C. (1998). The epistemic duty to seek more evidence. American Philosophical Quarterly, 35(2), 129–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1986). Change in view. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (2001). On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (2000). Evaluative focal points. In: B. Hooker, E. Mason , D. Miller (Eds.), Morality, rules and consequences (pp. 134–55). Edinburgh: Edinburgh.

  • Keller, S. (2004). Friendship and belief. Philosophical Papers, 33(3), 329–51.

  • Kelly, T. (2003). Epistemic rationality as instrumental rationality: a critique. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66(3), 612–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2002). The rationality of belief and some other propositional attitudes. Philosophical Studies, 110(2), 163–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiesewetter, B. (2017). The normativity of rationality. Oxford: Oxford.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. & Sosa, E. (Eds.). (2006). The epistemology of testimony. Oxford: Oxford.

  • Lord, E. (2018). The importance of being rational. Oxford: Oxford.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, J. (2016). What we talk about when we talk about epistemic justification. Inquiry, 59(7–8), 867–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, M. (2016). Cohen on ‘epistemic'. Inquiry, 59(7–8), 889–905.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKay, R., & Dennett, D. (2009). The evolution of misbelief. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32(6), 493–561.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P., Smith, M. (2000). Global consequentialism, in Hooker et al. (2000):121-33.

  • Plantinga, A. (1983). Reason and belief in God. In Plantinga, A. & Wolsteroff, N. (Eds.) Faith and rationality: reason and belief in God (pp. 16–93). Notre Dame: Notre Dame.

  • Podgorski, A. (2017). Rational delay. Philosophers’ Imprint, 17(5), 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preston-Roedder, R. (2013). Faith in humanity. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 87(3), 664–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. (1984). Alienation, consequentialism, and the demands of morality. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 13(2), 134–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rinard, S. (2019). Equal treatment for belief. Philosophical Studies, 176(7), 1923–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shah, N. (2006). A new argument for evidentialism. Philosophical Quarterly, 56(225), 481–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shah, N. (2003). How truth governs belief. Philosophical Review, 112(4), 447–82.

  • Siegel, S. (2017). The rationality of perception. Oxford: Oxford.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. (1976). From substantive to procedural rationality. In: S. K. Kuipers, R. G. Wagenaar, T. J. Kastelein, W. A. Nijenhuis (Eds.), 25 years of economic theory (pp. 65-86) NY: Springer.

  • Smith, H. (2014). The subjective moral duty to inform oneself before acting. Ethics, 125(1), 11–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stocker, M. (1976). The schizophrenia of modern ethical theories. Journal of Philosophy, 73(14), 453–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, S. (2006). Epistemic partiality in friendship. Ethics, 116(3), 498–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swanton, C. (2001). A virtue ethical account of right action. Ethics, 112(1), 32–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sylvan, K. (2020). An epistemic non-consequentialism. Philosophical Review, 129(1), 1–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Way, J. (2012). Transmission and the wrong kind of reason. Ethics, 122(3), 489–515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper benefitted greatly from discussions with Arianna Falbo, Daniel Friedman, Ned Hall, Eliran Haziza, and Susanna Rinard; audiences at Harvard, Oxford and the Early Career Inquiry Network; and the comments of two anonymous reviewers for Philosophical Studies.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Thorstad.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Thorstad, D. Inquiry and the epistemic. Philos Stud 178, 2913–2928 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01592-y

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01592-y

Keywords

Navigation