Skip to main content
Log in

Phenomenological method and contemporary ethics

  • Published:
Continental Philosophy Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Following a brief summation of the phenomenological method, the paper considers three metaethical positions adopted by phenomenologists and the implications of those positions for a normative ethics. The metaethical positions combine epistemological and ontological viewpoints. They are (1) non-intellectualism and strong value realism as represented by the axiological views of phenomenologists such as Scheler, Meinong, Reinach, Stein, Hartmann, von Hildebrand, and Steinbock; (2) non-intellectualism and anti-realism as represented by the freedom-centered phenomenologies of Sartre, Beauvoir, and Merleau-Ponty; and (3) weak intellectualism and weak value realism as represented by Husserl and Drummond. The paper argues that only the third metaethical view can support a normative ethics (1) that is consistent with the essential features of the phenomenological method, (2) that allows for freedom in an agent’s choosing from a multiplicity of first-order goods, including vocational goods, practical identities, and life plans, available in the agent’s factical circumstances, and (3) that provides norms governing the correctness of our actions and our obligations to others. The normative dimension is introduced, first, by the requirement that the fulfillment of first-order evaluations and choices be truthful, that is, that the (emotive) evaluations be appropriate and the actions right. Second, transcendental considerations revealed in the phenomenological analysis of intentional experience disclose a notion of second-order goods of agency that universally bind agents in their exercise of freedom and their dealings with others.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For brief summaries of the development of ethics within the phenomenological tradition see Drummond (2020a) and Loidolt (2018).

  2. Drummond (2008).

  3. Husserl (2014, p. 58).

  4. This claim needs qualification, for some phenomenologists believe—wrongly, in my view—that there are experiences that are non-intentional. Husserl (1970b, p. 572), for example, distinguishes non-intentional feelings from what he calls (intentional) feeling-acts (e.g., taking pleasure in a melody, joy concerning some event) (1970b, pp. 569–70). Non-intentional feelings, such as pains, are feeling-sensations (Gefühlsempfindungen) or sensory states—a form of bodily self-awareness—rather than feeling-acts directed toward objects. I have suggested elsewhere (2020c) that intentional feelings are a Gestalt whose moments are the varied and distinct feeling-sensations that, taken together, constitute a bodily attitude toward an object. Non-intentional feelings can, for present purposes, be put aside. They do not in and of themselves possess moral content. They can be implicated in moral experiences, especially moral emotions, but in those contexts they are implicated in intentional feeling-acts, such as compassion, callousness, admiration, or contempt.

  5. McDowell (1998a, pp. 207–212; 1998b, pp. 63–64).

  6. Husserl (2014, p. 75).

  7. Drummond (2007, p. 58).

  8. Examples include Nicolai Hartmann (1963), Edmund Husserl (1988; 2004), Alexius Meinong (2020), Adolf Reinach (1989), Max Scheler (1973), Edith Stein (1986; 1989), and Dietrich von Hildebrand (1916; 1922; 1953). Martin Heidegger is the notable exception.

  9. Strong realism regarding values is more often associated with strongly cognitivist or intellectualist positions regarding the apprehension of value. These positions view the emotions, in Martha Nussbaum’s words, as “identical with the acceptance of a proposition that is both evaluative and eudaimonistic, that is, concerned with one or more of the person’s important goals and ends” (2001, p. 41). See also Solomon (1980) and Neu (2000). These early phenomenologists, in opposition both to Kantian rationalism and the empiricistic feeling-theories of William James (1884) and Carl Lange (1887), stressed the capacity of intentional feelings to grasp objective values; see also Goldie (2000).

  10. For a contemporary view of this sort, see Findlay (1961, 1970). Anthony Steinbock frequently invokes Scheler in his work on the emotions, although his analyses of particular emotions often appeal to beliefs that appear to be constituent parts of the emotion; see, e.g., Steinbock (2013, 2014).

  11. Scheler (1973, p. 68). See also Mulligan (1998, p. 161).

  12. Scheler (1973, p. 18).

  13. Scheler (1973, p. 17). For a criticism of Scheler’s axiology, see Drummond (2013; 2020c).

  14. Scheler (1973, pp. 203ff.).

  15. Von Hildebrand (1953, p. 24).

  16. Von Hildebrand (2016, p. 14).

  17. Von Hildebrand (2016, p. 16). See also von Hildebrand (1953, pp. 34–43, 53–59).

  18. Von Hildebrand (1953, p. 42).

  19. Hartmann (1963, p. 357).

  20. Hartmann (1963, pp. 358–360).

  21. See Drummond (2018).

  22. See Drummond (2020b).

  23. Mulligan (2009, pp. 154).

  24. Heidegger is a difficult case. In the first place, he criticizes the notion of value in general, and, in the second place, it is disputed whether he commits himself to a “decisionism” (see, e.g., Tugendhat (1986) and Okrent (1999)) or a “deep deliberation” (see Burch (2010, p. 212) and Crowell (2007, pp. 55–56, 59–62; 2013, pp. 206–213)). We need note only that he develops neither an explicit theory of value beyond his discussions of Befindlichkeit nor of ethics beyond his discussions of conscience (Gewissen) and resoluteness (Entschlossenheit). While the controversy makes clear that Heidegger is no decisionist in any simple sense, it is not clear to me that it has demonstrated that Heidegger is not a more nuanced and sophisticated decisionist, and my view is that he ultimately is just such a decisionist.

  25. See Sartre (1992), Beauvoir (1948), and Merleau-Ponty (2012).

  26. Beauvoir (1948, p. 153).

  27. Merleau-Ponty (2012, pp. 464–473, 480–481).

  28. Sartre (2007, p. 24).

  29. The exception here is Simone de Beauvoir. An aspect of the non-intellectualist anti-realism rooted in freedom is to show that freedom is “concretely contextualized in terms of political struggles and historical reality”; see Crowell (2017, §3.2). Moving beyond Sartre’s position, Beauvoir claims that the freedom of others is not merely an obstacle to the exercise of my own freedom. Rather, the realization of my freely chosen projects requires that others, not impeding my freedom, exercise their own freedom in ways that cooperate and support my projects. Moreover, in Beauvoir’s view, evil is the denial of freedom. Consequently, we are obligated to protect the freedom of all agents and to guarantee the conditions of freedom for all agents, myself and others, and, in particular, to recognize and oppose oppressive forces within the situation. These two aspects of her thought establish the space in which a normative ethical theory can be developed.

  30. Crowell (2012, p. 216).

  31. Sartre (1992, pp. 76–78).

  32. Cf. Darwall (2006).

  33. Levinas (1969, p. 66).

  34. Levinas (1969, p. 215).

  35. Levinas (1969, pp. 43, 50–51).

  36. See Husserl (1989, p. 12). The term Wertnehmung is a modification of Wahrnehmung and invites an analogy with perception. Just as to perceive (wahrnehmen) is to take as true, to perceive a value (wertnehmen) is to take as valuable.

  37. Husserl (1988, p. 255).

  38. This formulation modifies Husserl’s position in the fifth investigation in Logical Investigations, §15. Husserl claimed that an intentional feeling-act was founded on what he called an objectifying act (a perception or judgment). I claim that the founding moment is not the perceiving or judging act, but the perceptual or propositional sense of the presentation of the non-axiological properties. This sense, in relation to the subject’s circumstances detailed above, motivates the intentional feeling and, when the feeling is appropriate, justifies the axiological sense presenting the object as valued; cf. Drummond (2002; 2013; 2017). Husserl later (2014, §117) changed his view and recognized that intentional feelings and emotions are objectifying, although he did not abandon his view of the founding relation. Husserl viewed emotions, in effect, as an addition to perception, whereas I am claiming that perception is an abstractive modification of a complex original experience having cognitive, affective, and practical dimensions and senses.

  39. Husserl (2014, pp. 190–91).

  40. This view is similar, but not identical, to John McDowell’s claim that value-attributes are analogous to perceived secondary qualities. McDowell (1998b, p. 143) says, “To press the analogy is to stress that evaluative ‘attitudes,’ or states of will, are like (say) colour experience in being unintelligible except as modifications of a sensibility like ours. The idea of value experience involves taking admiration, say, to represent its object as having a property that (although there in the object) is essentially subjective in much the same way as the property that an object is represented as having by an experience of redness—that is, understood adequately only in terms of the appropriate modification of human (or similar) sensibility. The disanalogy, now, is that a virtue (say) is conceived to be not merely such as to elicit the appropriate ‘attitude’ (as a colour is merely such as to cause the appropriate experiences), but rather such as to merit it.” The point of the analogy is to stress that the relation to the subject does not entail that the secondary qualities or values do not inhere as objective properties, and the point of the disanalogy is that causality is not the category in which to describe the relation between the valuable thing and the value-experience.

  41. See, e.g., (Husserl, 1970a, pp. 57–58).

  42. For a discussion of the appropriateness of feelings and emotions as well as the valuations accomplished therein, see Drummond, (2017), and for a discussion of the justification of action, see Drummond (2010).

  43. Husserl (1989, pp. 281–282).

  44. Drummond (2010, p. 420).

  45. See Drummond (2010, pp. 423–424). This move to intersubjectivity and the moral order has a similar structure to what we have seen in Beauvoir; cf. supra, n. 29.

  46. Cf. Drummond (2010).

  47. For more details, see Drummond (2006, 2010, 2013, 2017, 2018, 2020b, 2020c).

References

  • Burch, Matthew. 2010. "Death and Deliberation: Overcoming the Decisionism Critique of Heidegger’s Practical Philosophy." Inquiry 53(3): 211–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crowell, Steven. 2007. "Conscience and Reason: Heidegger and the Grounds of Intentionality." In Transcendental Heidegger, ed. S. Crowell and J. Malpas, 43–62. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowell, Steven. 2012. "Sartre’s Existentialism and the Nature of Consciousness." In The Cambridge Companion to Existentialism, ed. S. Crowell, 199–226. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Crowell, Steven. 2013. Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crowell, Steven. 2017. “Existentialism.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E. N. Zalta, winter 2017. Available at: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/existentialism/ (Accessed: 28 June 2019).

  • Darwall, Stephen. 2006. The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, John J. 2002. “Complicar Las Emociones.” Translated by M. Oyata. Areté. Revista de Filosofía 14(2): 175–189.

  • Drummond, John J. 2006. "Respect as a Moral Emotion: A Phenomenological Approach." Husserl Studies 22(1): 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, John J. 2007. "Phenomenology: Neither Auto- nor Hetero- Be." Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 6(1–2): 57–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, John J. 2008. "The Transcendental and the Psychological." Husserl Studies 24(3): 193–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, John J. 2010. "Self-Responsibility and Eudaimonia." In Philosophy Phenomenology Sciences, ed. C. Ierna, H. Jacobs, and F. Mattens, 441–460. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, John J. 2013. “The Intentional Structure of Emotions.” Logical Analysis and the History of Philosophy/Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse 16: 244–263.

  • Drummond, John J. 2017. "Having the Right Attitudes." New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 15: 142–163.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, John J. 2018. "Emotions, Value, and Action." New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 16: 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, John J. 2020a. "Ethics." In The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology, ed. D. DeSantis, C. Majolino, and B. Hopkins, 187–197. London and New York: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, John J. 2020b. "Acting, Choosing, Deliberating." In The Routledge Handbook of the Phenomenology of Agency, ed. C. Erhard and T. Keiling, 374–385. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, John J. 2020c. "The Varieties of Affective Experience." In The Routledge Handbook of the Phenomenology of the Emotions, ed. T. Szanto and H. Landweer, 239–249. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Findlay, J.N. 1961. Values and Intentions. London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Findlay, J.N. 1970. Axiological Ethics. London: Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldie, Peter. 2000. The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, Nicolai. 1963. Ethics. Translated by S. Coit. New York: Humanities Press.

  • Von Hildebrand, Dietrich. 1916. “Die Idee der sittlichen Handlung.” Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 3: 126–151.

  • Von Hildebrand, Dietrich. 1922. “Sittlichkeit und ethische Werterkenntnis.” Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 5: 463–602.

  • Von Hildebrand, Dietrich. 1953. Ethics. Chicago: Franciscan Press.

  • Von Hildebrand, Dietrich. 2016. Aesthetics: Volume I. Steubenville, OH: Hildebrand Project.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1970. Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology. Translated by D. Cairns. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1970. Logical investigations. Translated by J. N. Findlay. 2 vols, New York: Humanities Press.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1976. Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Erstes Buch, Allgemeine Einführung in die reine Phänomenologie. Edited by K. Schuhmann. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1988. Vorlesungen über Ethik und Wertlehre, 1908–1914. Edited by U. Melle. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1989. Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy. Second Book: Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution. Translated by R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 2004. Einleitung in die Ethik: Vorlesungen Sommersemester 1920/1924. Edited by H. Peucker. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 2014. Ideas for a Pure Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy. First Book: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. Translated by D. O. Dahlstrom. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.

  • James, William. 1884. "What is an Emotion?" Mind 9: 188–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, Carl. 1887. Ueber Gemüthsbewegungen. Eine psycho-physiologische Studie. Leipzig: T. Thomas.

  • Levinas, Emmanuel. 1969. Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority. Translated by A. Lingis. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.

  • Loidolt, Sophie. 2018. “Value, Freedom, Responsibility: Central Themes in Phenomenological Ethics”. In The Oxford Handbook for The History of Phenomenology, ed. D. Zahavi, 696–716. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John. 1998b. "Values and Secondary Qualities." In Mind, Value, and Reality, 131–150. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John. 1998c. "Virtue and Reason." In Mind, Value, and Reality, 50–73. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John. 1998a. “Non-Cogitivism and Rule-Following.” In Mind, Value, and Reality, pp. 198–218. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Meinong, Alexius. 2020. On Emotional Presentation. Translated by M. L. S. Kalsi. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 2012. Phenomenology of Perception. Translated by D. A. Landes. London and New York: Routledge.

  • Mulligan, Kevin. 1998. "From Appropriate Emotions to Values." The Monist 81(1): 161–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan, Kevin. 2009. “On Being Struck by Value—Exclamations, Motivations, and Vocations.” In Leben mit Gefühlen. Emotionen, Werte und ihre Kritik, ed. B. Merkel, pp. 141–161. Paderborn: mentis-Verlag.

  • Neu, Jerome. 2000. A Tear is an Intellectual Thing: The Meanings of Emotion. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okrent, Mark. 1999. "Heidegger and Korsgaard on Human Reflection." Philosophical Topics 27: 47–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reinach, Adolf. 1989. “Die Überlegung: ihre ethische und rechtliche Bedeutung.” In Sämtliche Werke: Textkritische Ausgabe, ed. K. Schuhmann and B. Smith. Munich: Philosophia Verlag.

  • Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1992. Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology. Translated by H. Barnes. New York: Washington Square Press.

  • Sartre, Jean-Paul. 2007. Existentialism Is a Humanism. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, Max. 1973. Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values: A New Attempt Toward the Foundation of an Ethical Personalism. Translated by M. S. Frings and R. L. Funk. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

  • Solomon, Robert C. 1980. "Emotions and Choice." In Explaining Emotions, ed. A. Rorty, 251–281. Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, Edith. 1986. Essays on Woman. Washington, DC: ICS Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, Edith. 1989. On the Problem of Empathy. 3rd rev. ed. Translated by W. Stein. Washington, DC: ICS Publications.

  • Steinbock, Anthony J. 2013. "The Distinctive Structure of the Emotions. In Husserl’s Ideen, ed. L. Embree and T. Nenon, 91–104. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Steinbock, Anthony J. 2014. Moral Emotions: Reclaiming the Evidence of the Heart. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tugendhat, Ernst. 1986. Self-Consciousness and Self-Determination. Translated by P. Stern. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beauvoir, Simone de. 1948. The Ethics of Ambiguity. Translated by B. Frechtman. New York: Philosophical Library.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John J. Drummond.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Drummond, J.J. Phenomenological method and contemporary ethics. Cont Philos Rev 54, 123–138 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-021-09529-w

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-021-09529-w

Keywords

Navigation