Skip to main content
Log in

Embedded mental action in self-attribution of belief

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

You can come to know that you believe that p partly by reflecting on whether p and then judging that p. Call this procedure “the transparency method for belief.” How exactly does the transparency method generate known self-attributions of belief? To answer that question, we cannot interpret the transparency method as involving a transition between the contents p and I believe that p. It is hard to see how some such transition could be warranted. Instead, in this context, one mental action is both a judgment that p and a self-attribution of a belief that p. The notion of embedded mental action is introduced here to explain how this can be so and to provide a full epistemic explanation of the transparency method. That explanation makes sense of first-person authority and immediacy in transparent self-knowledge. In generalized form, it gives sufficient conditions on an attitude’s being known transparently.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Evans’s (1982) characterization of the transparency method is the most often cited, but—as Moran (2001) notes—Edgley (1969) seems to have provided the first characterization.

  2. Here I follow Burge (1996) in taking “warrant” to be a broad term that covers epistemic entitlement, inferential justification, evidentiary support, and so forth (see pp. 93–94).

  3. See Moran (2001), Barnett (2015), Williams (2004), Gallois (1996), Byrne (2011), and Shoemaker (1995) for more on the connection between transparency and self-knowledge.

  4. There is naturally far more to say on this point to make proper sense of an explanation of Moorean absurdities. Note, too, that not all those philosophers aiming to explain the absurdity of Moorean assertions and judgments accept that an epistemic explanation is the right kind to give. See Green and Williams (2007) for arguments on both sides of this divide.

  5. Gallois (1996) names these “Moore inferences” because reasoning in this way explicitly avoids commitment to the Moorean absurdity “p, but I don’t believe that p” (p. 46).

  6. Byrne (2012) credits Ryle (1949) with coining the phrase “privileged access.”.

  7. Some, however, reject the converse. Davidson (1984/2001, 1987/2001) and Wright (1989), among others, offer non-epistemic explanations of first-person authority.

  8. This is related to the distinct point that knowledge cannot be gained by way of false lemmas. Some take that to be the lesson of Gettier’s (1963) famous thought experiment. Byrne (2011, p. 207) correctly points out, however, that one need not draw that lesson from Gettier; instead, we might restrict knowledge to safe cases. Moore inferences are, as he points out, as safe as it gets.

  9. See Barnett (2015) for extensive careful discussion of the epistemological ramifications of accepting Moore inferences as such. He also points out two further disanalogies between Moore inferences and inferences in general which, for reasons of space, I have omitted here.

  10. Cf. Frege (1979, p. 3), quoted by Boghossian (2014, p. 4): “To make a judgment because we are cognizant of other truths as providing a justification for it is known as inferring.”.

  11. It is worth noting that self-knowledge of reasons might be transparent in a way directly analogous to self-knowledge of belief: you may well know your own considerations for or against believing that p by considering what in fact provides evidence for (or logically implies that) p. Yet this observation cannot alone complete Moran’s explanation. The same issues that motivate this paper—questions about why judging that p leads to knowing you believe that p—would then apply in analogous ways for knowledge of your considerations for and against belief that p.

  12. Here (2011) and elsewhere (especially 2009a) Boyle makes plausible that a belief is “an exercise of agency” (2009a passim) insofar as its subject controls and guides its development.

  13. This challenge is sharpened by the fact that subjects can apparently fail to know their own beliefs. Boyle (2011) is constrained to deny this. He writes: “when a belief is present but not consciously accessible, so too is the knowledge of that belief” (p. 229). This is a deeply counterintuitive conclusion. It certainly seems to be the case that you can discover, with surprise, that you have some belief that you previously never knew you had—not even tacitly.

  14. Compare Heal (2002) and O’Brien (2005). Heal argues that the judgment that I believe that p as made in the course of the transparency method is also a judgment that p, because it shares the “long-term consequences” of the judgment that p (p. 17). Yet it is not clear why meeting this condition requires identification of these judgments. O’Brien may also have a no-move view about self-knowledge of judgment, if not belief. She writes: “concluding that ‘P is true’, on considering whether P is true, is … equivalent to the subject realising the practically known possibility of judging that P” (p. 594). This practical knowledge just is the knowledge that one is judging that P. However, O’Brien explicitly avoids extending this account to belief (pp. 599–600).

  15. For the following characterization of mental action I am indebted quite generally to O’Brien (2007), O’Brien and Soteriou (2009), Peacocke (2008), and Ryle (1971a, b, c).

  16. There is one delicacy here. Below, I suggest that deciding what to do (which implies forming an intention) can be intentional. If so, and if something’s being intentional is partly a matter of having an intention to do it, then not all intention formation can be intentional, on pain of vicious regress. Sometimes you must be able to decide what to do without doing that (so deciding) intentionally. An anonymous reviewer drew my attention to this subtle point.

  17. In personal communication, Christopher Peacocke has suggested that there could be intentional mental actions with unconscious contents. Though I disagree, I leave this subtle controversy aside for now. Even if some intentional mental actions lack conscious contents, certainly some mental actions have conscious contents. That weaker claim is all that is strictly required for the purposes of the epistemic explanation provided in Sect. 3 below.

  18. See also Davidson (1963/2001) on the connection between intentional actions and particular intensional descriptions of those actions. For more on mental action awareness generally, see O’Brien (2007), O’Brien and Soteriou (2009), and Peacocke (2008).

  19. In order to make best sense of my asking you this question when you yourself do not report to me what you are doing, assume that I have insight into what you are currently doing in thought just by watching you: I know that particular scowl you make when looking at your rival’s portrait is caused by your plotting, or I know that your crestfallen expression while watching your daughter’s tennis match is a result of a real judgment that she has no future at Wimbledon.

  20. See Williams (1976) for a related argument against doxastic voluntarism.

  21. Broader classes of mental actions I will call “kinds”: thus judging is a kind of mental action.

  22. This phenomenon is not particularly circumscribed to mental actions rather than actions in general. Compare the following case in non-mental action (with thanks to John Campbell): conceptualizing what you’re about to do as aiming for target one partly makes it the case that what you go on to do, when you let fly, is attempt to hit target one. I focus here on mental action for simplicity and brevity, but it’s important to note that this point about embedded mental action proceeds from a more general point about action and how it is conceptualized in thought.

  23. Conceptualizing these people in the right way would do the trick, but that is precisely the point being made here.

  24. In this paper I follow the convention of using small capital letters to refer to concepts.

  25. In fact, these conditions cannot quite be said to be sufficient for use of the transparency method, because they do not rule out deviant causal chains of the kind famously discussed by Davidson (1973/2001). Suffice it to say, for now, that the transparency method is used only if all the listed conditions are met and the intentions of the first two conditions cause the embedded mental action of the third and fourth conditions in the right way.

  26. I do not, however, endorse the claim that judgment at some time t is sufficient for belief at any other time t’, or for any interval of time T.

  27. I do not mean, here, simply to interdefine judgment and belief as (for example) Crane (2001) does: “judgment is the formation of belief” (p. 104). I take judgment that p to be possible when one already has the belief that p. If judgment just is, by definition, the formation of belief, then either this would not be possible, or one would have to be able to supplant a pre-existing belief that p with a new belief that p just by judging that p. Both options seem unattractive.

  28. There is no in-principle limitation on how short-lived genuine beliefs can be. There is no absurdity in saying “I really believed that for just one moment.” Consider the following example. In a hurry to catch a flight, I rush through airport security and pause, uncertain which gate is mine. I glance at my boarding pass and see “34B.” I start towards gate 34B, before realizing, just one moment later, that “34B” is my seat and my gate is instead 11B. I pivot on my heel and take off in the opposite direction. In this situation, it is true that I believed that my gate was 34B—my taking a particular directed action to move towards the higher-numbered gates illustrates that—but I believed it just momentarily.

  29. It’s not even obvious that we must deny that one has the relevant belief over the extended interval. This scenario might best be understood as a case of conflicting belief instead. If one judges that p at t, one must also believe that p at t. But one may also judge that p at t while believing that ¬p as well.

  30. I’d like to thank an anonymous reviewer for highlighting this point.

  31. See also Wittgenstein (1958), Shoemaker (1968), and Pryor (1999).

  32. For more on using the first-person in self-attribution of belief, see Boyle (2009b, pp. 153–4).

  33. Here I do not mean to endorse the general principle that any inference or application of a concept whose availability to the subject is required for possessing that concept are inferences or applications to which the possessor is then entitled at any time. In its general form, this principle has interesting counterexamples. See Boghossian and Williamson (2003) for extended discussion.

  34. Those who take content externalism to threaten self-knowledge (e.g. Boghossian 1989) may disagree that this is all that’s necessary by way of warrant here. I take the line endorsed by Burge (1996), Heil (1988), and Peacocke (1996) on this point: there is no such threat. Those still concerned about content externalism should at least note one nice feature of any given embedded mental actions: one and the same intentional mental action cannot enjoy two distinct environments that might contribute to the individuation of content. Cf. Burge (1996) on self-verifying judgments.

  35. Some might argue that this is not even necessary; true warranted judgment could count as knowledge just as much as true warranted belief could. I simply accept this point.

  36. See Cassam (2014), p. 5–6, for a helpful characterization of these intuitions. Compare Moran (2001, Section 4.5), and Heal (2002, p. 2). Russell’s (1912) claim that we are directly acquainted with our own mental states can also be understood as expressing the thought that our knowledge of our own beliefs is both epistemically and psychologically immediate.

  37. See, however, Paul (2012) for an argument to the contrary.

  38. I’m indebted to an anonymous reviewer of this paper for a careful presentation of this objection.

  39. I’m grateful to Peter Epstein for expressing this point in a compelling way.

References

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957). Intention. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnett, D. J. (2015). Inferential justification and the transparency of belief. Noûs, 50(1), 1–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, P. (1989). Content and self-knowledge. Philosophical Topics, 17(1), 5–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, P. (2014). What is inference? Philosophical Studies, 169, 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boghossian, P., & Williamson, T. (2003). Blind reasoning. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 77, 225–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, M. (2009a). Active belief. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 39(sup. 1), 119–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, M. (2009b). Two kinds of self-knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 78, 133–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, M. (2011). Self-knowledge and transparency II: Transparent self-knowledge. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, LXXXV, 223–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brueckner, A. (1998). Moore inferences. The Philosophical Quarterly, 48(192), 366–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1996). Our entitlement to self-knowledge I. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 96, 91–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2005). Introspection. Philosophical Topics, 33(1), 79–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2011). Self-knowledge and transparency I: Transparency, belief, intention. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, LXXXV, 201–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2012). Knowing what I want. In J. Liu & J. Perry (Eds.), Consciousness and the self: New essays (pp. 165–183). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassam, Q. (2014). Self-knowledge for humans. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2001). Elements of mind: An introduction to the philosophy of mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1963/2001). Actions, reasons, and causes. In D. Davidson (Ed.), Essays on action and events (pp. 3–19). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Davidson, D. (1973/2001). Freedom to act. In D. Davidson (Ed.), Essays on action and events (pp. 63–81). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Davidson, D. (1984/2001). First person authority. In D. Davidson (Ed.), Subjective, intersubjective, objective (pp. 3–14). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Davidson, D. (1987/2001). Knowing one’s own mind. In D. Davidson (Ed.), Subjective, intersubjective, objective (pp. 15–38). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Edgley, R. (1969). Reason in theory and practice. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1979). Logic. In G. Frege (Ed.), Posthumous writings (pp. 1–8). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallois, A. (1996). The world without, the mind within. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23(6), 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, M., & Williams, J. N. (Eds.). (2007). Moore’s paradox: New essays on belief, rationality, and the first person. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heal, J. (2002). On first-person authority. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 102, 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. (1988). Privileged access. Mind, 97, 238–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moran, R. (2001). Authority and estrangement: An essay on self-knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran, R. (2003). Responses to O’Brien and Shoemaker. European Journal of Philosophy, 11(3), 402–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moran, R. (2004). Replies to Heal, Reginster, Wilson, and Lear. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69(2), 455–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moran, R. (2012). Self-knowledge, ‘transparency’, and the forms of activity. In D. Smithies & D. Stoljar (Eds.), Introspection and Consciousness (pp. 211–236). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, L. (2003). Moran on agency and self-knowledge. European Journal of Philosophy, 11(3), 375–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, L. (2005). Self-knowledge, agency, and force. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 71(3), 580–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, L. (2007). Self-knowing agents. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, L., & Soteriou, M. (Eds.). (2009). Mental action. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paul, S. K. (2012). How we know what we intend. Philosophical Studies, 161, 327–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1996). Our entitlement to self-knowledge II: Entitlement, self-knowledge, and conceptual redeployment. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 96, 117–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1998). Conscious attitudes, attention, and self-knowledge. In C. Wright, B. C. Smith, & C. MacDonald (Eds.), Knowing our own minds (pp. 63–121). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (2008). Mental action. In C. Peacocke (Ed.), Truly understood (pp. 245–285). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pryor, J. (1999). Immunity to error through misidentification. Philosophical Topics, 26(1), 271–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pryor, J. (2005). There is immediate justification. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 181–202). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1912/2004). The problems of philosophy. New York: Barnes & Noble Books.

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. London: Barnes & Noble.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1971a). A puzzling element in the notion of thinking. In G. Ryle (Ed.), Collected papers, volume II: Collected essays 1929–1968 (pp. 391–406). London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1971b). Thinking and reflecting. In G. Ryle (Ed.), Collected papers, volume II: Collected essays 1929–1968 (pp. 465–479). London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1971c). The thinking of thoughts: What is ‘Le Penseur’ doing? In G. Ryle (Ed.), Collected papers, volume II: Collected essays 1929–1968 (pp. 480–496). London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2002). A phenomenal, dispositional account of belief. Noûs, 36(2), 249–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2012). Self-ignorance. In J. Liu & J. Perry (Eds.), Consciousness and the self: New essays. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Setiya, K. (2011). Knowledge of intention. In A. Ford, J. Hornsby, & F. Stoutland (Eds.), Essays on Anscombe’s intention (pp. 170–197). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shah, N., & Velleman, J. D. (2005). Doxastic deliberation. The Philosophical Review, 114(4), 497–534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1968). Self-reference and self-awareness. Journal of Philosophy, 65(19), 555–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1988). On knowing one’s own mind. Philosophical Perspectives, 2, 183–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1995). Moore's paradox and self-knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 77(2/3), 211–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2003). Moran on self-knowledge. European Journal of Philosophy, 11(3), 391–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2009). Self-intimation and second-order belief. Erkenntnis, 71(1), 35–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silins, N. (2012). Judgment as a guide to belief. In D. Smithies & D. Stoljar (Eds.), Introspection and consciousness (pp. 295–327). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1976). Deciding to believe. In B. Williams (Ed.), Problems of the self: Philosophical papers 1956–1972 (pp. 136–151). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.    

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, J. N. (2004). Moore's paradoxes, Evans's principle and self-knowledge. Analysis, 64(4), 348–353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, G. M. (2004). Review: Comments on authority and estrangement. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69(2), 440–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958). The blue and brown books. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (1989). Wittgenstein’s later philosophy of mind: Sensation, privacy, and intention. Journal of Philosophy, 86(11), 622–634.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for invaluable commentary on an earlier draft. For earlier illuminating commentary and extensive discussion, I would also like to thank John Campbell, Barry Stroud, and Christopher Peacocke. Thanks also to Jackson Kernion, Eugene Chislenko, Jim Hutchinson, Julian Jonker, Philippe Chuard, Alex Kerr, Michael Martin, Melissa Fusco, Rachel Rudolph, Alex Kocurek, Ravit Dotan, Austin Andrews, Adam Bradley, Quinn Gibson, Peter Epstein, Umrao Sethi, Dylan Murray, Kathryn Grzenczyk Mantoan, Jeffrey Kaplan, Kirsten Pickering, and Ethan Jerzak.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Antonia Peacocke.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Peacocke, A. Embedded mental action in self-attribution of belief. Philos Stud 174, 353–377 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0685-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0685-4

Keywords

Navigation