Skip to main content
Log in

Realist-expressivism and the fundamental role of normative belief

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The goal of this paper is to show that a cognitivist–externalist view about moral judgment is compatible with a key intuition that motivates non-cognitivist expressivism. This is the intuition that normative judgments have a close connection to action that ordinary “descriptive factual beliefs” do not have, or, as James Dreier has suggested, that part of the fundamental role of normative judgment is to motivate. One might think that cognitivist–externalist positions about normative judgment are committed to viewing normative judgments as having the same role in our psychology as ordinary descriptive factual beliefs. This paper argues to the contrary. It restricts attention to moral judgments. It develops an account of moral belief according to which, first, moral beliefs are representational cognitive states that have the same basic nature as ordinary descriptive factual beliefs. Yet, second, their fundamental role is such that, when all goes well, moral beliefs mesh with our moral policies to motivate action. The paper draws on a society-centered account of the grounding of morality, a distinction between “basic” and “internal” ways of thinking of the moral properties, and a hybrid account of the “meaning” of moral predicates, called “realist-expressivism.”

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Copp (2007b). I here use “meaning” in a broad sense to include both the truth-conditional semantic content of a term and other properties a term may have due to linguistic conventions governing the conditions under which it can felicitously be used in assertions.

  2. I proposed some of these ideas in Copp (2017).

  3. For the idea of a policy as a kind of general intention, see Bratman (2007: 167). Taking this idea on board, I could reformulate the sentence in the text to say that simple assertions using moral terms typically felicity-express a relevant general intention.

  4. In Kent Bach’s (1999) view, to implicate something is to mean to convey it. Since I do not think that a person making a moral assertion typically means to convey that she has a specific conative attitude, I introduced the idea of simplicature, where, roughly, a simplicature would qualify as an implicature if it were intended (Copp 2009a, 182–185). Here I set aside this complication.

  5. A version of the objection was raised by Kent Bach, in conversation, as an objection to the hybrid account of pejorative terms that I have proposed (Copp 2007b, 2009a, 2014). But since I offered this account as an analogue of RE, there is an analogous objection to RE, as I see things. Stephen Finlay raised a related objection (2005).

  6. I assume that the essential properties of something are the properties, if any, that the thing has in every possible world where it exists.

  7. I thank Ali Kazmi for very helpful discussions of the ideas in this section.

  8. I am here thinking of reference broadly so that, for example, we can say that predicates “refer” to properties. I am grateful to Andrew Alwood for pointing out the need to relativize to times.

  9. My understanding of the issues was shaped by discussions with Ali Kazmi and by McKay and Nelson (2014), Speaks (2014), and Schwitzgebel (2015). I was also helped by Braun (1998), Salmon (1986), and Soames (2002).

  10. I take the term “coloring” from Frege, but I do not intend to be using it in the way that Frege did. For Frege, color seems to be a property of certain words, such as, perhaps, pejorative terms. For me, in this paper, “coloring” refers to a psychological and phenomenological property of certain beliefs. A person’s ways of thinking have a psychological effect on the quality of relevant beliefs, a quality I refer to as the “coloring” of the beliefs. Of course this effect can vary in degree. I apologize for any confusion, but the term “coloring” is better for my purposes than any alternative I have found. See Frege (1979: 140–141, 197–198; 1984: 161, 185, 357).

  11. Bratman discusses the possibility of a “self-opaque agent,” an agent who, for example, has a policy without knowing this about herself (2007: 191–194). Smith discusses an agent who is moved by vanity but does not realize this (1994: 106).

  12. I was helped here by Speaks (2014).

  13. The kind of normative naturalism that I defend is committed to there being a naturalistic WOT of wrongness as well as the basic and the internal normative WOTs.

  14. I am grateful to participants in the 2015 Rio Metaethics Conference for pressing this objection.

  15. On my view, there is a natural property “N-authoritativeness” such that for a moral standard to be authoritative is for it to be N-authoritative. But I do not think this is a conceptual truth. See Copp (1995, 2007a, 2015a).

  16. I thank Andrew Alwood for pressing this objection.

  17. Julia Telles de Menezes reminded me (in discussion) that Michael Smith views a desire to do what one believes to be right as fetishistic (Smith 1994: 75). It might seem that he would also view a policy of avoiding wrongdoing as fetishistic. I think not, but a discussion of this worry would take me too far afield. See Zangwill (2003).

  18. Yet the agent need not know this about herself. Bratman suggests the possibility of having a policy without knowing this about oneself (2007: 191–194). I here set aside this complication.

  19. A WOT of wrongness is a WOT of a property that actions have if and only if they are cases of wrongdoing. For simplicity, I will often blur the distinction between a WOT of wrongness and a WOT of wrongdoing.

  20. I am grateful to Peter Railton for helping me to think about how best to characterize the internal normative WOTs.

  21. First, there could be cases in which different moral codes would do roughly equally well at enabling people to cope with the problem of sociality. I ignore this issue here (see Copp 1995: 198–199, 2007a: 17, 243). Second, a problem arises if everyone else is complying with a moral code that is not the ideal (see Copp 1995: 199–200). Here I am simplifying by supposing that the properties of the ideal moral code(s) determine the answer to relevant moral questions.

  22. Dreier seems uncertain that it is a failure of rationality. He says, it’s “maybe a rational mistake” (2015: 163).

  23. I am grateful Jordan Bell and the other members of my 2016 graduate seminar to for helpful discussion of the example.

  24. I owe this objection to an anonymous referee.

References

  • Bach, K. (1999). The myth of conventional implicature. Linguistics and Philosophy, 22(4), 327–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. (2007). Structures of agency: Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Braun, D. (1998). Understanding belief reports. The Philosophical Review, 107, 555–595.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (1995). Morality, normativity, and society. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (2007a). Morality in a natural world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (2007b). Realist-expressivism: A neglected option for moral realism. In D. Copp, Morality in a natural world  (pp. 153–202).  Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.  Originally published in Social Philosophy and Policy, 18(2001), 1–43.

  • Copp, D. (2009a). Realist-expressivism and conventional implicature. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 4, pp. 167–202). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (2009b). Toward a pluralist and teleological theory of normativity. Philosophical Issues, 19, 21–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (2012). Normativity and Reasons: Five Arguments from Parfit Against Normative Naturalism. In S. Nuccetelli & G. Seay (Eds.), Ethical naturalism: Current debates (pp. 24–57). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (2014). Can a Hybrid Theory Have it Both Ways: Moral Thought, Open Questions, and Moral Motivation. In G. Fletcher & M. Ridge (Eds.), Having it both ways (pp. 51–74). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (2015a). Explaining normativity. Proceedings and Addresses of the APA, 89, 48–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (2015b). Rationality and moral authority. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. 10, pp. 134–159). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (2017). Normative Naturalism and Normative Nihilism: Parfit’s Dilemma for Naturalism. In S. Kirchin (Ed.), Reading Parfit on what matters (pp. 28–53). London: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (2006). The second-person standpoint: Morality, respect, and accountability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreier, J. (2015). Another world: The metaethics and metametaethics of reasons fundamentalism. In R. Johnson & M. Smith (Eds.), Passions and projections: themes from the philosophy of Simon Blackburn (pp. 155–171). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finlay, S. (2005). Value and implicature. Philosophers’ Imprint, 5(4), 1–20. Accessed at www.philosophersimprint.org/005004/.

  • Frege, G. (1979).  In H. Hermes, F. Kambartel & F. Kaulbach (Eds.), Posthumous writings.  Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Frege, G. (1984).  In B. McGuinness (Ed.), Collected papers on mathematics, logic, and philosophy.  Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

  • Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise choices, apt feelings. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKay, T., & Nelson, M. (2014). Propositional attitude reports. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (spring 2014 edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/prop-attitude-reports/.

  • Potts, C. (2005). The logic of conventional implicatures. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. (2003). Facts, values and norms: essays toward a morality of consequence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, N. (1986). Frege’s puzzle. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2015). Belief. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (summer 2015 edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/belief/.

  • Sennet, A., & Copp, D. (2017). Pejoratives and ways of thinking. Analytic Philosophy (forthcoming).

  • Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (2002). Beyond rigidity: The unfinished semantic agenda of naming and necessity. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Speaks, J. (2014). Theories of meaning. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (fall 2014 edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/meaning/.

  • Zangwill, N. (2003). Externalist moral motivation. American Philosophical Quarterly, 40, 143–154.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Some of the ideas developed in this essay were presented to the Tenth Symposium on Ethics and Political Philosophy, Center for Ethics and Philosophy of Mind, Universidade Federal do Rio de Janeiro, Brazil, March, 2014, to the Rio-2015 Metaethics Conference, January, 2015 and to the Departments of Philosophy at York University and the University of Calgary in December, 2014 and 2015, respectively. I am grateful to members of these audiences for helpful discussion and especially to Andrew Alwood, Ali Kazmi, Adam Sennet and Teemu Toppinen for their detailed comments. In addition, I would like to thank Christian Coons, Simon Kirchin, Nicholas Laskowski, David McNaughton, Wilson Mendonca, Claudia Passos, Peter Railton, Fabio Shecaira, Paul Teller, Julia Telles de Menezes, two anonymous referees, and the members of the Davis discussion group in ethics and related subjects.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Copp.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Copp, D. Realist-expressivism and the fundamental role of normative belief. Philos Stud 175, 1333–1356 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0913-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0913-6

Keywords

Navigation