Skip to main content
Log in

Bare conditionals in the red

  • Published:
Linguistics and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Bare conditionals, I argue, exhibit Conditional Duality in that when they appear in downward entailing environments they differ from bare conditionals elsewhere in having existential rather than universal force. Two recalcitrant phenomena are shown to find a new explanation under this thesis: bare conditionals under only, and bare conditionals in the scope of negative nominal quantifiers, or what has come to be known as Higginbotham’s puzzle. I also consider how bare conditionals behave when embedded under negation, arguing that such conditionals often involve denial negation. One important conclusion that emerges from the discussion is that an account of bare conditionals that validates Conditional Excluded Middle is not warranted. By limiting the scope of the (variably) strict analysis Conditional Duality is also a way of maintaining such an account.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Adams, E. (1975). The logic of conditionals. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Atlas, J. D. (1993). The importance of being only: Testing the neo-Gricean versus neo entailment paradigms. Journal of Semantics, 10, 301–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barker, S. J. (1994). Conditional excluded middle, conditional assertion, and only if. Analysis, 53, 254–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barker, S. J. (1997). E-type pronouns, DRT, dynamic semantics and the quantifier/variable binding model. Linguistics and Philosophy, 20, 195–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Lev, M. (2016). Homogeneity phenomena and free choice disjunction. Handout, talk Hebrew University Jerusalem.

  • Bartsch, R. (1973). ‘Negative Transportation’ gibt es nicht. Linguistische Berichte, 27, 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bassi, I., & Bar-Lev, M. (2016). Existential semantics for bare conditionals. Handout, MIT LF Reading Group meeting.

  • Cohen, A. (2004). Existential generics. Linguistics and Philosophy, 27, 137–168.

  • Deal, A. R. (2011). Modals without scales. Language, 87(3), 559–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dekker, P. (2001). On if and only. In R. Hastings, B. Jackson, & Z. Zvolensky (Eds.), Proceedings from SALT XI (pp. 114–133). Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowty, D. (1994). The role of negative polarity and concord marking in natural language reasoning. In Proceedings from SALT IV.

  • Dummett, M. (1973). Frege. Philosophy of language. New York: Harper & Row Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egrì P. & Politzer, G. (2013). On the negation of indicative conditionals. In M. Aloni, M. Franke, & F. Roelofsen (Eds.), Proceedings of the 19th Amsterdam Colloquium (pp. 10–18), University of Amsterdam.

  • Fodor, J. D. (1970). The linguistic description of opaque contexts. Dissertation, MIT.

  • Gajewski, J. (2005). On the excluded middle. Paper presented at the 36th Meeting of the North Eastern Linguistics Society, University of Massachusetts Amherst.

  • Geis, M. (1973). If and unless. In B. B. Kachru, R. B. Lees, Y. Malkiel, A. Pietrangeli, & S. Saporta (Eds.), Issues in linguistics (Papers in Honor of Henry and Reneé Kahane) (pp. 231–253). Urbana-Champaign, IL: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I., & Kratzer, A. (1998). Semantics in generative grammar. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herburger, E. (2000). What counts. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Herburger, E. (2015a). Only if: If only we understood it. In: E. Csipak, & H. Zeijlstra (Eds.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 19 (pp. 284–301), published online and hosted by the German Semantic Society.

  • Herburger, E. (2015b). Conditional perfection: The truth and the whole truth. In: S. D’Antonio, M. Moroney, & C. R. Little (Eds.) Proceedings of Salt 25 (pp. 615–635), published online and hosted by Linguistic Society of America.

  • Herburger, E., & Mauck, S. (2013). The chance of being an NPI. In E. Csipak, R. Eckardt, M. Li, & M. Sailer (Eds.), Beyond ‘any’ and ‘ever’. New explorations in negative polarity sensitivity (pp. 213–240). Berlin: Mouton DeGrutyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higginbotham, J. (1986). Linguistic theory and Davidson’s program in semantics. In E. LePore (Ed.), Truth and interpretation: Perspectives on the philosophy of Donald Davidson (pp. 29–48). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higginbotham, J. (2003). Conditionals and compositionality. In J. Hawthorne & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Language and philosophical linguistics, Volume 17: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 181–194). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. (1989). A natural history of negation. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. (1996). Exclusive company: Only and the semantics of vertical inference. Journal of Semantics, 13, 11–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. (2002). Assertoric inertia and NPI licensing. In M. Andronis, E. Debenport, A. Pycha, & K. Yoshimura (Eds.), Proceedings from the Chicago linguistics society: The panels (pp. 55–82). Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huitink, J. (2010). Quantified conditionals and compositionality. Language and Linguistics Compass, 4, 42–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kadmon, N. (1989). On unique and non-unique reference and asymmetric quantification. Dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst, published 1993. New York: Garland.

  • Klinedinst, N. (2010). Quantified conditionals and Conditional Excluded Middle. Journal of Semantics, 28, 149–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. (1986). Conditionals. In A. M. Farley, P. Farley, & K. E. McCollough (Eds.), Papers from the Parasession pragmatics and grammatical theory (pp. 115–135). Chicago: Chicago Linguistics Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. (2012). Modals and conditionals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. (2014). Chasing hook: Quantified indicative conditionals. In W. Lee & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conditionals, probability and paradox: Themes from the philosophy of Dorothy Edgington. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (1996). Pragmatic strengthening in plural predications and donkey sentences. In T. Galloway & J. Spence (Eds.), Proceedings of SALT IV. Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasersohn, P. (1999). Pragmatic halos. Language, 75, 522–551.

  • Leslie, S. J. (2009). If, unless and quantification. In R. J. Stainton & C. Viger (Eds.), Compositionality, context and semantic values: Essays in honour of Ernie Lepore, Volume 85: Studies in linguistics and philosophy (pp. 3–30). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, C. I. (1918). Survey of symbolic logic. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1975). Adverbs of quantification. In E. Keenan (Ed.), Formal semantics of natural language (pp. 178–188). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Löbner, S. (1985). Definites. Journal of Semantics, 4, 275–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ludlow, P. (2002). LF and natural logic. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Logical form and language (pp. 132–168). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magri, G. (2013). An account for the homogeneity effects triggered by plural definites and conjunction based on double strengthening. Ms. CNRS, Paris 8.

  • Malamud, S. A. (2012). The meaning of plural definites: A decision theoretic approach. Semantics and Pragmatics, 5, 1–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthewson, L. (2013). Gitskan modals. International Journal of American Linguistics, 79, 349–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCawley, J. (1974). If and only if. Linguistic Inquiry, 5, 632–635.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCawley, J. (1993). Everything linguists always wanted to know about semantics but were ashamed to ask. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, T. (2010). Epistemic modality and evidentiality in Gitskan at the semantics-pragmatics interface. Doctoral dissertation, University of British Columbia.

  • Pizzi, C., & Williamson, T. (2005). Conditional excluded middle in systems of consequential implication. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 34, 333–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rooth, M. (1985). Association with focus. Dissertation, University of Massachussetts.

  • Rullmann, H., Matthewson, L., & Davis, H. (2008). Modals as distributive indefinites. Natural Language Semantics, 20, 317–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sag, I. (1976). Deletion and logical form. Dissertation, MIT.

  • Schein, B. (2003). Adverbial, descriptive reciprocals. In J. Hawthorne (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives 17 (pp 333–367).

  • Schein, B. (2016). Noughty bits. Linguistics and Philosophy, 39, 459–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlenker, P. (2004). Conditionals as definite descriptions. (A referential analysis). Research on Language and Computation, 2(3), 417–162.

  • Schubert, L., & Pelletier, F. (1989). Generically speaking, or, using discourse representation theory to interpret generics. In G. Chierchia, B. Partee, & R. Turner (Eds.), Properties, types and meaning. Vol II: Semantic issues (pp. 193–268). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sommers, F. (1982). The logic of natural language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spector, B. (2007). Aspects of the pragmatics of plural morphology: On higher order implicatures. In U. Sauerland & P. Stateva (Eds.), Presupposition and implicature in compositional semantics. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in logical theory, volume 2: American philosophical quarterly monograph series (pp. 98–112). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1975). Indicative conditionals. Philosophia, 5, 269–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1981). A defense of conditional excluded middle. In W. L. Harper, R. Stalnaker, & B. Pearce (Eds.), IFS: conditionals, belief, decision, chance, and time. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szabolcsi, A., & Haddican, B. (2004). Conjunction meets negation: A study of cross-linguistic variation. Journal of Semantics, 21, 219–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Craenenbroeck, J., & Merchant, J. (2013). Ellipsis phenomena. In M. den Dikken (Ed.), The Cambridge handbook of generative syntax (pp. 701–745). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K. (1997). Bare plurals, bare conditionals, and only. Journal of Pragmatics, 14, 1–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K. (1998). Quantifiers and ‘if’-clauses. Philosophical Quarterly, 48, 209–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K. (1999). NPI licensing, Strawson entailment, and context dependency. Journal of Semantics, 16, 97–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, L. (2001). Counterfactuals in a dynamic context. In M. Kenstowicz (Ed.), Ken Hale: A life in language (pp. 123–152). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K., & Iatridou, S. (2002). If and when ‘if’-clauses can restrict quantifiers. Ms. MIT.

  • Wallis, J. (1687). Institutio logicae. Oxford: Prostant abud J. Fletcher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, J. R. G. (2010). Defending conditional excluded middle. Nous, 44, 650–668.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yanovic, I. (2016). Old English *motan, variable force modality, and the presupposition of inevitable actualization. Language, 93(3), 489–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yoon, Y. (1994). Weak and strong interpretations of quantifiers and definite NPs in Englsih and Korean, Dissertation, University of Texas at Austin.

Download references

Acknowledgements

For very helpful questions and comments I would like to thank two anonymous reviewers for Linguistics and Philosophy, and also Sam Alxatib, Wayne Davis, Larry Horn, Paul Portner, Aynat Rubinstein, Barry Schein, and Benjamin Spector, who commented on an earlier version at aworkshop in honor of Martin Prinzhorn in Vienna in November 2017. Parts of this paper were also presented at the Conditionals at a Cross-Roads Workshop (University of Konstanz, November 2016), the New Research in Modality Workshop (Georgetown University, May 2016), at the 25th Semantics and Linguistic Theory Conference (Stanford, May 2015) and at the 19th Sinn und Bedeutung Conference (Göttingen University, September 2014). I am grateful to the audiences there for their insightful questions. All remaining mistakes are my own.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elena Herburger.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Herburger, E. Bare conditionals in the red. Linguist and Philos 42, 131–175 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-018-9242-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-018-9242-2

Keywords

Navigation