Skip to main content
Log in

Agentive awareness is not sensory awareness

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I argue that the conscious awareness one has of oneself as acting, i.e., agentive awareness, is not a type of sensory awareness. After providing some set up in Sect. 1, I move on in Sect. 2 to sketch a profile of sensory agentive experiences (SAEs) as representational states with sensory qualities by which we come to be aware of ourselves as performing actions. In Sect. 3, I critique two leading arguments in favor of positing such sensory experiences: the argument from pathology and the argument from cognitive impenetrability. Since neither of these arguments succeeds, the case for positing SAEs is dealt a significant blow. I proceed in Sect. 4 to advance my positive argument against SAEs. The argument runs as follows: If SAEs exist, then they must exist in some sensory modality or set of sensory modalities. Either the relevant sensory modalities are ones that we already recognize, or they are novel sensory modalities. I will argue that neither of these options is workable, and so we have nowhere to locate SAEs. Agentive awareness is not sensory awareness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This brand of self-awareness has gone under a number of other labels as well, most popularly, “the sense of agency” (e.g., de Vignemont and Fourneret 2004; Gallagher 2000; Marcel 2003; Peacocke 2003). Others include “the phenomenology of agency” (e.g., Pacherie 2008), “control consciousness” (e.g., Mandik 2010), and “action consciousness” (e.g., Prinz 2007).

  2. Though this first argument, if it were successful, would not by itself be sufficient for establishing the existence of sensory agentive experiences, it is worth considering here, since some theorists may be tempted to appeal to it in order to move towards that conclusion.

  3. Certainly there is considerable dispute that the converse holds. For example, MacPherson (2012) argues that there is at least one case of color perception in which one’s beliefs about the typical colors of objects affects the colors that those objects appear to have, and that the interpretation of this result that appeals to cognitive penetration of color perception cannot be dismissed.

  4. I set aside for now mental actions such as mentally multiplying twelve times thirteen or imagining a pink elephant. It is worth noting, however, that sensory approaches to agentive awareness have difficulty accounting for such actions, especially when grounded in the comparator model, since it is unclear that forward modeling takes place in these cases given that there is no reason for a motor command to be generated (though see Campbell 1999).

  5. I’m grateful to an anonymous reviewer for directing me to this study.

  6. Though see also Prinz (2012, pp. 237–239) in which he notes some problems for the Prinz (2007) view, and ends up abandoning it in favor of a deflationary approach to agentive awareness on which there is no experience of authorship, but simply experiences of our actions and their disruption.

  7. It is worth noting that Prinz’s (2007) original proposal is that SAEs arise from the match between the forward model prediction and sensory feedback. But he revises it to exclusively rely on forward model predictions in order to accommodate cases in which agentive experiences seem to be present despite there being no sensory feedback to match with a forward model prediction, as in the case of deafferented individuals and when one is under anaesthesia.

  8. This reasoning seems problematic, however, since the two could be compared simply in terms of their representational content, in the way that a belief about something might be compared with a perception of that thing in terms of the respective content of each state, despite having different representational formats. I set aside this worry here, however, to focus on other aspects of Prinz’s view.

References

  • Albers, J. (2006). Interaction of color. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1968). A materialist theory of mind. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T. (2011). The sense of agency. In F. Macpherson (Ed.), The senses (pp. 355–374). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T., & Pacherie, E. (2007). Narrators and comparators: The architecture of agentive self-awareness. Synthese, 159, 475–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J. (2010). Action and awareness of agency: Comments on Christopher Frith. Pragmatics and Cognition, 18(3), 584–596.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, S.-J., & Frith, C. (2003). Self-awareness and action. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 13, 219–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, S.-J., Frith, C. D., & Wolpert, D. M. (1999). Spatio-temporal prediction modulates the perception of self-produced stimuli. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 11(5), 551–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, S.-J., Goodbody, S. J., & Wolpert, D. M. (1998). Predicting the consequences of our own actions: The role of sensorimotor context estimation. The Journal of Neuroscience, 18(18), 7511–7518.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, S.-J., Oakley, D. A., & Frith, C. D. (2003). Delusions of alien control in the normal brain. Neuropsychologia, 41(8), 1058–1067.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, S.-J., Smith, J., Steel, R., Johnstone, C. E., & Frith, C. D. (2000a). The perception of self-produced sensory stimuli in patients with auditory hallucinations and passivity experiences: Evidence for a breakdown in self-monitoring. Psychological Medicine, 30(5), 1131–1139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, S.-J., Wolpert, D., & Frith, C. (2000b). Why can’t you tickle yourself? NeuroReport, 11(11), R11–R16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2003). Mental paint. In M. Hahn & B. Ramberg (Eds.), Reflections and replies: Essays on the philosophy of Tyler Burge. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2009). Experience and Content. Philosphical Quarterly, 59, 429–451.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (1999). Schizophrenia, the space of reasons and thinking as a motor process. The Monist, 82(4), 609–625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J. D., Bizzell, J., Kim, C., Bellion, C., Carpenter, K. L., Dichter, G., & Belger, A. (2010). Attention deficits in schizophrenia—preliminary evidence of dissociable transient and sustained deficits. Schizophrenia Research, 122(1–3), 104–112.

  • Carruthers, G. (2012). The case for the comparator model as an explanation of the sense of agency and its breakdowns. Consciousness and Cognition, 21, 30–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2004). The representational character of experience. In B. Leiter (Ed.), The future for philosophy (pp. 153–181). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Vignemont, F. (2011). Embodiment, ownership and disownership. Consciousness and Cognition, 20, 82–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Vignemont, F., & Fourneret, P. (2004). The sense of agency: A philosophical and empirical review of the ‘‘who’’ system. Consciousness and Cognition, 13, 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Della Sala, S. (2005). The anarchic hand. The Psychologist, 18(10), 606–609.

    Google Scholar 

  • Desantis, A., Weiss, C., Schutz-Bosbach, S., & Waszak, F. (2012). Believing and perceiving: Authorship belief modulates sensory attenuation. PLoS One, 7(5), e37959.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. (1992). The cognitive neuropsychology of schizophrenia. Hove: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. (2007). Making up the mind: How the brain creates our mental world. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. D., Blakemore, S., & Wolpert, D. M. (2000). Explaining the symptoms of schizophrenia: Abnormalities in the awareness of action. Brain Research Reviews, 31(2–3), 357–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2000). Philosophical conceptions of the self: Implications for cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4(1), 14–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gold, J. M., Fuller, R. L., Robinson, B. M., Braun, E. L., & Luck, S. J. (2007). Impaired top-down control of visual search in schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Research, 94(1–3), 148–155.

  • Haggard, P., Clark, S., & Kalogeras, J. (2002). Voluntary action and conscious awareness. Nature Neuroscience, 5(4), 382–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1990). The intrinsic quality of experience. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 31–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keeley, B. L. (2002). Making sense of the senses: Individuating modalities in humans and other animals. Journal of Philosophy, 99(1), 5–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindner, A., Thier, P., Kircher, T. T., Haarmeier, T., & Leube, D. T. (2005). Disorders of agency in schizophrenia correlate with an inability to compensate for the sensory consequences of actions. Current Biology, 15(12), 1119–1124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacPherson, F. (2011). Individuating the senses. In F. Macpherson (Ed.), The senses (pp. 3–43). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacPherson, F. (2012). Cognitive penetration of colour experience: Rethinking the issue in light of an indirect mechanism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84(1), 24–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandik, P. (2010). Control consciousness. Topics in Cognitive Science, 2, 643–657.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marcel, A. (2003). The sense of agency: Awareness and ownership of action. In J. Roessler & N. Eilan (Eds.), Agency and self-awareness: Issues in philosophy and psychology (pp. 48–93). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellors, C. S. (1970). First-rank symptoms of schizophrenia. British Journal of Psychiatry, 117, 15–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, T. (2006). Conscious volition and mental representation: Toward a more fine-grained analysis. In N. Sebanz & W. Prinz (Eds.), Disorders of volition (pp. 19–48). Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mylopoulos, M. I. (2011). Why reject a sensory imagery theory of control consciousness? Topics in Cognitive Science, 3(2), 268–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mylopoulos, M. (2012). Evaluating the case for the low-level approach to agentive awareness. Philosophical Topics, 40(2), 103–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie, E. (2008). The phenomenology of action: A conceptual framework. Cognition, 107, 179–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (2003). Awareness, ownership, and knowledge. In J. Roessler & N. Eilan (Eds.), Agency and self-awareness: Issues in philosophy and psychology (pp. 94–110). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penfield, W. (1975). The mystery of the mind: A critical study of consciousness and the human brain. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, D. (2004). The phenomenology of cognition or what is it like to think that p? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69(1), 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. J. (2007). All consciousness is perceptual. In B. P. McLaughlin & J. Cohen (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of mind. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. J. (2012). The conscious brain: How attention engenders experience. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M. (2004). Varieties of higher-order theory. In R. J. Gennaro (Ed.), Higher-order theories of consciousness: An anthology (pp. 17–44). Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins B. V.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M. (2005). Consciousness and mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shergill, S. S., Samson, G., Bays, P. M., Frith, C. D., & Wolpert, D. M. (2005). Evidence for sensory prediction deficits in schizophrenia. American Journal of Psychiatry, 162(12), 2384–2386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1994). Self-knowledge and “inner sense”: Lecture I: The object perception model. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54(2), 249–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spence, S. A., Brooks, D. J., Hirsch, S. R., Liddle, P. F., Meehan, J., & Grasby, P. M. (1997). A PET study of voluntary movement in schizophrenic patients experiencing passivity phenomena (delusions of alien control). Brain, 120(Pt 11), 1997–2011.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Synofzik, M., Vosgerau, G., & Newen, A. (2008). Beyond the comparator model: A multifactorial two-step account of agency. Consciousness and Cognition, 17(1), 219–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2000). Consciousness, color, and content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2003). Consciousness and persons: Unity and identity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiller, C., Juptner, M., Fellows, S., Rijntjes, M., Leonhardt, G., Kiebel, S., et al. (1996). Brain representation of active and passive movements. Neuroimage, 4(2), 105–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert, D. M. (1997). Computational approaches to motor control. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 1(6), 209–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wong, H. Y. (2012). A measure of my agency? Consciousness and Cognition, 21(1), 48–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I’m very grateful to Jacob Berger, Grace Helton, David Rosenthal, Frédérique de Vignemont, and audiences at the Graduate Center, CUNY, and NYU for helpful feedback on earlier drafts of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Myrto I. Mylopoulos.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mylopoulos, M.I. Agentive awareness is not sensory awareness. Philos Stud 172, 761–780 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0332-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0332-x

Keywords

Navigation