Skip to main content
Log in

Rights bearers and rights functions

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The Will Theory of Rights has commonly been criticized for excluding from the class of rights bearers all subjects who are incapable of agency. The Interest Theory of Rights faces the challenge of avoiding undue proliferation of the class of rights bearers. I advance a novel argument for a specific demarcation of the class of rights bearers. I then argue that this demarcation implies that the function of the moral rights of subjects incapable of exercising agency is to protect them from being treated with illegitimate disregard in a certain sense. I advance reasons for holding that this theory is neither a Will Theory nor an Interest Theory, or a combination of these theories. The proposed account is significant also if it is interpreted as a version of the Interest Theory. It brings significant benefits in the form of cohesiveness, simplicity, and intuitive appeal.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Here, I follow my discussion in Andersson (2013, pp. 176–179).

  2. I am grateful to a referee of this journal for drawing my attention to this point.

  3. Here, I follow my discussion in Andersson (2013, pp. 186–187).

  4. “Demand” theories of rights hold that rights are something that can be “demanded” or “insisted upon.” Cf. ( Feinberg 1973, pp. 58–59; Darwall 2006, p. 18; Skorupski 2010, XII. 6, XIV. 2–3). Such accounts accept unwaivable rights. Will Theorists and Demand theorists agree, however, that competence for agency is necessary in order to be a rights bearer, and this is the only aspect of these theories that is relevant for the issue of inclusion or exclusion of unempowered individuals in the class of rights bearers. Hence, the argument advanced in this article applies to all these theories.

  5. He then refines this model, but discussing the “Simple Hybrid” model is sufficient for my purposes.

  6. I am here following my discussion in Andersson (2013, pp. 175–190).

  7. It could be objected that adolescents acquire the capacity to exercise agency before becoming adults. I will assume that any subject with capacity to exercise agency in the sense of being able to make reflective choices between alternative courses of action and being able to reflect over her preferences is an adult. This ability, rather than age, determines whether a subject is an adult in the relevant sense.

  8. For thorough discussion, see (Andersson 2013, pp. 185–190).

References

  • Andersson, A. (2013) Choices, interests, and potentiality: What distinguishes bearers of rights? Journal of Value Inquiry, 2013 175–190.

  • Bentham, J. (1987). Anarchical fallacies. In J. Waldron (Ed.), Nonsense upon stilts: Bentham, Burke, and Marx on the rights of man (pp. 46–76). London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (2006). The second person standpoint (p. 18). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Fabre, C. (2009). Preconception rights. In S. de Wijze, M. H. Kramer, & I. Carter (Eds.), Hillel Steiner and the anatomy of justice (pp. 57–58). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1973). Social philosophy (pp. 58–59). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1980). Rights, justice, and the bounds of liberty: Essays in social philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Feinberg, J. (1992). Freedom and fulfilment: Philosophical Essays (p. 20). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  • Hart, H. L. A. (1955). Are there any natural rights? The Philosophical Review, 64(2), 175–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A. (1973). Legal rights (Chap. VII). In Essays on Bentham. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Hart, H. L. A. (1982). Essays on Bentham: Studies in jurisprudence and political theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hohfeld, W. (1923). Some fundamental legal conceptions as applied in judicial reasoning. In Fundamental legal conceptions as applied in judicial reasoning. New Haven: Yale University Press.

  • Kant, E. (1965). The metaphysical elements of justice (p. 35) (J. Ladd, Trans.). Indianapolis: Bodd-Merril.

  • Kant, E. (1991). The metaphysics of morals (p. 56) (M. Gregor, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kluge, E. H. W. (1975). The practice of death (pp. 17, 91). New Haven: Yale University Press.

  • Kramer, M. H. (1998). Rights without trimmings. In A debate over rights (pp. 80–91). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Kramer, M. H. (2001). Getting rights right. In M. H. Kramer (Ed.), Rights, wrongs, and responsibilities (pp. 28–95). New York: Palgrave and Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, M. H. (2010). Refining the Interest Theory of Rights. The American Journal of Jurisprudence, 55, 31–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, M. H., & Steiner, H. (2007). Theories of rights: Is there a third way? Oxford Journals of Legal Studies, 27(2), 281–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, D. (1970). The correlativity of rights and duties. Noûs, 4, 45–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons, D. (1994). Rights, welfare, and Mill’s moral theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. (1982). Children’s rights: A test case for theories of rights. In Legal right and social democracy: essays in legal and political philosophy. New York: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1986). The morality of freedom (pp. 165–192). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Skorupski, J. (2010). The domain of reasons (XII. 6, XIV. 2–3). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Solnick, P. B. (1985). Proxy consent for incompetent non-terminally ill adult patients. Journal of Legal Medicine, 6(1), 1–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sreenivasan, G. (2005). A hybrid theory of claim rights. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies., 25(2), 257–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sreenivasan, G. (2010). Duties and their directions. Ethics, 120, 465–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, H. (1994). An essay on rights. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, H. (1998). Working rights. In M. H. Kramer, N. E. Simmonds, & H. Steiner (Eds.), A debate over rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Steiner, H. (2013). Directed duties and inalienable rights. Ethics, 123(2), 230–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wenar, L. (2005). The nature of rights. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 33(3), 223–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wenar, L. (2013). The nature of claim rights. Ethics, 123(2), 202–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author gratefully acknowledges the helpful comments of a referee of this journal.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anna-Karin Margareta Andersson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Andersson, AK.M. Rights bearers and rights functions. Philos Stud 172, 1625–1646 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0368-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0368-y

Keywords

Navigation