Skip to main content
Log in

Depicting and seeing-in. The ‘Sujet’ in Husserl’s phenomenology of images

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I investigate an underappreciated element of Husserl’s phenomenology of images: the consciousness of the depicted subject (Sujet or Bildsujet), which Husserl calls the Sujetintention, e.g. the awareness of the sitter of a portrait. Husserl claims that when a consciousness regards a figurative image, it is absorbed in the awareness of the depicted subject and yet this subject some how withholds its presence in the midst of its appearance in the image-object (Bildobjekt). Image-consciousness is an intuitive (anschaulich) consciousness that intends a being that is both ‘in’ and ‘beyond’ the image: the depicted subject haunts the image. Borrowing Richard Wollheim’s language, the aim of this study is to determine what it means for a consciousness to see a depicted-subject in an image-depiction, which happens on the basis of seeing an image-object in a material image-thing, like paint, canvas, ink, paper etc. Restricting myself to figurative images, I will argue against the view that the relation to the depicted subject is symbolic or signitive. I argue that the consciousness of the Sujet is quasi-perceptual, which allows for a better account of the depicted subject’s sense of absence. I develop this view on the basis of Husserl’s claims that the depicted subject is the bearer of norms inherent to intuitive appearances, which concern how the profiles and movements of an object ought to unfold, though they fail to do so for image-consciousness. This failure is not a mere privation for the image as a perceptual appearance but is inherent to its status as a mediated and artificial presence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I am deeply indebted to the reviewers of this paper and to Prof. Ullrich Melle. Their incisive comments have helped me to improve this paper in a way I could not have done on my own.

  2. Although we may affirm (some) aspects of Stiegler’s analyses in The Discrete Image concerning the impact that digital modes of production have had on the belief (i.e. the thetic attitude) involved in contemporary image-consciousness, his opening remarks—where he invokes the distinction between a ‘pure mental image’ and an ‘image-object’—are misleading insofar as a phenomenology of images never posits the existence of images that would be unconditioned by actual or real image-things. We must add, however, that the phenomenology of images does not and cannot suppose a specific technological history of the production of images. Such analyses must always follow more foundational ones. Further, we may, partially, disagree with Lotz who draws on Stiegler’s essay when he says that Husserl’s phenomenology of images is “anti-cultural” because Husserl ignores the techniques of image production. Rather, it would be closer to the mark to call Husserl’s analyses ‘ante-cultural.’ Cf. Stiegler 2002, 147–149, 158–159; and Lotz 2007, 178.

  3. Throughout I will privilege the use of the German term Sujet. This is to avoid two points of confusion. First, it is best to avoid any relation to the more common philosophical use of the term ‘subject.’ Goodman for one decried the “trick of language” that turns an object into a subject once it is depicted (Goodman 1968, fn #2). Second, the term ‘depicted object’ is not sufficiently clear. As Twardowski observed, when we hear someone speak of a depicted object, say a landscape that a painter has rendered, it is not clear whether s/he refers to image on the canvas or the factual, real landscape (Twardowski 1977, 11–12).

  4. All references to Husserl’s texts are to the Husserliana editions, followed by page references to the English translation in square brackets.

  5. Among others, I would like to highlight here: Brough 1999, Bernet 2004, Lotz 2007, Ferencz-Flatz 2009, de Warren 2010, Wiesing 2010, Brough 2012, Aldea 2013.

  6. Cf. Aldea 2013, 374–375. The first sort of seeing-in is the one already familiar to us in Wollheim’s work. Translating the two sets of terminology: seeing-in (image-consciousness) demands that we see both the medium (image-thing) and the represented object (image-object) in a single complex perceptual experience (in the unity of an intuitive intentional act) (Wollheim 1980, 219).

  7. “Die ‘Verdecktheit’ des Trägers ist die genuine Weise seiner Gegebenheit. Verdecktheit heißt aber nicht Unsichtigkeit.” My translation.

  8. “…es ist berufener Erreger für eine bestimmte Bilderscheinung.” My translation.

  9. For the image, visit: http://www.musee-orsay.fr/fr/collections/oeuvres-commentees/peinture.html?no_cache=1&zoom=1&tx_damzoom_pi1%5BshowUid%5D=1862

  10. For a concise description of the role of apprehensions and sensory-contents in image-consciousness, cf. Bernet 2004, 86.

  11. Translation slightly modified.

  12. In a later text from 1921/1924 Husserl discusses this in terms of ‘mode of performance’ rather than attitude: “The terms ‘phantasy’ and ‘fiction’ therefore have two significational directions: 1) One is directed toward reproduction (and re-presentation of whatever kind), […] 2) The other is directed toward the mode of performing” (Hua XXIII; 575 [693]). My emphases.

  13. Husserl also notes that there is a class of images that function like signs and bear external, associative relations to their ‘meant’ objects. For instance, a gallery catalogue might present miniature pictures of the paintings on display. These images merely indicate which rooms contain which paintings, and do not really work to depict landscapes, or duchesses, or bowls of fruit. A certain image might also work like an “Erinnerungszeichen”, not so much depicting the Sujet as reminding one of it (Hua XXIII, 35 [38]).

  14. My translation.

  15. Brough also argues that the Sujetintention cannot be a symbolic consciousness, since the symbol and the symbolized do not have the same relation of identity and difference as the depiction and depicted. The appearance of a name neither adequately nor inadequately represents the perceptual traits of the thing it designates (Brough 1999, 120–121).

  16. An important qualification: For Husserl a totally empty intuition is a contradiction in terms, like a round square. The empty components of perception are usually the hidden profiles of an object; one profile is directly visible while we emptily perceive the others. In the case of searching for the key in the cushions, however, we do not yet see any key-profiles or feel any key-surfaces. Nonetheless we do not merely expect the key (in the sense of a presentification of it). Rather, our perception has motivated protentional components; the perception of the key does in some sense have fulfilled components as we feel the couch that we intend as the key-setting. Hence there is a contiguity in the perception of the couch and the eventually found key, even though they are distinct objects.

  17. I stress again that this demand only imposes itself to the extent that we, the viewers of the image, are interested in having the image-subject give itself in a direct intuition.

  18. Brough develops a similar position, though he says that concepts necessarily mediate image-consciousness. This move accommodates non-figurative art, whose Sujet may be an abstract concept which requires abstract artistic representation, but it brings together two definitions of ‘idea’ that I would want to keep separate: one perceptual-prescriptive (which is immanent to perception), the other theoretical-eidetic (which is extraneous to perception and is constituted in a higher order cognitive act). (cf. Brough 2012, 557; 559–560).

  19. “C’est. le vrai Cervin (absent) que je vois à travers ‘la fenêtre’ de l’image et c’est. lui qui m’empêche de prendre l’image-objet pour une vraie réalité.” My translation, my emphasis.

References

  • Aldea, A. S. (2013). Husserl’s struggle with mental images. Continental Philosophy Review, 46, 371–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barthes, R. (1980). La chambre claire. Paris: Cahiers du Cinéma.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barthes, R. (1985). The responsibility of forms, tr. Hill and Wang: Richard Howard. New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernet, R. (1995). Perception as a teleological process of cognition in Husserl. In R. Bernet, D. Welton, & G. Zavota (Eds.), Edmund Husserl: critical assessments (Vol. III, pp. 159–171). London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernet, R. (2004). Conscience et existence. Perspectives phénoménologiques. Paris: PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brough, J. (1999). Cuts and bonds: Husserl’s systematic investigation of representation. Philosophy Today, 43, 115–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brough, J. (2012). Something that is nothing but can be anything. The image and our consciousness of it. In D. Zahavi (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of contemporary phenomenology (pp. 545–563). Oxford: Oxford UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Warren, N. (2010). Tamino’s eyes, Pamina’s gaze. Husserl’s phenomenology of image-consciousness refashioned. In C. Ierna, H. Jacobs, & F. Mattens (Eds.), Philosophy, phenomenology, sciences (pp. 303–332). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ferencz-Flatz, C. (2009). Gibt es perzeptive Phantasie? Als-ob-Bewusstsein, Widerstreit und Neutralität in Husserls Aufzeichnungen zur Bildbetrachtung. Husserl Studies, 25, 235–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fink, E. (1966). Studien zur Phänomenologie 1930–1939. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1968). Languages of art. An approach to a theory of symbols. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merril.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, R. (1998). Picture, image and experience. Cambridge UP: A philosophical inquiry. Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1969). Zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins. Husserliana X. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1977). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und Phänomenologischen Philosophie. Erstes Buch. Husserliana III.1. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1980). Phantasie, Bildbewusstsein und Erinnerung. Zur Phänomenologie der anschaulichen Vergegenwartigungen. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1898-1925). Husserliana XXIII. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. (1984a). Logische Untersuchungen, Band 1. Zweiter Teil. Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis. Husserliana XIX/1. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1984b). Logische Untersuchungen, Band 2. Zweiter Teil. Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis. Husserliana XIX/2. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1991). On the phenomenology of the consciousness of internal time (1893–1917), J.B. Brough (tr.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2001). Logical investigations, volume 2, J.N. Findlay (tr.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2005). Phantasy, image-consciousness and memory (1898–1925), J. Brough (tr.). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2014). Ideas for a pure phenomenology and phenomenological philosophy. First book, D. Dahlstrom (tr.). Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • IJsseling, S. (1997). Mimesis. On appearing and being, trs. H. IJsseling and J. Bloechel. Kampen: KOK Pharos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lotz, C. (2007). Depiction and plastic perception. A critique of Husserl’s theory of picture consciousness. Continental Philosophy Review, 40, 171–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (2005). Imaginaire. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokolowski, R. (1971). Husserlian meditations. Evanston: Northwestern UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stiegler, B. (2002). The discrete image. In B. Stiegler & J. Derrida (Eds.), Echographies of television (pp. 145–164). Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Twardowski, K. (1977) On the content and object of presentations, R. Grossmann (tr.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Vernant, J.-P. (2006) Myth and thought among the Greeks, J. Loyd and F. Fort (trs.). New York: Zone books.

  • Volonté, P. (1997). Husserls Phänomenologie der Imagination. Freiburg/Munich: Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiesing, L. (2005). Artifizielle Präsenz. Suhrkamp: Studien zur Philosophie des Bildes. Frankfurt a.M.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiesing, L. (2010). Artificial presence. Philosophical studies in image theory, N.F. Schott (tr.). Stanford: Stanford UP.

  • Wollheim, R. (1980). Art and its objects. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wollheim, R. (1987). Painting as an art. Princeton UP: Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Patrick Eldridge.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Eldridge, P. Depicting and seeing-in. The ‘Sujet’ in Husserl’s phenomenology of images. Phenom Cogn Sci 17, 555–578 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9531-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9531-1

Keywords

Navigation