Skip to main content
Log in

Pretense and imagination from the perspective of 4E cognitive science: introduction to the special issue

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this text, we will introduce the reader to the special issue on Pretense and Imagination from the Perspective of 4E Cognitive Science. To do so, we will introduce the concept of 4E cognition and showcase what the available 4E approaches to pretense and imagination look like, in particular if they are contrasted with current cognitivist accounts. Against this background, we provide an overview of the articles included in this special issue.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a useful overview of the meanings behind each ‘E’, see Newen, de Bruin & Gallagher (2018).

  2. While 4E approaches to pretense and imagination are novel to current trends in philosophy and cognitive science, they are often inspired by the works of analytic philosophers such as Ludwig Wittgenstein or Gilbert Ryle, phenomenologists Martin Heidegger, Maurice Merleau-Ponty and Jean-Paul Sartre, pragmatists Herbert Mead and John Dewey, or psychologists Leo Vygotsky and Herbert Mead, whose views in many ways prefigure the current 4E trends to pretense and imagination. Providing a further historical grounding of 4E thought on imagination and pretense is beyond the scope of this introduction.

  3. In this section, we will focus mainly on pretense to showcase the differences between the orthodox cognitivist proposals and available embodied and enactive proposals of accounting for pretense. After all, while some imaginings are accepted to be embodied, non-propositional, and possibly non-representational, this is not the case with pretense, which is seen as necessarily a representational phenomenon for the reasons presented in this section.

  4. There are many notions of mental representation available in the literature, and much discussion over the roles they play in philosophy and in cognitive science (for a recent edited volume, see Smortchkova et al., (2020)). However, to explain pretense and imagination, not any notion of mental representation will do. The notion of representation most likely to play a relevant role in the abovementioned theories is one that refers to a mental object with semantic properties (content, reference, truth-conditions, truth-value) and fulfils some conditions of satisfaction, because in pretend play one ‘replaces one thought content for another’, or specifies one thing under a new description. Conversely, any weak notion of mental representation (e.g., environmentally-correlated inner states or mappings) is not the notion of representation that carries the relevant weight to explain pretense as a representational phenomenon, and is not thereby a notion that 4E cognition would necessarily take issue with.

  5. Such proposal finds support in Gilbert Ryle’s (1949) anti-Cartesian philosophical position targeting the taking of the ‘mental’ to the realm of the ‘inner’. Ryle argues that pretending does not require additional operations such as “seeing things in the mind’s eye, hearing things in one’s head and so on, i.e. some piece of fancied perceiving” (1949, pp. 233–234).

  6. This view finds ground in Jean-Paul Sartre’s (2004) view that “[t]he expression ‘mental image’ gives rise to confusion” (p. 7), as mental imagery is better thought of as a process of consciousness, and not a ‘picture’ found in consciousness.

  7. These articles focus mainly on pretense. Imagination is only discussed in the context of pretense engagements, such as play or performance.

  8. For more on the discussion about the compatibility of 4E cognition with ecological psychology, see McGann et al., (2020).

  9. Radical enactivism is a particular variety of enactivism that emphasizes that there are basic forms of cognition that do not involve representational content (see Hutto & Myin 2013, 2017).

References

  • Baron-Cohen, S. (1991). Precursors to a theory of mind: Understanding attention in others. Natural theories of mind: Evolution development and simulation of everyday mindreading, 1, 233–251

    Google Scholar 

  • Clowes, R. W., & Mendonça, D. (2016). Representation Redux: Is there still a useful role for representation to play in the context of embodied, dynamicist and situated theories of mind? New Ideas in Psychology, 40, 26–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (2004). Arts and Minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G., & Ravenscroft, I. (2002). Recreative Minds: Imagination in Philosophy and Psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Durt, C., Tewes, C., & Fuchs, T. (Eds.). (2017). Embodiment, enaction, and culture: Investigating the constitution of the shared world. MIT Press

  • Fiske, S. T., & Taylor, S. E. (2013). Social cognition: From brains to culture. Sage

  • Foglia, L., & Grush, R. (2011). The Limitations of a Purely Enactive (Non-Representational) Account of Imagery. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 18(5–6), 35–43

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist interventions: Rethinking the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, T. R., & Winner, E. (2011). Engagement in role play, pretense, and acting classes predict advanced theory of mind skill in middle childhood. Imagination Cognition and Personality, 30(3), 249–258

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, P. L., & Kavanaugh, R. D. (1993). Young Children’s Understanding of Pretense.Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development58 (1) (Serial No. 231).

  • Hutto, D. D. (2015). Overly enactive imagination? Radically re-imagining imagining. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 53, 68–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic Minds without Content. Cambridge: MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2017). Evolving enactivism: Basic minds meet content. MIT Press

  • Ilundáin-Agurruza, J. (2017). Muscular Imaginings—A Phenomenological and Enactive Model for Imagination. Sport Ethics and Philosophy, 11(1), 92–108

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ingold, T. (2013). Making: Anthropology, archaeology, art and architecture. Routledge

  • Kind, A. (2022). Imagination and Creative Thinking. Cambridge University Press

  • Langland-Hassan, P. (2020). Explaining imagination. Oxford University Press

  • Leslie, A. (1987). Pretense and representation: The origins of “theory of mind. Psychological Review, 94(4), 412–426

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liao, S., & Gendler, T. (2019). “Imagination”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition), E. N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/imagination

  • Lillard, A. (1994). Making sense of pretense. In C. Lewis, & P. Mitchell (Eds.), Children’s early understanding of mind: Origins and Development (pp. 211–234). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates

    Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L. (2013). How things shape the mind. MIT Press

  • McGann, M., Di Paolo, E. A., Heras-Escribano, M., & Chemero, A. (2020). Enaction and Ecological Psychology: Convergences and Complementarities. Frontiers in Psychology, 11, 617898

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Medina, J. (2013). An Enactivist Approach to the Imagination: Embodied Enactments and “Fictional Emotions”. American Philosophical Quarterly, 50(3), 317–335

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, R. W. (Ed.). (2002). Pretending and Imagination in Animals and Children. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Newen, A., De Bruin, L., & Gallagher, S. (2018). 4E cognition: Historical roots, key concepts, and central issues. The Oxford handbook of 4E cognition, 1, 3–15

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2000). A cognitive theory of pretense. Cognition, 74(2), 115–147

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2003). Mindreading: An Integrated Account of Pretence, Self-Awareness and Understanding of Other Minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J. (1991). Understanding the representational mind. MIT Press

  • Piaget, J. (1962). Play, dreams, and imitation in childhood. New York: Norton

    Google Scholar 

  • Picciuto, E., & Carruthers, P. (2016). Imagination and pretense. In A. Kind (Ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Imagination (pp. 334–345). London: Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • Read, C., & Szokolszky, A. (2016). A developmental ecological study of novel metaphoric language use. Language Sciences, 53, 86–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reddy, V., & Morris, P. (2004). Participants don’t need theories: Knowing minds in engagement. Theory & Psychology, 14(5), 647–665

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rucińska, Z. (2016). What Guides Pretence? Towards the Interactive and the Narrative Approaches. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 15(1), 117–133

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rucińska, Z. (2017). The Role of Affordances in Pretend Play. In C. Durt, T. Fuchs, & C. Tewes (Eds.), Embodiment, Enaction, and Culture: Investigating the Constitution of the Shared World (pp. 257–277). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Rucińska, Z. (2019). Social and Enactive Perspectives on Pretending. Avant, Vol. X, No. 3

  • Rucińska, Z., & Gallagher, S. (2021). Making imagination even more embodied: imagination, constraint and epistemic relevance. Synthese, 199, 8143–8170

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The Concept of Mind. London: Hutchinson

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J. P. (2004). (Original: 1940, L’Imaginaire: Psychologie Phenomenologique de l’imagination). The Imaginary: A Phenomenological Psychology of the Imagination. Lon-don: Routledge: Trans. J. Webber

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. (2014). The Routledge Handbook of Embodied Cognition, 1 Edn. London: Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group (Routledge handbooks)

  • Smortchkova, J., Dołrega, K., & Schlicht, T. (Eds.). (2020). What are mental representations?. Oxford University Press

  • Spaulding, S. (2010). Embodied Cognition and Mindreading. Mind & Language 25, pp. 119–140

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press

  • Zawidzki, T. W. (2013). Mindshaping: A new framework for understanding human social cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The special issue is based on the themes of the international conference “Pretend Play and E-Cognition”, hosted at the University of Antwerp, Belgium, on 19 and 20 September 2019. We would like to thank Erik Myin, Shaun Gallagher, Erik Rietveld and the participants of this conference who inspired the themes of this special issue, as well as the anonymous reviewers who reviewed the manuscripts submitted to this special issue.

Funding

ZR’s research was funded by FWO grant “Enactive Approaches to Pretending”, grant number 12J0419N.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding authors

Correspondence to Zuzanna Rucińska or Martin Weichold.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest:

None.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rucińska, Z., Weichold, M. Pretense and imagination from the perspective of 4E cognitive science: introduction to the special issue. Phenom Cogn Sci 21, 989–1001 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-022-09856-0

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-022-09856-0

Navigation