Skip to main content
Log in

Combining the representational and the relational view

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper tries to meet the three basic constraints in the metaphysics of perception—that, following Schellenberg (Philos Stud 149:19–48, 2010), I call here the particularity constraint, the indistinguishable constraint, and the phenomenological constraint—by putting forward a new combination of the two well-known contradictory views in this field: the relational view and the content view. Following other compatibilists (such as Schellenberg in Philos Stud 149:19–48, 2010), I do think that it is possible to reconcile the two views, recognizing that experience has both a relational and a representational dimension. However, in opposition to the current ways of combining these two views, I reject the idea of gappy contents. Instead, my proposal is builds on Lewis’s famous semantic (Philosophy and grammar, Riedel, Dordrecht, 1980b), according to which the content of sentences is best modeled as complex functions from context-index pairs to truth-values. In conformity with the content view, I want to suggest that perceptual experiences do represent complex properties or complex functions (e.g., being a yellow-cube-straight-ahead) that are either veridical or falsidical of particulars in contexts and indexes. In this relativist framework, I can also accommodate the relational claim that our experience of particulars must be understood as a fundamental cognitive relation rather than as a representation. In this way, particulars also play a key role in individuating perceptual experiences. Two token experiences, e and e′, are different when one of the following conditions is met: first, if two different particulars, a and a′, are causally responsible for the token experiences e and e′, respectively, regardless of the time and location in which the perceptual experiences take place; second, if the same particular a, which is causally responsible for both e and e′, is either located in a different place or is in the same location but at a different time.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1965). The intentionality of sensation: A grammatical feature. In R. J. Butler (Ed.), Analytical philosophy: Second series. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1968). A materialist theory of the mind. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (1987). Thought and reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (1997). Searle against the World. Unpublished. http://userwww.sfsu.edu/~kbach/Searle.html.

  • Brewer, B. (2006). Perception and content. European Journal of Philosophy, 14, 165–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1991). Vision and intentional content. In E. Lepore & R. Van Gulick (Eds.), John Searle and his critics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (2002). Reference and consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M. (1992). Perceptual content and local supervenience. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 92, 1992.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1969). Seeing and knowing. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fish, W. (2009). Perception, hallucination, and illusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1961). The causal theory of perception. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supp. 35, 121–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1990). The intrinsic quality of experience. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 31–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (2004). The obscure object of hallucination. Philosophical Studies, 120, 113–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (2006). Better than mere knowledge? The function of sensory awareness. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 260–290). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1980a). Veridical hallucination and prosthetic vision. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 58, 239–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1980b). Index, context, and content. In S. Kanger, & S. Öhman (eds.), Philosophy and grammar (pp 79–100). Dordrecht: Riedel.

  • Lycan, W. G. (1996). Consciousness and experience. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (2002). Particular thoughts and singular thought. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 51, 173–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (2004). The limits of self-awareness. Philosophical Studies, 120, 37–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (2006). On being alienated. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 354–410). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1991). Intentionality De Re. In E. Lepore & R. Van Gulick (Eds.), John Searle and his critics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1982). The character of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1947). A system of logic. London: Longmans.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1993). Book review: The imagery debate Michael Tye. Philosophy of Science, 60(4), 675–677.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pitcher, G. (1970). Pain perception. Philosophical Review, 74(July), 368–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1912). The problems of philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, S. (2010). The particularity and phenomenology of perceptual experience. Philosophical Studies, 149, 19–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Soteriou, M. (2000). The particularity of visual perception. European Journal of Philosophy, 8, 173–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Travis, C. (2004). The silence of the senses. Mind, 113, 57–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (1992). Visual qualia and visual content. In T. Crane (Ed.), The contents of experience (pp. 158–176). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness: A representational theory of the phenomenal mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2009). Consciousness revisited: Materialism without phenomenal concepts. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roberto Horácio de Sá Pereira.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

de Sá Pereira, R.H. Combining the representational and the relational view. Philos Stud 173, 3255–3269 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0662-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0662-y

Keywords

Navigation