Skip to main content
Log in

Symmetry-breaking dynamics in development

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recognition of the plasticity of development — from gene expression to neuroplasticity — is increasingly undermining the traditional distinction between structure and function, or anatomy and behavior. At the same time, dynamic systems theory — a set of tools and concepts drawn from the physical sciences — has emerged as a way of describing what Maurice Merleau-Ponty calls the “dynamic anatomy” of the living organism. This article surveys and synthesizes dynamic systems models of development from biology, neuroscience, and psychology in order to propose an integrated account of growth, learning, and behavior. Key to this account is the concept of self-differentiation or symmetry-breaking. I argue that development can be understood as a cascade of symmetry-breaking events brought about by the ongoing interactions of multiple, nested, nonlinear dynamic systems whose self-organizing behaviors gradually alter their own anatomical conditions. I begin by introducing the concept of symmetry-breaking as a way of understanding anatomical development. I then extend this approach to motor development by arguing that the organism’s behavior grows along with its body, like a new organ. Finally, I argue that the organism’s behavior and its world grow together dialectically, each driving the other to become more complex and asymmetrical through its own increasing asymmetry. Thus development turns out to be a form of cognition or sense-making, and cognition a form of development.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Multicellular organisms also evolved from single-celled organisms. Thus the enactive approach also emphasizes the evolved character of both cognition and development (Thompson 2007). However, this article focuses not on evolution, but on development, which is many orders of magnitude faster and thus much easier to observe directly.

  2. For more on the relation between Merleau-Ponty and enactivism, including criticism in both directions, see Dreyfus 2002, Marratto 2012, Moss Brender 2013, Pollard 2014, Thompson 2007.

  3. On Merleau-Ponty’s method of using scientific sources for philosophical purposes, see Meacham 2014, Morris 2012, Rouse 2004, Toadvine 2009, Welsh 2006. My own use of empirical research is informed both by Merleau-Ponty’s method and by his results, which this article attempts to revise and build upon using more recent science.

  4. For more on Merleau-Ponty’s discussion of embryology and development in the Nature lectures, see Foti 2013, Hansen 2004, Morris 2008.

  5. For introductions to dynamic systems theory, see Norton 1995, Strogatz 2001.

  6. This focus on symmetry-breaking distinguishes my account from those of Johnston and Edwards (2002) and Lewis (2000), but I take the three accounts to be compatible and complementary.

  7. The role of symmetry-breaking in my account might usefully be compared to the role played by programs or algorithms in mechanistic accounts of development, but I lack the space to do this here. For criticism of the concept of “programs” in biology, see E. F. Keller 2000, Moss 1992, Oyama 2000, Robert 2004; and in the cognitive sciences, see Thelen and Smith 1994, van Gelder and Port 1995, van Gelder 1995, 1998.

  8. For more on the epistemological and ontological implications of these claims, and their relation to Merleau-Ponty’s concept of form (Gestalt), see Moss Brender 2013.

  9. For introductions to symmetry and symmetry-breaking, see Ball 2009, Mainzer 2005, Schmidt 2008, Stewart and Golubitsky 1992.

  10. Recall Merleau-Ponty’s claim that “physiological activity is a behavior facing an internal milieu” (Merleau-Ponty 2003, p. 179).

  11. See E. F. Keller 2000 on the current shift from structural to functional genomics (p. 7).

  12. Recall Merleau-Ponty’s claim that behavior “can be considered as a prolongation of the activity of an organism beyond its own body,” or “a physiological activity in external circuit” (2003, pp. 178–9)

  13. This mastery is equally a dependence and a vulnerability. Sensorimotor habits acquired in one environment can become a liability in novel environments, as demonstrated by the “moving room” experiments of Lee and Aronson (1974). Russon (2003) argues that this is the structure of human neurosis: embodied habits acquired in one context propel us into new situations to which these habits are no longer adequate.

  14. Recall the definition of symmetry as invariance under a transformation. We can think of the organism’s movements as transformations that reveal environmental (a)symmetries by generating variations and invariants in the organism’s perceptual field (Gibson 1950, 1965, 1986/1979). Which environmental (a)symmetries the organism discovers will thus depend on which transformations it applies (Moss Brender 2013).

References

  • Ball, P. (2009). Nature’s patterns (Vol. 3 vols). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, P., & Gluckman, P. (2011). Plasticity, robustness, development and evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, P., & Gluckman, P. (2012). Plasticity and robustness in development and evolution. International Journal of Epidemiology, 41, 219–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beer, R. D. (2009). Beyond control: The dynamics of brain-body-environment interaction in motor systems. In D. Sternad (Ed.), Progress in motor control (pp. 7–24). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bourgeois, K., Khawar, A., & Neal, S. (2005). Infant manual exploration of objects, surfaces, and their interrelations. Infancy, 8(3), 233–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruineberg, J., & Rietveld, E. (2014). Self-organization, free energy minimization, and optimal grip on a field of affordances. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 599. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2014.00599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrge, L., Sporns, O., & Smith, L. B. (2014). Developmental process emerges from extended brain–body–behavior networks. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 18(8), 395–403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chialvo, D. R. (2010). Emergent complex neural dynamics. Nature Physics, 6(10), 744–750.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chiel, H. J., & Beer, R. D. (1997). The brain has a body: Adaptive behavior emerges from interactions of nervous system, body and environment. Trends in Neurosciences, 20, 553–557.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chiel, H. J., Ting, L. H., Ekeberg, Ö., & Hartmann, M. J. (2009). The brain in its body: Motor control and sensing in a biomechanical context. The Journal of Neuroscience, 29(41), 12807–12814.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coghill, G. E. (1929). Anatomy and the problem of behavior. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1985). Treatise on man. In J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, & D. Murdoch (Trans.), The philosophical writings of Descartes, vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Original work published 1662.

  • Dreyfus, H. (2002). Intelligence without representation – Merleau-Ponty’s critique of mental representation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 367–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forgacs, G., & Newman, S. A. (2005). Biological physics of the developing embryo. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Foti, V. M. (2013). Tracing expression in Merleau-Ponty: Aesthetics, philosophy of biology, and ontology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation? The Journal of Philosophy, 92(7), 345–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder, T. (1998). The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21(5), 615–665.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder, T., & Port, R. F. (1995). It’s about time: An overview of the dynamical approach to cognition. In R. F. Port & T. van Gelder (Eds.), Mind as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gesell, A., & Amatruda, C. S. (1971). The Embryology of Behavior: The Beginnings of the Human Mind. Westport: Greenwood Press. Original work published in 1945.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1950). The perception of the visual world. Cambridge: Riverside Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1965). Constancy and invariance in perception. In G. Kepes (Ed.), The nature and art of motion (pp. 60–70). New York: Brazilier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1986). The ecological approach to visual perception. New York: Taylor & Francis Original work published 1979.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J., & Gibson, E. J. (1955). Perceptual learning: Differentiation or enrichment? Psychological Review, 62(1), 32–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, M. B. N. (2004). The embryology of the (in)visible. In T. Carman & M. B. N. Hansen (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Merleau-Ponty (pp. 231–264). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Held, R., & Hein, A. (1963). Movement-produced stimulation in the development of visually guided behavior. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 56(5), 872–876.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphrey, J. D. (2008). Vascular adaptation and mechanical homeostasis at tissue, cellular, and sub-cellular levels. Cell Biochemistry and Biophysics, 50(2), 53–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, T. D., & Edwards, L. (2002). Genes, interactions, and the development of behavior. Psychological Review, 109(1), 26–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaneko, K., & Yomo, T. (1999). Isologous diversification for robust development of cell society. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 199(3), 243–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, A. D. (1995). Model genetic circuits encoding autoregulatory transcription factors. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 172(2), 169–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, E. F. (2000). The century of the Gene. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, J. S. (2012). Multistability and metastability: Understanding dynamic coordination in the brain. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, B: Biological Sciences, 367(1591), 906–918.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kretch, K. S., Franchak, J. M., & Adolph, K. E. (2013). Crawling and walking infants see the world differently. Child Development, 85(4), 1503–1518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, D., & Aronson, E. (1974). Visual proprioceptive control of standing in human infants. Perception & Psychophysics, 15(3), 529–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, M. D. (2000). The promise of dynamic systems approaches for an integrated account of human development. Child Development, 71(1), 36–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. C. (1991). Biology as ideology: The doctrine of DNA. New York: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. C. (1996). Evolution as engineering. In J. Collado-Vides et al. (Eds.), Integrative approaches to molecular biology (pp. 1–10). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mainzer, K. (2005). Symmetry and complexity in dynamical systems. European Review, 13(Supp. 2), 29–48.

  • Marratto, S. L. (2012). The Intercorporeal self: Merleau-Ponty on subjectivity. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meacham, D. (2014). Sense and life: Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy of nature and evolutionary biology. Discipline Filosofiche, 24(2), 137–163.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinhardt, H. (2001). Organizer and axes formation as a self-organizing process. International Journal of Developmental Biology, 45(1), 177–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1963). The Structure of Behavior. (trans: Fisher, A.L.). Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press. Original work published 1942.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2003). Nature: Course Notes from the Collège de France. (trans: Vallier, R.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012). Phenomenology of Perception. (trans: Landes, D.). New York: Routledge. Original work published 1945.

  • Morris, D. (2008). The time and place of the organism: Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy in embryo. Alter: Revue de phénoménologie, 16, 69–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, D. (2012). Merleau-Ponty, passivity and science: From structure, sense and expression, to life as phenomenal field, via the regulatory genome. Chiasmi International: Trilingual Studies Concerning Merleau-Ponty’s Thought, 14, 89–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moss, L. (1992). A kernel of truth? On the reality of the genetic program. Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1992(1), 335–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moss Brender, N. (2013). Sense-making and symmetry-breaking: Merleau-Ponty, cognitive science, and dynamic systems theory. Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy, 17(2), 247–271.

    Google Scholar 

  • Needham, A., Barrett, T., & Peterman, K. (2002). A pick-me-up for infants' exploratory skills: Early simulated experiences reaching for objects using 'sticky mittens' enhances young infants' object exploration skills. Infant Behavior & Development, 25, 279–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson, D. J. (2012). The concept of mechanism in biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 43, 152–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson, D. J. (2013). Organisms ≠ Machines. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44(4), 669–678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson, D. J. (2014). The machine conception of the organism in development and evolution: A critical analysis. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 48, 162–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, A. (1995). Dynamics: An introduction. In R. F. Port & T. van Gelder (Eds.), Mind as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan, J. K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 939–1031.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S. (2000). The ontogeny of information (2nd ed.). Durham: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, C. (1989). The discriminating nature of infants' exploratory actions. Developmental Psychology, 25(6), 885–893.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petitot, J. (1995). Morphodynamics and attractor syntax: Constituency in visual perception and cognitive grammar. In R. F. Port & T. van Gelder (Eds.), Mind as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petitot, J., & Smith, B. (1996). Physics and the phenomenal world. In R. Poli & P. M. Simons (Eds.), Formal ontology (pp. 233–253). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pollard, C. (2014). Merleau-Ponty and embodied cognitive science. Discipline Filosofiche, 24(2), 67–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robert, J. S. (2004). Embryology, Epigenesis, and evolution: Taking development seriously. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J. (2004). Merleau-Ponty’s existential conception of science. In T. Carman & M. B. N. Hansen (Eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Merleau-Ponty (pp. 265–290). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rubinov, M., Sporns, O., van Leeuwen, C., & Breakspear, M. (2009). Symbiotic relationship between brain structure and dynamics. BMC Neuroscience, 10(1), 55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, E. S. (1945). The Directiveness of organic activities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Russon, J. (2003). Human experience: Philosophy, neurosis, and the elements of everyday life. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, J. C. (2008). From symmetry to complexity: On instabilities and the Unity in diversity in nonlinear science. International Journal of Bifurcation and Chaos, 18(4), 897–910.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sporns, O. (2011). Networks of the brain. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, I., & Golubitsky, M. (1992). Fearful symmetry: Is god a geometer? Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strogatz, S. H. (2001). Nonlinear dynamics and chaos: With applications to physics, biology, chemistry, and engineering. Cambridge: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thelen, E. (1995). Motor development: A new synthesis. The American Psychologist, 50(2), 79–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thelen, E., & Fisher, D. M. (1983). The Organization of Spontaneous leg Movements in newborn infants. Journal of Motor Behavior, 15(4), 353–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thelen, E., & Smith, L. (1994). A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition and action. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in Life. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toadvine, T. (2009). Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy of nature. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trewavas, A. (2003). Aspects of plant intelligence. Annals of Botany, 92, 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turvey, M. T., & Fitzpatrick, P. (1993). Commentary: Development of perception-action systems and general principles of pattern formation. Child Development, 64(4), 1175–1190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1991). Organism: A meshwork of selfless selves. In A. I. Tauber (Ed.), Organism and the origins of self. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Welsh, T. (2006). From gestalt to structure: Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s early analysis of the human sciences. Theory & Psychology, 16(4), 527–551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, H. R. (1999). Spikes, decisions, and actions: The dynamical foundations of neuroscience (Vol. 5). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zernicke, R. F., & Schneider, K. (1993). Biomechanics and developmental neuromotor control. Child Development, 64(4), 982–1004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Noah Moss Brender.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Moss Brender, N. Symmetry-breaking dynamics in development. Phenom Cogn Sci 16, 585–596 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9521-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-017-9521-3

Keywords

Navigation