Skip to main content
Log in

Pragmatic Interpretations of Vague Expressions: Strongest Meaning and Nonmonotonic Consequence

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent experiments have shown that naive speakers find borderline contradictions involving vague predicates acceptable. In Cobreros et al. (Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41, 347–385, 2012a) we proposed a pragmatic explanation of the acceptability of borderline contradictions, building on a three-valued semantics. In a reply, Alxatib et al. (Journal of Philosophical Logic, 42, 619–634, 2013) show, however, that the pragmatic account predicts the wrong interpretations for some examples involving disjunction, and propose as a remedy a semantic analysis instead, based on fuzzy logic. In this paper we provide an explicit global pragmatic interpretation rule, based on a somewhat richer semantics, and show that with its help the problem can be overcome in pragmatics after all. Furthermore, we use this pragmatic interpretation rule to define a new (nonmonotonic) consequence-relation and discuss some of its properties.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. According to the strongest meaning hypothesis, if a sentence can give rise to several closely related meanings, the sentence should be interpreted in the strongest possible way. A similar principle was used by [1] as well.

  2. Notice that the semantics for the connectives coincides with those of [19, 22, 23]. As in TCS, we here give a substitutional semantics for simplicity, but nothing hangs on that.

  3. This account of the conditional problem is new, and not discussed in TCS.

  4. The notion of ‘model’ that we use here is not exactly the standard model-theoretic notion, where interpretation of non-logical constants varies between models. In contrast, the notion of ‘model’ we use in section 4 to define various notions of entailment will be the standard model-theoretic one. We hope this will never give rise to confusion.

  5. Interestingly enough, this is exactly what Priest’s LP m predicts for this type of example as well (see [5]). We will come back to this later.

  6. Van Fraassen uses these truth-makers to give a semantics for the notion of ‘tautological entailment’ introduced by [3], a notion of entailment that is weaker than both Kleene’s K3 and Priest’s LP. For recent work on truth-makers, see [13]. For use of the same framework for quite a different purpose, see [28].

  7. Note that the definition of T(ϕ) parallels the construction of the disjunctive normal form of ϕ.

  8. To give a semantics of tautological entailments, [14] looks at models that neither have to be maximal, nor consistent.

  9. Our pragmatic interpretation rule does not account for the ‘scalar implicature’ that from ‘ (p ∧ ¬ p) ∨ q’ we conclude that only one of the disjuncts is as true as possible. It is easy to change the pragmatic interperation rule to account for this—and for embedded implicatures—as well (by changing ‘ ∃ST(ϕ)’ in the definition \(PRAG(\phi ,c) = \{\mathcal {M} |\ \exists S \in T(\phi ): \mathcal {M} \in [\![S]\!]^{t}_{c} \ \& \ \neg \exists \mathcal {N} \in [\![S]\!]^{t}_{c} : \mathcal {M}<_{S} \mathcal {N}\}\) which is equivalent to the one used in the main text, into ‘ ∃!ST(ϕ)’), but a discussion of this would go beyond the purpose of this paper.

  10. Also APS treat conditionals in terms of material implication. Our assumption that we just use 3 truth-values instead of all the ones in [0,1] has as a consequence that the following sentences \(p \curlywedge \neg p\), \((p \curlywedge \neg p) \curlywedge p\) and \((p \curlywedge \neg p) \curlywedge \neg (p \curlywedge \neg p)\) will all have value 1 exactly if p has value \(\frac {1}{2}\). In APS, instead, it is predicted that these different sentences have value 1 in different circumstances. For instance, \((p \curlywedge \neg p) \curlywedge p\) is predicted to have value 1 iff p has value \(\frac {2}{3}\). Notice that on our analysis the three sentences are predicted to be equivalent because they are predicted to have the same exact truth-maker: {p, ¬ p}.

  11. As it turns out, this rescaling method is virtually identical to the recalibration-method proposed by [18] to account for adjective-noun combinations.

  12. In fact, in case the language does not have special connectives, this consequence relation is S3, the intersection of K3 and LP.

  13. See [6, 7] for empirical arguments. For a rebuttal of some of these claims, see, among others, [15, 27, 3032].

  14. For what it is worth, we can make sense of our predictions for (9) as well as for (10), even though the predictions APS makes for (10) might seem more appropriate. Consider the reading of (10) made salient by the elaboration: ‘Adam is (surely) tall, and either he is (also) not tall or else John is rich (but I forget which)’. It seems to us that our prediction for this elaboration is correct, and that APS mispredicts here. Still, even if our prediction turns out to be incorrect, this still wouldn’t automatically mean that a semantic analysis would be preferred to a pragmatic one. It is possible to change the pragmatic interpretation rule so as to predict the same interpretation for (10) as APS does. For instance, by assuming that the definition of T(ϕψ) should be as given in the main text only if T(ϕ) and T(ψ) are singletons. In any other case we should only allow AB to be an element of T(ϕψ) for AT(ϕ) and BT(ψ), if AB does not contain a p! that was not yet in either A or B, where p! = {p, ¬ p}:

    $$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}}T(\phi \wedge \psi) &=& \{A \cup B: A \in T(\phi), B \in T(\psi)\}, \text{if}\,\, T(\phi)\,\, \text{and}\,\, T(\psi)\,\, \text{are singletons}, \\ & =& \{A \cup B: A \in T(\phi), B \in T(\psi), \neg \exists p: p! \subseteq A \cup B \ \& \ p! \not\subseteq A\ \& \ p! \not\subseteq B\}, \text{otherwise}. \end{array} $$

    At this point, however, we are undecided on whether we should change the definition of T(ϕψ), because we feel that an assertion of a sentence like (10) would be inappropriate because it violates Grice’s maxim of Manner. Notice, though, that in case we would interpret not (10), but rather a sentence like ¬ TaRj in a context where Ta is known to be strictly true, we would already make the same prediction as APS. As it turns out, however, the alternative definition could be relevant for the analysis of pragmatic entailment discussed in the following section.

  15. because we demand that x P y is true provided Px and Py have truth values not differing by more than \(\frac {1}{2}\).

  16. Notice that the simple definition \({\Gamma } \models ^{spr}_{\sim } \phi \) iff S(Γ) ⊆ PRAG(ϕ, S(Γ)) wouldn’t work (with S(Γ) as the class of models where all the elements of Γ are strictly true) because there will be models where Txx T y is stricly true, but where Ty is only tolerantly true.

  17. Notice that if we had defined pragmatic consequence as follows: \( {\Gamma } \models \!^{prt}_{c}\ \psi \mbox { iff } PRAG(\bigwedge _{\phi \in {\Gamma }},c) \subseteq \{\mathcal {M}\in c: \mathcal {M}\in [\![\psi ]\!]^{t}\}\), things would have been different. In that case we could only conclude from p, ¬ pq that either p is only tolerantly true, or that q is strictly true. This has an important consequence, though: it can be that ϕ, ψprt χ although ϕψprt χ, for p, ¬ pqprt q but p ∧ (¬ pq) ⊮prt q. This problem could be solved, however, by adopting the alternative definition of T(ϕψ) as given in footnote 14.

  18. One might think that an interesting difference with LP shows up here: can we not ensure the validity of the disjunctive syllogism ϕ, ¬ ϕψprt ψ by adding ¬ (ϕ ∧ ¬ ϕ) as an extra premise, even though LP cannot (because ¬ (ϕ ∧ ¬ ϕ) is an LP-tautology)? Unfortunately, adding ¬ (ϕ ∧ ¬ ϕ) as an extra premise cannot guarantee the validity of the disjunctive syllogism for ⊧prt either, as can be seen by taking ϕ to be p ∧ ¬ p.

  19. The other direction doesn’t hold, though. Assume ⊧prt ϕψ. Now it doesn’t follow that ϕprt ψ. For take ϕ: = p ∧ ¬ p and ψ:=q.

  20. Some (e.g. [25]) have also questioned conjunction elimination.

  21. Note though, that ϕ, ¬ ϕprt ψ.

  22. In fact, our consequence relation verifies (slight variants of) all the standard conditions of nonmonotonic reasoning (as stated by [20]): (i) Reflexivity: ϕprt ϕ, (ii) Left Equivalence: if PRAG(ϕ) = PRAG(ψ), then from ϕprt χ, it follows that ψprt χ (Notice that the condition PRAG(ϕ) = PRAG(ψ) cannot be replaced by ⊧prt ϕψ.) (iii) Right Weakening: if ⟦ψt ⊆ ⟦χt, then ϕprt χ follows from ϕprt ψ, (Of course not if ⟦ψt ⊆ ⟦χt were replaced by ψprt χ or by ⊧prt ψχ.), (iv) Cautious Monotonicity: if ϕprt χ and ϕprt ψ, then it follows that ϕψprt χ, and (v) Or: if ϕprt χ and ψprt χ, then ϕψprt χ. Obviously, (vi) Cautious Cut (if ϕψprt χ and ϕprt ψ, then ϕprt χ) does not hold, at least in case of \(\models ^{prt}_{\sim }\): a \(\models ^{prt}_{\sim }\)-conclusion indeed may have a lower truth-value than that of the premises it is based on. Notice that in these rules we have always interpreted the premises as one conjunction. For the reason behind that, see footnote 17.

  23. Beall [5] notes that \((q \wedge \neg q) \models ^{LP^{m}} (q \wedge \neg q) \vee r\) and \((q \wedge \neg q) \vee r\models ^{LP^{m}} r\), but \((q \wedge \neg q)\not \models ^{LP^{m}} r\).

  24. In fact, we think that ⊧prt is strictly weaker than \(\models ^{LP^{m}}\), but leave a discussion of this to another occasion.

  25. Van Rooij [29] uses this notion in relation to the well-known knowability-paradox.

References

  1. Alxatib, S., & Pelletier, F.R. (2011). The psychology of vagueness: borderline cases and contradictions. Mind and Language, 26, 287–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Alxatib, S., P. Pagin, U. Sauerland (2013). Acceptable contradictions: pragmatics or semantics? A reply to Cobreros et al. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 42, 619–634.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Anderson, A.R., & N.D. Belnap (1962). Tautological entailments. Philosophical Studies, 13(1–2), 9–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Batens, D. (2000). A survey of inconsistency-adaptive logics. D. Batens et al (eds.), Frontiers of Paraconsistent Logic (pp. 49–73). Baldock: Research Studies Press.

  5. Beall, Jc. (2013). Why Priest’s reassurance is not reassuring. Analysis. 72(3), 517–525.

  6. Chierchia, G. (2004). Scalar implicatures, polarity phenomena and the syntax/pragmatics interface. Structures and Beyond (pp. 39–103). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  7. Chierchia, G., Fox, D., Spector, B. (2012). The grammatical view of scalar implicatures and the relationship between semantics and pragmatics. In P. Portner, C. Maienborn, K. von Heusinger (Eds.), Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

  8. Cobreros, P., Egré, P., Ripley, D., van Rooij, R. (2012a). Tolerant, classical, strict. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41, 347–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Cobreros, P., Egre, P., Ripley, D., van Rooij, R. (2012b). Tolerance and mixed consequence in a S’valuationist setting. Studia logica, 100, 853–876.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Cobreros, P., P. Egré, D. Ripley, R. van Rooij. (2013). Vagueness, truth and permissive consequence. In Achourioti et al. (Eds), Unifying the philosophy of truth. Springer.

  11. Egré, P., V. de Cardelle, D. Ripley (2013). Vagueness and order effects in color categorization. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 265–300.

  12. Fine, K. (1975). Vagueness, truth, and logic. Synthese, 30, 265300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Fine, K. (2014). Truth-Maker semantics for intuitionistic logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 43, 549–577.

  14. van Fraassen, B. (1969). Facts and tautological entailments. Journal of Philosophy, 66, 477–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Franke, M. (2011). Quantity implicatures, exhaustive interpretation, and rational conversation. In Semantics and Pragmatics (vol. 4, pp. 1–82).

  16. Grice, H.P. (1967). Logic and conversation. In William James Lectures, Harvard University, reprinted in Studies in the Way of Words, 1989. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  17. Kamp, H. (1975). Two theories of adjectives. In E. Keenan (ed.), Formal Semantics of Natural Language (pp. 123–155). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  18. Kamp, H., & Partee, B. (1995). Prototype theory and compositionality. Cognition, 57, 129–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Kleene, S.C. (1952). In Introduction to Metamathematics. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Kraus, S., Lehman, D., Magidor, M. (1990). Nonmonotonic reasoning, preferential models and cumulative logics. Artificial Intelligence, 4, 167–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Lewis, C.I. (1918). In A Survey of Symbolic Logic. Calif: Berkeley.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Łukasiewicz, J (1920). O logice trójwartościowej. Ruch Filozoficzny, 5, 170–171.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Priest, G. (1979). The logic of paradox. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8, 219–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Priest, G. (1991). Minimally inconsistent LP. Studia Logica, 50, 321–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Read, S (1988). Relevant Logic. Basil Blackwell.

  26. Ripley, D. (2011). Contradictions at the borders. In R. Nouwen, R. van Rooij, H.-C. Schmitz, U. Sauerland (Eds.), (2012), Vagueness in communication. LICS: Springer.

  27. van Rooij, R., & K. Schulz (2004). Exhaustive interpretation of complex sentences. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 13, 491–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. van Rooij, R. (2014). Leibnizian intensional semantics for syllogistic reasoning. In R. Ciuni et al (Eds.), Recent Trends in Philosophical Logic Trends in Logic (vol. 41, pp. 179–194). Heidelberg: Springer.

  29. van Rooij, R. Nonmonotonicity and Knowability: As Knowable as Possible. C. Baskent, L. Moss, R. Ramanujum (Eds.), Festschrifft in honor of Rohit Parikh. Verlag: Springer (to appear).

  30. Sauerland, U. (2004). Scalar implicatures in complex sentences. Linguistics and Philosophy, 27, 363–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Schulz, K., & R. van Rooij (2006). Pragmatic meaning and non-monotonic reasoning: the case of exhaustive interpretation. Linguistics and Philosophy, 29, 205–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Spector, B. (2007). Scalar implicatures: exhaustivity & Gricean reasoning. In M. Aloni, & P. Dekker (Eds.), Questions in Dynamic Semantics Current Issues in the Semantics/Pragmatics Interface 17. Elsevier.

  33. Serchuk, P., Hargreaves, I., Zach, R (2011). Vagueness, logic and use: Four experimental studies on vagueness. Mind and Language, 26, 540–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Williamson, T. (1994). Vagueness. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We wish to thank the reviewers for their helpful comments. Thanks also to audiences and colleagues at the universities of Amsterdam, Tilburg, NYU, and Barcelona where part of this material was presented, for helpful feedback. Financial support for this work was provided by the Marie Curie Initial Training Network ESSENCE-project, the NWO-sponsored ‘Language in Interaction’-project, and the project ‘Logicas no-transitivas. Una nueva aproximacion a las paradojas’, funded by the Ministerio de Economa y Competitividad, Government of Spain. Thanks also to grants ANR-10-LABX-0087 IEC and ANR-10-IDEX-0001-02 PSL, as well as to the the European Research Council (FP7/2007-2013) under ERC Advanced Grant agreement number 229 441-CCC (PI: Recanati).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert van Rooij.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Cobreros, P., Egré, P., Ripley, D. et al. Pragmatic Interpretations of Vague Expressions: Strongest Meaning and Nonmonotonic Consequence. J Philos Logic 44, 375–393 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-014-9325-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-014-9325-7

Keywords

Navigation