Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Double trouble: Should double embryo transfer be banned?

  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

What role should legislation or policy play in avoiding the complications of in-vitro fertilization? In this article, we focus on single versus double embryo transfer, and assess three arguments in favour of mandatory single embryo transfer: risks to the mother, risks to resultant children, and costs to society. We highlight significant ethical concerns about each of these. Reproductive autonomy and non-paternalism are strong enough to outweigh the health concerns for the woman. Complications due to non-identity cast doubt on the extent to which children are harmed. Twinning may offer an overall benefit rather than burden to society. Finally, including the future health costs for children (not yet born) in reproductive policy is inconsistent with other decisions. We conclude that mandatory single embryo transfer is not justified and that a number of countries should reconsider their current embryo transfer policy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Other forms of ART (for example, controlled ovarian stimulation without IVF) are also associated with increased rates of multiple birth [6]. In this article, we focus on issues related to IVF, however, the central arguments potentially also apply to regulation of other forms of ART.

  2. The American Society for Reproductive Medicine has issued guidelines recommending restriction on the number of embryos transferred depending on the mother’s age [9], but those recommendations do not have the force of law.

  3. Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority (HFEA) regulations in the UK require clinics to set out policies that will reduce their multiple birth rate to 10 % [10]. This has led some clinics to adopt policies that effectively mandate SET for younger women [11].

  4. We frame our discussion in terms of restriction of liberty (rather than, say, protection of interests) because this is the direct policy question being debated: whether double embryo transfers should be legally limited. (As noted below, the default in the past has been to allow transfer of greater number of embryos). While this emphasizes the issue of autonomy at the outset, we do not mean to dismiss other issues relevant to policy such as prevention of harm. As we will argue, a central question is whether the harms (to woman, child or others) attributable to DET are sufficiently weighty that double embryo transfer should not be permitted.

  5. If DET should be banned (at least for some women), a fortiori, transfer of larger number of embryos should also be prohibited. However, if the arguments in favour of limiting DET do not succeed, there is a further question about multiple (>2) embryo transfer.

  6. For this reason, even countries with policies that limit DET may permit it in older women.

  7. Although, in the general population, twins have higher cerebral palsy rates, IVF twins may be less affected. Identical twins who share a placenta or amniotic sac have a substantially higher rate of complications (and neurological morbidity) [21]. However, twins arising from DET are dizygotic (non-identical) and consequently have fewer complications.

  8. One way of reducing complications from multiple pregnancies associated with IVF has been to employ multifetal pregnancy reduction, with selective termination performed to reduce pregnancies to singletons or twins. However, complication rates in reduced pregnancies remain higher than non-reduced pregnancies (of the same number) [22]. There are potential neurological complications in the remaining fetus/fetuses [23].

  9. A speculum will be inserted into the woman’s vagina, and a catheter passed through the cervix. The only difference between SET and DET is whether one or two 0.1 mm embryos are inserted into the uterus.

  10. We do not mean to suggest that this right is absolute. It is, rather, a pro tanto right—one that has significant strength, but can be overridden under certain circumstances. The next sections will discuss whether such circumstances obtain in the case of DET.

  11. There may be some cases of justified paternalistic restriction on inserting property into one’s body, as in the case of self-mutilation or severe self-harm (such as swallowing a sharp object one owns). But those exceptions arise only when the action involves highly likely and very substantial harm; the relative risks of multiple pregnancy, while non-negligible, hardly rise to that level.

  12. US courts have sometimes regarded stored embryos as having a status intermediate between property and persons. More recent decisions typically have granted couples disposition over their embryos equivalent to that given to transferrable property, subject to contract law [41].

  13. There is an interesting contrast between Sweden’s attitude to SET (mandatory except in exceptional circumstances) [7] and caesarean section on demand (discouraged but permitted) [45].

  14. The subscript notation A2 here indicates a child born as part of a twin gestation.

  15. A1 indicates a child born as part of a singleton pregnancy

  16. In some circumstances, the non-identity problem might mean that neither A2 nor B2 are harmed. If multiple embryo transfer were to lead to a sufficiently severe neurological disability in A2, it might be thought to be identity-changing, such that the disabled child A2 is different from the non-disabled singleton A1 who might have existed. As noted, the harms attributable to DET are not likely to be of this severity. One unique feature of the harm in DET is that, in almost all circumstances, neither twin will ever be in a position to complain about being harmed from being a twin—since they will never know whether they were embryo A (destined to exist in both cases) or embryo B. At best, they would know that they had a 50 % chance of having been harmed from being transferred as a twin.

  17. If further SET cycles were undertaken after a successful pregnancy, embryos other than B and C would be used to maintain non-identity.

  18. ITDET has not (to our knowledge) been performed in humans, and it is unknown whether it would be associated with harms to the children thus conceived. Such harms would need to be taken into account were ITDET to be explored as a way to address possible harms of DET. (Artificial twinning has been used successfully in several other species [51]).

  19. In the environmental damage case, future people live much worse lives than the (different) people who would have lived had the environment not been damaged. This seems impersonally bad.

  20. Such views are often taken to lead to a counter-intuitive or ‘repugnant’ conclusion that it is generally better to bring more and more people into existence, even if each additional person only has a life barely worth living. However, this population ethic need not be endorsed here: we can merely make the negative claim that such a benefit means one should not interfere with reproductive choices, without endorsing the positive claim that such a benefit implies it is better to maximize reproduction.

  21. As noted earlier, the additional physical, financial, and psychological burden of additional IVF treatment cycles leads at least some women to prefer DET over repeat SET.

  22. Using figures from Scotland et al. [27], in young women, cost per live-born child with DET is £22,341.70, compared with £24,647.60 (calculated from Scotland et al. Table 1—60 children per 100 cycles DET, 45 children per 100 cycles repeated SET1).

  23. There are differences between natural reproduction and artificial reproduction that make it easier for governments to limit artificial reproduction than the natural form. Further, limits to natural reproduction might be thought to threaten rights (for example, to privacy) that are not at stake, or less at stake, when discussing numbers of embryos transferred. However, as we argued earlier, women’s negative right against state interference in reproductive decision making includes whether to undergo DET. Infertile women are already at a disadvantage (struggling with infertility) and may be spending significant resources to alleviate it. Restricting their reproductive rights only serves to disadvantage them further. Furthermore, countries like Sweden and Turkey not only do not restrict natural reproduction, they have adopted a range of policies to positively promote childbirth [61, 62]. It would appear hypocritical to restrict access to DET on the basis of concerns about overpopulation, while at the same time to be positively promoting reproduction by other means. Finally, population growth attributable to artificial reproduction constitutes only a tiny proportion of global population increase. The world population has increased by approximately 3 billion since 1978, while, as noted, there have been 5 million births from IVF (approximately 0.17 % of global population growth). Restrictions on IVF are likely, therefore, to be highly inefficient means of curbing population growth.

  24. This estimate incorporates future earnings and tax. However, even if this is ignored and only health costs are assessed, given the approximate cost of $17,000 for one cycle of PGD, it would appear to be clearly cost effective to perform PGD or prenatal diagnosis over live birth.

  25. Most parents in this situation would be likely to choose pre-implantation genetic diagnosis. However, it is possible that some parents (for example, with a strong religious objection to disposal of viable embryos) would choose to avoid PGD.

  26. As noted, DET is potentially cheaper than SET in the long-run. However, if only health related costs are to be included, patients might be required to pay $3600 for a DET rather than a SET cycle. This is approximately half the full cost of an IVF treatment cycle in the UK [32].

  27. Only 1 % of three or four embryo transfer cycles performed in the UK between 2003-2007 resulted in live-birth of three babies. This compares with approximately 7 % of two-embryo transfer cycles resulting in twin-live-birth [18]. Correspondingly, the economic benefit from additional tax-paying members of society is likely to be small. In the same study, the adjusted odds ratio of live birth with DET compared with SET was 1.65 (confidence interval 1.54–1.77), while the odds ratio of live birth with three embryo transfer (compared with SET) was 1.62 [18].

References

  1. European Society of Human Reproduction and Embryology. 2012. 5 million babies. http://www.eshre.eu/sitecore/content/Home/PressRoom/Pressreleases/PressreleasesESHRE2012/5millionbabies. Accessed March 1, 2014.

  2. European Society of Human Reproduction and Embryology. 2013. ART fact sheet. http://www.eshre.eu/Guidelines-and-Legal/ART-fact-sheet.aspx. Accessed March 1, 2014.

  3. The Multiple Births Foundation. 2013. One at a time. http://www.oneatatime.org.uk/index.htm. Accessed March 1, 2014.

  4. Thurin, Ann, Jon Hausken, Torbjörn Hillensjö, Barbara Jablonowska, Anja Pinborg, Annika Strandell, and Christina Bergh. 2004. Elective single-embryo transfer versus double-embryo transfer in in vitro fertilization. New England Journal of Medicine 351(23): 2392–2402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Peeraer, K., S. Debrock, A. Laenen, P. De Loecker, C. Spiessens, D. de Neubourg, and T.M. D’Hooghe. 2014. The impact of legally restricted embryo transfer and reimbursement policy on cumulative delivery rate after treatment with assisted reproduction technology. Human Reproduction 29(2): 267–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Fauser, B.C., P. Devroey, and N.S. Macklon. 2005. Multiple birth resulting from ovarian stimulation for subfertility treatment. Lancet 365(9473): 1807–1816.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Maheshwari, Abha, Siriol Griffiths, and Siladitya Bhattacharya. 2011. Global variations in the uptake of single embryo transfer. Human Reproduction Update 17(1): 107–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Bissonnette, F., S.J. Phillips, J. Gunby, H. Holzer, N. Mahutte, P. St-Michel, and I.J. Kadoch. 2011. Working to eliminate multiple pregnancies: A success story in Québec. Reproductive Biomedicine Online 23(4): 500–504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. American Society for Reproductive Medicine. 2013. Criteria for number of embryos to transfer: A committee opinion. Fertility and Sterility 99(1): 44–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority. 2011. Improving outcomes for fertility patients: Multiple births. http://www.hfea.gov.uk/docs/2011-12-01_-_Multiple_Births_Publication_2011_-_Rationalising_Register_Data_-_FINAL_1.2.DOC.pdf. Accessed February 1, 2014.

  11. Midland Fertility Services. 2014. Embryo transfer policy. http://www.midlandfertility.com/investigations-and-treatments/treatments/embryo-transfer-policy/. Accessed July 16, 2014.

  12. Van Voorhis, Brad, Eric D. Levens, and Micah J. Hill. 2013. Should single-embryo transfer be mandatory in patients undergoing IVF? Contemporary Ob/Gyn, November 1. http://contemporaryobgyn.modernmedicine.com/contemporary-obgyn/news/should-single-embryo-transfer-be-mandatory-patients-undergoing-ivf?contextCategoryId=26. Accessed March 1, 2014.

  13. Janvier, A., B. Spelke, and K.J. Barrington. 2011. The epidemic of multiple gestations and neonatal intensive care unit use: The cost of irresponsibility. Journal of Pediatrics 159(3): 409–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Van Voorhis, Bradley J. 2007. In vitro fertilization. New England Journal of Medicine 356(4): 379–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority. 2009. IVF—chance of success. http://www.hfea.gov.uk/ivf-success-rate.html. Accessed March 1, 2014.

  16. McLernon, D.J., K. Harrild, C. Bergh, et al. 2010. Clinical effectiveness of elective single versus double embryo transfer: Meta-analysis of individual patient data from randomised trials. British Medical Journal 341: c6945.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Kjellberg, Ann Thurin, Per Carlsson, and Christina Bergh. 2006. Randomized single versus double embryo transfer: Obstetric and paediatric outcome and a cost-effectiveness analysis. Human Reproduction 21(1): 210–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Lawlor, Debbie A., and Scott M. Nelson. 2012. Effect of age on decisions about the numbers of embryos to transfer in assisted conception: A prospective study. Lancet 379(9815): 521–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Sullivan, Elizabeth A., Yueping A. Wang, Irene Hayward, Georgina M. Chambers, Peter Illingworth, John McBain, and Robert J. Norman. 2012. Single embryo transfer reduces the risk of perinatal mortality, a population study. Human Reproduction 27(12): 3609–3615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Pinborg, Anja, Anne Loft, Lone Schmidt, Gorm Greisen, Steen Rasmussen, and Anders Nyboe Andersen. 2004. Neurological sequelae in twins born after assisted conception: Controlled national cohort study. British Medical Journal 329(7461): 311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Adegbite, A.L., S. Castille, S. Ward, and R. Bajoria. 2004. Neuromorbidity in preterm twins in relation to chorionicity and discordant birth weight. American Journal of Obstetrics and Gynecology 190(1): 156–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Cheang, C.U., L.S. Huang, T.H. Lee, C.H. Liu, Y.T. Shih, and M.S. Lee. 2007. A comparison of the outcomes between twin and reduced twin pregnancies produced through assisted reproduction. Fertility and Sterility 88(1): 47–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Geva, E., L. Lerner-Geva, Z. Stavorovsky, et al. 1998. Multifetal pregnancy reduction: A possible risk factor for periventricular leukomalacia in premature newborns. Fertility and Sterility 69(5): 845–850.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Grady, Rosheen, Nika Alavi, Rachel Vale, Mohammad Khandwala, and Sarah D. McDonald. 2012. Elective single embryo transfer and perinatal outcomes: A systematic review and meta-analysis. Fertility and Sterility 97(2): 324–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Sazonova, Antonina, Karin Källén, Ann Thurin-Kjellberg, Ulla-Britt Wennerholm, and Christina Bergh. 2013. Neonatal and maternal outcomes comparing women undergoing two in vitro fertilization (IVF) singleton pregnancies and women undergoing one IVF twin pregnancy. Fertility and Sterility 99(3): 731–737.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Fiddelers, A.A.A., J.L. Severens, C.D. Dirksen, J.C.M. Dumoulin, J.A. Land, and J.L.H. Evers. 2007. Economic evaluations of single- versus double-embryo transfer in IVF. Human Reproduction Update 13(1): 5–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Scotland, G.S., D. McLernon, J.J. Kurinczuk, et al. 2011. Minimising twins in in vitro fertilisation: A modelling study assessing the costs, consequences and cost-utility of elective single versus double embryo transfer over a 20-year time horizon. BJOG: An International Journal of Obstetrics and Gynaecology 118(9): 1073–1083.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Mill, John Stuart. 2011. On liberty. Luton: Andrews UK Limited.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  29. Roberts, Stephen A., Linda McGowan, Andy Vail, and Daniel R. Brison. 2011. The use of single embryo transfer to reduce the incidence of twins: Implications and questions for practice from the ‘towardSET?’ project. Human Fertility 14(2): 89–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Leese, Brenda, and Jane Denton. 2010. Attitudes towards single embryo transfer, twin and higher order pregnancies in patients undergoing infertility treatment: A review. Human Fertility 13(1): 28–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Pinborg, Anja, Anne Loft, Lone Schmidt, and Anders Nyboe Andersen. 2003. Attitudes of IVF/ICSI-twin mothers towards twins and single embryo transfer. Human Reproduction 18(3): 621–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Chambers, Georgina M., Elizabeth A. Sullivan, Osamu Ishihara, Michael G. Chapman, and G. David Adamson. 2009. The economic impact of assisted reproductive technology: A review of selected developed countries. Fertility and Sterility 91(6): 2281–2294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Verberg, M.F., M.J. Eijkemans, E.M. Heijnen, F.J. Broekmans, C. de Klerk, B.C. Fauser, and N.S. Macklon. 2008. Why do couples drop-out from IVF treatment? A prospective cohort study. Human Reproduction 23(9): 2050–2055.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Thurin-Kjellberg, Ann, Catharina Olivius, and Christina Bergh. 2009. Cumulative live-birth rates in a trial of single-embryo or double-embryo transfer. New England Journal of Medicine 361(18): 1812–1813.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Dworkin, G. 1983. Comment on Narveson: In defense of equality. Social Philosophy and Policy 1: 28–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Paris, J.J. 2010. Autonomy does not confer sovereignty on the patient: A commentary on the Golubchuk case. American Journal of Bioethics 10(3): 54–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Paris, J.J., M.D. Schreiber, M. Statter, R. Arensman, and M. Siegler. 1993. Beyond autonomy—physicians’ refusal to use life-prolonging extracorporeal membrane oxygenation. New England Journal of Medicine 329(5): 354–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Berg, Jessica Wilen. 2005. Owning persons: The application of property theory to embryos and fetuses. Wake Forest Law Review 40: 4–16.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Goold, Imogen. 2014. Why does it matter how we regulate the use of human body parts? Journal of Medical Ethics 40(1): 3–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Wilkinson, Stephen. 2003. Bodies for sale: Ethics and exploitation in the human body trade. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Dickens, B.M., and R.J. Cook. 2010. The legal status of in vitro embryos. International Journal of Gynecology and Obstetrics 111(1): 91–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. Stillman, Robert J., Kevin S. Richter, and Howard W. Jones. 2013. Refuting a misguided campaign against the goal of single-embryo transfer and singleton birth in assisted reproduction. Human Reproduction 28(10): 2599–2607.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Ryan, Ginny L., Amy E.T. Sparks, Christopher S. Sipe, Craig H. Syrop, Anuja Dokras, and Bradley J. Van Voorhis. 2007. A mandatory single blastocyst transfer policy with educational campaign in a United States IVF program reduces multiple gestation rates without sacrificing pregnancy rates. Fertility and Sterility 88(2): 354–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Liu, Shiliang, Robert M. Liston, K.S. Joseph, Maureen Heaman, Reg Sauve, Michael S. Kramer, and Maternal Health Study Group of the Canadian Perinatal Surveillance System. 2007. Maternal mortality and severe morbidity associated with low-risk planned cesarean delivery versus planned vaginal delivery at term. Canadian Medical Association Journal 176(4): 455–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Wiklund, Ingela, Gunnar Edman, and Ellika Andolf. 2007. Cesarean section on maternal request: Reasons for the request, self-estimated health, expectations, experience of birth and signs of depression among first-time mothers. Acta Obstetricia et Gynecologica Scandinavica 86(4): 451–456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. Diekema, D.S. 2004. Parental refusals of medical treatment: The harm principle as threshold for state intervention. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 25(4): 243–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Risk of death and transportation. 2008. Bandolier. http://www.medicine.ox.ac.uk/bandolier/booth/Risk/trasnsportpop.html. Accessed May 1, 2014.

  48. Dawson, A. 2005. The determination of the best interests in relation to childhood immunisation. Bioethics 19(1): 72–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Stylianou, C., D. Critchlow, D.R. Brison, and S.A. Roberts. 2012. Embryo morphology as a predictor of IVF success: An evaluation of the proposed UK ACE grading scheme for cleavage stage embryos. Human Fertility: Journal of the British Fertility Society 15(1): 11–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Illmensee, Karl, Mike Levanduski, Andrea Vidali, Nabil Husami, and Vasilios T. Goudas. 2010. Human embryo twinning with applications in reproductive medicine. Fertility and Sterility 93(2): 423–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Savulescu, J. 2001. Procreative beneficence: Why we should select the best children. Bioethics 15(5–6): 413–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  53. Harris, J. 2000. Is there a coherent social conception of disability? Journal of Medical Ethics 26(2): 95–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Bennett, Rebecca. 2013. When intuition is not enough: Why the principle of procreative beneficence must work much harder to justify its eugenic vision. Bioethics 28(9): 447–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. McMahan, J. 2012. Causing people to exist and saving people’s lives. Journal of Ethics 17(1–2): 5–35.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Wilkinson, D. 2011. Should we replace disabled newborn infants? Journal of Moral Philosophy 8(3): 390–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  57. Savulescu, J. 2014. The nature of the moral obligation to select the best children. In The future of bioethics: International dialogues, ed. A. Akabyashi, 170–182. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  58. Bromer, Jason G., Baris Ata, Meltem Seli, Charles J. Lockwood, and Emre Seli. 2011. Preterm deliveries that result from multiple pregnancies associated with assisted reproductive technologies in the USA: A cost analysis. Current Opinion in Obstetrics & Gynecology 23(3): 168–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  59. Connolly, M., F. Gallo, S. Hoorens, and W. Ledger. 2009. Assessing long-run economic benefits attributed to an IVF-conceived singleton based on projected lifetime net tax contributions in the UK. Human Reproduction 24(3): 626–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  60. Connolly, M.P., M.S. Pollard, S. Hoorens, B.R. Kaplan, S.P. Oskowitz, and S.J. Silber. 2008. Long-term economic benefits attributed to IVF-conceived children: A lifetime tax calculation. American Journal of Managed Care 14(9): 598–604.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Gauthier, A.H. 2007. The impact of family policies on fertility in industrialized countries: A review of the literature. Population Research and Policy Review 26(3): 323–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  62. Turkey’s new population policy. 2013. Turkish review, June 1. http://www.turkishreview.org/microscope/turkey-s-new-population-policy_540666. Accessed March 17, 2015.

  63. Davis, Lynn B., Sara J. Champion, Steve O. Fair, Valerie L. Baker, and Alan M. Garber. 2010. A cost-benefit analysis of preimplantation genetic diagnosis for carrier couples of cystic fibrosis. Fertility and Sterility 93(6): 1793–1804.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  64. Avraham, S., and D.S. Seidman. 2012. The multiple birth epidemic: Revisited. Journal of Obstetrics and Gynaecology of India 62(4): 386–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  65. Stillman, Robert J., Kevin S. Richter, Nicole K. Banks, and James R. Graham. 2009. Elective single embryo transfer: A 6-year progressive implementation of 784 single blastocyst transfers and the influence of payment method on patient choice. Fertility and Sterility 92(6): 1895–1906.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  66. Chambers, Georgina M., Peter J. Illingworth, and Elizabeth A. Sullivan. 2011. Assisted reproductive technology: Public funding and the voluntary shift to single embryo transfer in Australia. Medical Journal of Australia 195(10): 594–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  67. Jain, Tarun, Bernard L. Harlow, and Mark D. Hornstein. 2002. Insurance coverage and outcomes of in vitro fertilization. New England Journal of Medicine 347(9): 661–666.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  68. Manninen, B.A. 2011. Parental, medical, and sociological responsibilities: “Octomom” as a case study in the ethics of fertility treatments. Journal of Clinical Research and Bioethics 1: 2.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Luke, B., M.B. Brown, J.E. Stern, D.A. Grainger, N. Klein, and M. Cedars. 2010. Effect of embryo transfer number on singleton and twin implantation pregnancy outcomes after assisted reproductive technology. Journal of Reproductive Medicine 55(9–10): 387–394.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Savulescu, J. 1995. Rational non-interventional paternalism: Why doctors ought to make judgments of what is best for their patients. Journal of Medical Ethics 21(6): 327–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  71. Savulescu, Julian. 1997. Liberal rationalism and medical decision-making. Bioethics 11(2): 115–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dominic Wilkinson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Wilkinson, D., Schaefer, G.O., Tremellen, K. et al. Double trouble: Should double embryo transfer be banned?. Theor Med Bioeth 36, 121–139 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-015-9324-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-015-9324-x

Keywords

Navigation