Skip to main content
Log in

Preferences, reasoning errors, and resource egalitarianism

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I aim to examine some problematic implications of the fact that individuals are prone to making systematic reasoning errors, for resource egalitarianism. I begin by disentangling the concepts of preferences, choices and ambitions, which are sometimes used interchangeably by egalitarians. Subsequently, I claim that the most plausible interpretation of resource egalitarianism takes preferences, not choices, as the site of responsibility. This distinction is salient, since preference-sensitive resource egalitarianism is faced with an important objection when applied to situations in which the empirically reasonable assumption that individuals have different degrees of computational abilities is introduced. I first show that this objection can be raised in cases involving individuals who have incomplete information, but that it ultimately fails for such cases since we can appeal to higher order insurance markets in order to mitigate any initial concerns. I further claim, however, that the objection is much more powerful in cases involving individuals who have different reasoning skills, since the appeal to higher order insurance markets is no longer tenable. Consequently, the ideal principle of justice proposed by Dworkin is met with a new feasibility challenge. Finally, I claim that the problem of reasoning errors and various forms of cognitive biases also affect Dworkin’s non-ideal principle of justice, skewing the outputs of the hypothetical insurance mechanism in an unjustifiable manner.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Parr (2017, forthcoming) for a conceptual and normative exploration of the envy test.

  2. Whether Dworkin's egalitarian theory is part of this family of views is debatable. On the one hand, the brute luck-option luck distinction which he introduces in Dworkin (1981b) underlies much of the luck egalitarian project and Dworkin has often been credited as the original founder of this line of thought (see Wolff 2010, pp. 336–337). This has led some authors, to argue that “there is clearly a brute luck egalitarian strand to his political philosophy, and it may be the most influential of its strands” (Knight 2012, p. 542) and many other authors (e.g. Anderson 1999; Scheffler 2003; Stemplowska 2013) to include his view within the luck egalitarian family. On the other hand, Dworkin (2003) himself has notoriously rejected this label, arguing that his theory does not ultimately seek to fully extinguish the effects of bad brute luck, and some philosophers have recently taken the distinction between resource egalitarianism and luck egalitarianism seriously (e.g. Jubb 2011; Tomlin 2013).

  3. Both arguments are criticized by Lippert-Rasmussen (2001, pp. 552–557).

  4. Various objections have been raised against Dwokin's insurance mechanism, of which I will only mention a few due to spatial constraints. Both Roemer (1985) and Fleurbaey (2009), for instance, argue that for individuals with similar tastes the insurance mechanism prescribes utilitarian allocations —with all their associated problems—, while for individuals with different tastes it prescribes allocations which make those who were unlucky to begin with even worse-off. Cohen Cristofidis (2004) suggests that the insurance mechanism is unable to generate distributions which satisfy the envy test, since the untalented still have legitimate reasons to envy the talented. Both Otsuka (2002) and Sandbu (2004) claim the simple availability of insurance, without any additional constraints might not be enough to properly convert brute luck to option luck. Consequently, Otsuka (2002) adds the supplementary conditions that (1) insurance must fully compensate the loss of resources associated with the bad brute luck outcome and (2) insurance must not be so expensive that it is impossible for the individual to purchase it, or even unreasonably expensive, while Sandbu (2004) refines Otsuka’s conditions with the demands that in the case where either (1) or (2) are not met, the individual who suffers a bad brute luck outcome must be compensated until the least risky reasonable prospect is equalized.

  5. Still, Cohen casts a legitimate shadow of doubt over the separateness of choice and preference in Dworkin’s work, claiming that he uses the phrases "decide what sort of life to pursue", which tracks choices, and "decide what sort of life one wants", which tracks preferences, interchangeably (Cohen 1989, pp. 928–929).

  6. In the context of responsibility-sensitive egalitarian theories of justice, I take this concept to embody those features on the basis of which ensuing distributive outcomes require no compensation for any of the individuals involved, as a matter of justice, since they are to be legitimately held accountable for the respective features.

  7. Framing effects reveal the propensity of individuals to hold different attitudes towards risk when the choice context is presented either in terms of losses or in terms of gains. The prevalence of framing effects in experimental settings has been replicated in a considerable number of studies. See Kuhberger (1998) for a meta-analysis, which concludes that "framing is a reliable phenomenon" (Kuhberger 1998, p. 23).

  8. I only take into account cases where the continuity test, which states that "a political community should regard certain conditions as disadvantaging some of its members only if those members' own views about what it is to live well also imply that those conditions disadvantage them" [Williams (2002, p. 387), also see Clayton (2000) for a different formulation and Colburn (2014) for a critique] would not be violated since individuals would consider that making choices which do not reflect their underlying preferences would be disadvantageous.

  9. G and I represent the gamble and insurance alternatives, while W and L represent the winning or losing of the gamble. The numbers at the end of each branch represent the resources gained in the respective outcome.

  10. See Bermudez (Bermudez 2009, pp. 25–27) for a brief overview of the most salient of these principles.

  11. For simplicity, I assume that they do not have any information regarding the likelihood of having full or incomplete information.

  12. The first node represents the choice of the individual to insure against having incomplete information (I) or reject the insurance and gamble (G). The next node on each branch is split between the outcome where individuals have full information and those in which individuals have incomplete information. The third series of nodes then depict the regular scenario of Fig. 2, with the premium and insurance payment incorporated into the payoff matrices. The numbers at the end of each branch represent the resources gained for the respective outcome.

  13. Assume that the loss overestimation bias is not identical to Kahneman and Tversky’s (1979) skewing of the value function in prospect theory towards a greater weighting of losses. For purposes of simplification, it should be simply interpreted as a systematic reasoning error, which arises in the context of using expected utility theory as a decisional mechanism.

  14. Even, for instance, sentencing decisions of professional magistrates (Englich et al 2006).

  15. See Tversky and Kahneman (1983).

  16. Note, therefore, that if choices are to be considered the appropriate site of responsibility in Dworkin's theory of justice, the problems mentioned in Sects. 4 and 5 would not appear.

  17. Many authors consider that the incorporation of responsibility within egalitarianism is Dworkin's most important contribution (see for instance Cohen 1989, p. 933) and it is precisely this move which has sparked the rise of luck egalitarian theories within the past few decades.

References

  • Anderson, E. (1999). What is the point of equality? Ethics, 109(2), 287–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J. (2009). Decision theory and rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, M. (2000). The resources of liberal equality. Imprints, 5, 63–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G. A. (1989). On the currency of egalitarian justice. Ethics, 99(4), 906–944.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G. A. (2004). Expensive tastes rides again. In J. Burley (Ed.), Dworkin and his critics (pp. 3–29). Malden: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen Cristofidis, M. (2004). Talent, slavery, and envy. In J. Burley (Ed.), Dworkin and his critics (pp. 30–44). Malden: Blackwell Publishing.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Colburn, B. (2014). Disadvantage, autonomy, and the continuity test. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 31(3), 254–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1981a). What is equality? Part 1: Equality of welfare. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 10(3), 185–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1981b). What is equality? Part 2: Equality of resources. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 10(4), 283–345.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1995). Foundations of liberal equality. In S. Darwall (Ed.), Equal freedom: Selected Tanner lectures on human values (pp. 190–306). Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (2000). Sovereign virtue: The theory and practice of equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (2002). Sovereign virtue revisited. Ethics, 113(1), 106–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (2003). Equality, luck and hierarchy. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 31(2), 190–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (2011). Justice for hedgehogs. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Englich, B., Mussweiler, T., & Strack, F. (2006). Playing dice with criminal sentences: The influence of irrelevant anchors on experts’ judicial decision making. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 32(3), 188–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey, M. (2009). Fairness, responsibility, and welfare. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamlin, A., & Stemplowska, Z. (2012). Theory, ideal theory and the theory of ideals. Political Studies Review, 10, 48–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hogarth, R., & Kunreuther, H. (1989). Risk, ambiguity, and insurance. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 2(1), 5–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, E., Hershey, J., Meszaros, J., & Kunreuther, H. (1993). Framing, probability distortions, and insurance decisions. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 7(1), 35–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jubb, R. (2011). On the significance of the basic structure: A priori baseline views and luck egalitarianism. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 14(1), 59–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47(2), 263–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knight, C. (2012). Distributive luck. South African Journal of Philosophy, 31(3), 541–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhberger, A. (1998). The influence of framing on risky decisions: A meta-analysis. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 75(1), 23–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, M. (2016). The undoing project. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lippert-Rasmussen, K. (2001). Egalitarianism, option luck, and responsibility. Ethics, 111(3), 548–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state and Utopia. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Otsuka, M. (2002). Luck, insurance, and equality. Ethics, 113(1), 40–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Otsuka, M. (2015). Prioritarianism and the measure of utility. Journal of Political Philosophy, 23(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parr, T. (2017). How to identify disadvantage: Taking the envy test seriously. Political Studies.

  • Rawls, J. (1971 [1999]). A theory of justice (revised edition). Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

  • Roemer, J. (1985). Equality of talent. Economics and Philosophy, 1(2), 151–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roemer, J. (1993). A pragmatic theory of responsibility for the egalitarian planner. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 22(2), 146–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandbu, M. (2004). On Dworkin’s brute-luck–option-luck distinction and the consistency of brute-luck egalitarianism. Politics, Philosophy and Economics, 3(3), 283–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Satz, D., & Ferejohn, J. (1994). Rational choice and social theory. Journal of Philosophy, 91(2), 71–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, S. (2003). What is egalitarianism? Philosophy & Public Affairs, 31(1), 5–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapira, Z., & Venezia, I. (2008). On the preference for full-coverage policies: Why do people buy too much insurance? Journal of Economic Psychology, 29, 747–761.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. (1978). Rationality as process and as product of thought. American Economic Review, 68(2), 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stemplowska, Z. (2013). Rescuing luck egalitarianism. Journal of Social Philosophy, 44(4), 402–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomlin, P. (2013). Choices, chance, and change: Luck egalitarianism over time. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 16(2), 393–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: heuristics and biases. Science, 185(4157), 1124–1131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1983). Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: The conjunction fallacy in probability judgment. Psychological Review, 90(4), 293–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1986). Rational choice and the framing of decisions. Journal of Business, 59(4), 251–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Volacu, A., & Dervis, O. (2016). Pluralist welfare egalitarianism and the expensive tastes objection. Contemporary Political Theory, 15(3), 285–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, A. (2002). Equality for the ambitious. The Philosophical Quarterly, 52(208), 377–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, T., Houston, C., Etling, K., & Brekke, N. (1996). A new look at anchoring effects: Basic anchoring and its antecedents. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 125(4), 387–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, J. (2007). Equality: The recent history of an idea. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 4(1), 125–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolff, J. (2010). Fairness, respect and the egalitarian ethos revisited. Journal of Ethics, 14(3), 335–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Matej Cibik, Pietro Intropi, Adrian Miroiu, Kasper Ossenblok, Tom Parr, Adam Slavny, Zofia Stemplowska and two anonymous reviewers for written comments on earlier versions of this paper. I am also grateful to an audience at the University of Warwick, where a previous draft was presented, for insightful discussions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alexandru Volacu.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Volacu, A. Preferences, reasoning errors, and resource egalitarianism. Philos Stud 175, 1851–1870 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0936-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0936-z

Keywords

Navigation