Introduction

Polarity-sensitive expressions (PSIs) are words or multi-word expressions that are limited in their distribution to a range of so-called licensing environments (Chierchia 2004, 2013; Giannakidou 1998, 2019; Israel 1996, 2011; Krifka 1995; Ladusaw 1979; Szabolcsi 2004; among others). We distinguish between negative polarity items (NPIs) like ever, which require a negative context to be licensed (1a), and positive polarity items (PPIs) like already, which are anti-licensedFootnote 1 by negative contexts (1b). Within and across languages, there is a large number of words that are polarity-sensitive, with substantial variation in their lexical categories: PSIs in English, for instance, include indefinites like ever, any (NPIs), some (PPI), degree modifiers like at all, all that, much (NPIs), pretty, somewhat (PPIs), and idiomatic expressions like to lift a finger, a red cent (NPIs), all the time in the world (PPI). In turn, the environments that license NPIs and/or anti-license PPIs themselves are extremely varied—in addition to sentential negation as in (1a), NPIs can also be licensed under the scope of negative quantifiers like no or nobody (2a), under downward-entailingFootnote 2 operators like few (3a), in nonveridicalFootnote 3 contexts like questions (4a) or the antecedent of conditionals (5a), and in superlatives (6a). Other (so-called strong) NPIs, by contrast, are licensed only in the strongest negative environments (e.g., either, which is only licensed in at least anti-additiveFootnote 4 environments). Similar patterns arise for PPIs: Already is acceptable in questions (4b), conditionals (5b) and superlatives (6b), while the PPI some is additionally acceptable under downward-entailing operators like few (Few people had eaten something for breakfast).

(1) a. Mary has*(n’t) ever been to Paris.

 b. John has(#n’t) already left the party.

(2) a. Nobody/*Somebody I know has ever been to Paris.

 b. #Nobody/Somebody has already left the party.

(3) a. Few/*Many of my students have ever been to Paris.

 b. #Few/Many people have already left the party.

(4) a. Has Mary ever been to Paris?

 b. Has John already left the party?

(5) a. If Mary ever goes to Paris, she must visit the Louvre.

 b. If John has already left the party, I cannot introduce him to Mary tonight.

(6) a.The Louvre is the best museum that Mary has ever been to.

 b. The funniest person who has already left the party is John.

(7) No one thinks that John hasn’t already left the party.

(8) A: John already left the party.

 B: No, John HASN’T already left, I just saw him.

Finally, the distribution of PPIs is further complicated by the fact that they can be rescued (Szabolcsi 2004) if the negation scoping over the PPI is itself outscoped by an (at least) downward-entailing operator (7), or if the negation is understood as an emphatic denial or contrast to an earlier assertion (8). By comparison, unlicensed NPIs always make the sentence ungrammatical; NPI and PPI violations are thus qualitatively distinct (Liu and Iordǎchioaia 2018; see also Liu et al. 2019 for experimental evidence).

Relatedly, deriving a general licensing property from the distributional facts outlined above has been a challenging pursuit. To highlight just a few controversial issues, let us consider two main approaches to polarity sensitivity: First off, scalar approaches (Israel 1996, 2011; Kadmon and Landman 1993; Krifka 1995; among others) hold that PSIs are expressions whose usage is restricted to contexts that license particular scalar inferences.Footnote 5 For the NPI ever, for instance, the assertion with the NPI has to be more informative than its alternatives to license its use. This is straightforwardly assured through the entailment relations between the former and the latter in contexts that are (at least) downward entailing. For questions (4), conditionals (5), or superlatives (6), however, it requires reliance on weaker concepts of entailment (e.g., Strawson-entailment, von Fintel 1999) or on a different notion of informativity (van Rooy 2003). Alternatively, the veridicality-based theory by Giannakidou (1998, 2019) holds that PSIs are sensitive to the veridicality of the environment, such that NPIs like ever are restricted to nonveridical contexts, whereas PPIs like already are repelled by contexts that are antiveridical, i.e., contexts where the falsehood of the proposition is entailed or presupposed. However, this approach, too, faces challenges, one of which is that one has to appeal to theoretically unattractive rescuing operations for NPIs that appear in contexts that do entail the truth of the proposition (e.g., Only Mary has ever been to Paris).

All in all, the intricacies of PSI licensing—as exemplified through their distributional differences and the difficulty to generalise to a unifying licensing property—constitute a challenge for language learners: Given that PSIs vary in strength, and may not occur equally frequently with their full set of licensing environments,Footnote 6 it is an open question how and at what point in development children learn to generalise from the limited input of a (licensed) PSI to an unconscious knowledge of all the contexts that can or cannot license said expression. To our knowledge, existing studies on the acquisition of PSIs have largely targeted the comprehension and production of highly frequent PSIs like any (O’Leary and Crain 1994; Tieu 2013; Tieu and Lidz 2016), some (O’Leary and Crain 1994), or the Dutch NPI hoeven (‘need’) (Lin et al. 2015, 2018), in relatively young age groups. The findings, summarised in more detail below, are that 5-year-olds are almost adult-like in their production of the tested NPIs, whereas the data is not as clear-cut for the PPI some. The present study will complement this work through an investigation of 11–12-year-olds’ comprehension of German NPIs and PPIs. Since children’s language faculty is still undergoing substantial development throughout childhood and adolescence, with important maturational milestones at age 10–11 (see below), our study provides important new insight on the comprehension of PSIs in a more mature, yet developing, language system. We identified four PSIs that are present, but infrequent, in German child language corpora, and used an auditory naturalness rating task to assess whether children at age 11–12 are aware of the distributional restrictions of the tested PSIs. The results show the correct directionality in children’s responses, i.e., a dispreference for un-/anti-licensed PSIs, but only for one of the tested expressions, the NPI jemals (‘ever’), did we find the same clear-cut distinction into grammatical and ungrammatical uses as for adults. For the three other expressions, children did not categorically reject un-/anti-licensed uses.

Previous Studies on the Acquisition of PSIs

The literature on the acquisition of PSIs primarily centres around the English NPI any and the Dutch NPI hoeven (‘need’). For any, Tieu (2013) reports that children are remarkably consistent in producing any within the scope of a licenser (primarily under the scope of sentential negation, Tieu 2013:53) in spontaneous speech, using any in affirmative contexts in only 2% of the analysed transcripts. This finding is consistent with earlier results from an elicited production study by O’Leary and Crain (1994) (reported in Gualmini 2004): 4–5-year-old children were prompted with short scenarios intended to provoke the use of some or any in their response. After a brief story, a puppet uttered a false statement about what had happened as in (9a) and (10a). Children were prompted for a response by asking ‘What really happened?’. Despite the use of any in the puppet’s utterance in (9a), children would usually respond with affirmative utterances using some (e.g., Every dog got some food) rather than any (*Every dog got any food). Together, the corpus and experimental data suggest that children show an early sensitivity to the distributional restriction of any in their produced speech. At the same time, it does not constitute direct evidence that children would actually reject any in all positive contexts, that is, that they have the grammatical knowledge that any is incompatible with positive linguistic environments.

(9) Context: The dogs are hungry, and every dog ate something.

 a. Puppet: Only one dog got any food.

 b. Experimenter: What really happened?

(10) Context: The dogs are hungry, but one of the dogs did not eat anything.

 a. Puppet: Every dog got some food.

 b. Experimenter: What really happened?

Mirroring the English data, spontaneous speech transcripts for Dutch hoeven (‘need’), too, indicate that children only rarely produce unlicensed instances (4% of the data were classified as non-adult-like) (Lin et al. 2015). Moreover, across all analysed transcripts, sentential negation was the most frequent licenser (95.9% in children’s utterances) and only at age 4–5 did negative quantifiers emerge as a second licenser used by children. Using an elicited imitation task, Lin et al. (2018) further showed that the set of licensers used by children widens over time: 2–5-year-olds would listen to sentences containing hoeven licensed by niet (‘not’), geen (‘no’), niemand (‘nobody’), weinig (‘few’), alleen (‘only’), or without a licenser, and were told to repeat the sentence as accurately as possible. Non-repetitions or changes in the repeated sentence are assumed to indicate that the stimulus was inconsistent with the child’s grammar (Lin et al. 2018:53). The authors found age-related differences in the repetition rates: Niet (‘not’) and geen (‘no’) emerged as licensers before the age of three, whereas the repetition rate for niemand (‘nobody’), weinig (‘few’), and alleen (‘only’) only increased at around 4 years of age. Moreover, children only rarely changed a sentence containing licensed hoeven to a sentence in which hoeven was not licensed. In response to sentences containing unlicensed hoeven, however, children changed the sentence in more than half of the responses, i.e., they added a licenser or substituted unlicensed hoeven with a different word in order to make the sentence grammatical.

From the Dutch data, Lin et al. (2015, 2018) argue for an input-driven conservative widening strategy, wherein children’s acquisition of hoeven is marked by two distinct developmental stages: First, a stage of analysing hoeven as being in a lexical dependency with the sentential negator niet or the negative quantifier geen, which is falsified by language input where hoeven receives other licensers. Then, a reanalysis to associate hoeven with an abstract NEG (negation) operator that encompasses the full range of licensing environments. This account provides a possible developmental pathway for the acquisition of NPIs that explains how children generalise from limited input to the full set of licensers and that accounts for the rarity of unlicensed NPIs in children’s speech. However, it remains unclear whether this approach is directly applicable to other NPIs: Hoeven is quite particular in so far as the corpus data indicates that it overwhelmingly appears with niet (80.8%) or geen (15.4%) as licensers in child-directed speech (Lin et al. 2015). A conservative widening strategy seems less plausible for NPIs that consistently appear with a greater variety of licensers, making the initial analysis step of lexically associating such NPIs with a particular lexical licenser much less attractive.

With regard to the acquisition of PPIs, we are only aware of a handful of studies. Within the same elicited production study reported above, O’Leary and Crain (1994) tested for children’s production of sentences containing the PPI some. After hearing the context in (10), children produced more negative utterances containing the NPI any (e.g., No, this dog didn’t get any food) than the PPI some (#No, this dog didn’t get some food). However, the results for the PPI some were not as clear-cut as for the NPI any, which was almost never used in positive contexts. Musolino (1999) further investigated this pattern using a Truth Value Judgment Task (TVJT) with 3–6-year-old children. Children were first presented with a story acted out by puppets (11), concluding with the puppet’s statement in (11a). (11a) is acceptable if the PPI is interpreted as taking wide scope over the negation (There is someone that the detective did not find), but is unacceptable under the narrow scope interpretation (There isn’t #someone/anyone that the detective found). Although the adult control group consistently accepted the utterance, children rejected it about half of the time, arguing that it was false because the detective found one of his friends. This indicates that children assigned the narrow scope reading to the sentence although this reading is not available in the adult grammar system. Similar findings have also been observed in a TVJT by Xiang et al. (2006).

(11) Context: A detective is playing hide and seek with his two friends. At first, he doesn’t find any of them, but eventually he discovers one of them behind a tree. He does not find the second friend.

 a. Puppet: The detective didn’t find someone.

Overall, the results from both tasks suggest that children below the age of six sometimes accept some under the scope of negation, and thus do not seem to have mastered its distributional restrictions yet. However, more research on other PPIs and on other languages will be needed to establish whether the acquisition of PPIs is delayed compared to the acquisition of NPIs in general, or whether the findings reported here are specific to the contrast between some and any.

To summarise, the reported research on the acquisition of PSIs focused on just a few (highly frequent) expressions, for which the consensus is that NPIs are consistently used with a licenser from early on, but that the range of licensing expression that a child employs may change, i.e., broaden, over time. By the age of 5, children behaved largely target-like in experimental tasks requiring the production of any or hoeven. However, since all of the studies tested children who are too young to participate in metalinguistic tasks like grammaticality judgments, we do not have direct evidence for children’s receptive knowledge of the ungrammaticality of NPIs in affirmative contexts. Instead, this conclusion is only available to us by inference from the absence of such constructions in children’s speech. Turning to PPIs, existing research focused on some, for which a target-like knowledge of the distributional constraint does not appear to be reached even by the age of six. A delay in the acquisition of PPIs may well be expected given that children cannot infer their distributional constraints from a co-occurrence with other linguistic elements. While NPIs usually appear with a negative element, PPIs do not have overt lexical associates. Instead, children must somehow realise that it is the absence of negation that licenses them, a process made all the more difficult by the presence of exceptions to this rule, such as the occurrence of PPIs under two negative operators or under emphatic denials (see Introduction).

The Current Study

In order to provide more direct evidence for children’s knowledge of the distributional restrictions of PSIs, we conducted a graded naturalness rating study using NPIs and PPIs in licensing and non-licensing (or anti-licensing) contexts in adults and 11–12-year-old children. This paradigm is a simple but sensitive measure suitable for older children, which allows us to assess immediately whether they perceive PSIs in non-licensing environments as ill-formed rather than having to infer so indirectly from utterances they do (or do not) produce. Following Ambridge (2012) and Karanth and Suchitra (1993), we assume that children can engage with and respond to judgment tasks in the intended manner by the age of 6–8.

Besides the suitability of the task, the more fundamental reason to test the age group between 11 and 12 is that cognitive developmental research indicates that the language faculty is still undergoing significant maturation up until at least age 10–11 (Broce et al. 2015; Nuñez et al. 2011; Skeide et al. 2014, 2016; Vissiennon et al. 2017; Wassenberg et al. 2008; for a review see Skeide & Friederici 2016) and that syntactic and semantic development continues throughout adolescence (Hahne et al. 2004; Schneider and Maguire 2019; Schneider et al. 2016). Neurophysiologically, these maturational processes are apparent both structurally and functionally: Diffusion tensor imaging indicates that the left arcuate fasciculus (AF), a white matter tract that connects frontal with inferior parietal and temporal language areas that is known to be involved in speech and syntax processing, undergoes significant microstructural changes in 5–8 year-olds (Broce et al. 2015). The bilateral AF microstructure was also able to predict performance on receptive and expressive language tests, underscoring that its maturation may play a crucial role in language development. Skeide et al. (2016) confirmed these microstructural changes of the AF in 3–10-year-olds and found that the fibre tract maturation together with activation levels of two language areas connected by the AF (the posterior super temporal gyrus (pSTG) and the left inferior temporal gyrus (left IFG)), predicted accuracy and speed of syntactic comprehension. Two fMRI studies on syntactic and semantic comprehension (Nuñez et al. 2011; Skeide et al. 2014) further suggest that syntax and semantics are only fully segregated into separate language modules by the age of 9–10, while for younger age groups the activation patterns for syntactic and semantic processing largely overlap. Lastly, a range of studies suggest that language development continues throughout adolescence: Testing 6–13-year-olds on passive sentences containing semantic or word-category based syntactic violations, Hahne et al. (2004) found that only 13-year-olds and adults showed the early left anterior negativity (ELAN) component that indicates an automatic detection of syntactic violations, whereas younger age groups only showed the later P600 component of syntactic processing. Two recent studies employing combined ERP and time–frequency analyses of EEG data (Schneider and Maguire 2019; Schneider et al. 2016) further show age-related differences in the neural oscillations associated with language processing: Children up to the age of 13 displayed non-adult-like oscillatory (beta and theta band) activity in response to syntactic and semantic violations. Cross-sectional behavioural studies on 5–17-year-olds (Dick et al. 2004) and 5–15-year-olds (Wassenberg et al. 2008) lend additional support to the neurophysiological findings reviewed here: Dick et al. (2004) found that complex language comprehension improved significantly with age, particularly in the comparison between children aged 9 or older compared to 5–8-year-olds, and Wassenberg et al. (2008) found a linear increase in performance up until sixth grade (around 11 years old). The 11–15-year-olds in the Wassenberg et al. study did not differ in performance, but also had not reached adult comprehension levels yet.

Altogether, the neurophysiological and behavioural literature thus suggests that the language system is still undergoing substantial development in middle childhood and adolescence, but appears to reach important maturational milestones such as the segregation of syntax and semantics around age 10. For an interface phenomenon like PSIs, this development may provide a crucial basis for an increasingly adult-like comprehension. By testing 11–12-year-olds in our study, we can therefore tap into children’s comprehension of polarity-sensitive expressions at a time point where the basic neural foundation for the processing of semantics and syntax, here in the form of the relation between PSI and licenser/anti-licenser, is secured, but where we could still expect differences in the efficiency and accuracy of comprehension compared to an adult control group.

Corpus Data

We decided to conduct a study on children’s comprehension of two German NPIs, jemals (‘ever’) and so recht (‘really’), and two German PPIs, durchaus (‘quite’/‘indeed’) and absolut (‘absolutely’). Their frequencies in the syntactically annotated (tagged-T) archive of the German reference corpus DeReKo (Leibniz Institute for the German Language 2020) are 9.341 for jemals, 6.688Footnote 7 for so recht, 34.100 for absolut, and 89.311 for durchaus. The two PPIs thus are more frequent than the NPIs. Do note however that jemals can also be shortened to je, which occurs much more frequently in the corpus (212.431). German je is incredibly multi-functional: Besides the temporal use as ever, je can be used to indicate reference to each element in a set (30 Euro je Person, ‘30 Euro per person’), can function as conjunction (je früher, desto besser, ‘the earlier, the better’), or express that something is conditional on something else (je nachdem, ‘depending on’). We were therefore unable to determine the frequency of temporal uses of je in this data.

The four PSIs were selected based on their classification as NPI/PPI in the German database of distributionally idiosyncratic items (CoDII; Trawiński and Soehn, 2008), and based on our findings in a corpus search conducted via the German CHILDES database (MacWhinney, 2000). All four PSIs appear in child-directed speech within the corpus, but none of them are frequent in children’s own utterances, underscoring the need of experimental data to identify at what point children acquire these PSIs. Specifically, we analysed all four PSIs’ distribution in five German subcorpora of the CHILDES database: The Caroline (Von Stutterheim 1989), Leo (Behrens 2006), Miller (1979), Rigol (2007), and Wagner (1985) corpora. In total, 1381 CHAT files containing data from children between the age of 1;00 and 14;10 were analysed. For jemals, we searched both for je and for jemals, manually determining whether the instances of je were temporal. We report the combined number of instances, but indicate in Table 1 which ones were je and which ones were jemals. Each of the four PSIs occurred with similar frequency in child-directed speech (Table 1) and was always appropriately licensed. Interestingly, the NPI je(mals) appears with a very diverse set of licensers, including downward-entailing environments, nonveridical environments (questions and conditionals), but also superlatives and comparatives. While so recht, too, can be licensed by some of these contexts, the child-directed speech is clearly biased towards licensing by sentential negation. Critically, recall that under the conservative widening strategy proposed by Lin et al. (2015, 2018), this may lead children to initially analyse so recht as lexically associated with the sentential negation nicht. For je(mals), on the other hand, the diversity of licensers makes this approach less plausible. So far, however, it is unclear whether this could result in a delay of the acquisition of this NPI (because children may initially not be able to identify a specific lexical associate that licenses je(mals)), or might in turn facilitate it (due to a faster generalization to the abstract semantic property licensing je(mals)). Including both NPIs in our rating study may thus provide some insight on this question.

Table 1 Distribution of the four investigated PSIs in child directed speech in the German CHILDES corpora

The PPIs absolut and durchaus both appear exclusively in their licensed form in child-directed speech. Note, however, that among the instances of absolut, the corpus search revealed 12 instances (one third of all instances) in which it scopes above a negation, as in ‘Das ist absolut kein Problem’ (‘This is absolutely no problem’). For durchaus, on the other hand, no instance with wide scope negation was found, although ‘Das ist durchaus kein Problem’ (‘This is indeed no problem’) is well-formed as well. Once more, it is an open question whether the common occurrence of a PPI scoping above negation may prevent children from successfully acquiring the knowledge that the expression cannot in turn scope under negation. We will return to both the contrast between je(mals) and so recht, and the contrast between durchaus and absolut, in the discussion of our experimental results.

Children’s utterances within the analysed corpora show only very few, if any, spontaneous uses of the investigated PSIs (Table 2). So recht occurs most frequently, albeit with 7 of the 9 recorded instances coming from a single child, Leo. On the upside, there are no unlicensed PSI uses either, aside from one instance of so recht that could not be clearly classified due to word omissions (Table 2).

Table 2 Distribution of the four investigated PSIs in children’s speech in the German CHILDES corpora

Overall, the data from the German CHILDES corpora thus show that all four PSIs appear with a similar frequency in child-directed speech, but critically differ with regard to the distribution of their licensing environments. The data from children’s utterances, on the other hand, are too limited to draw conclusions on the acquisition of these PSIs, and in particular, do not allow us to conclude anything about children’s knowledge of their distributional restrictions. To measure precisely that, we conducted an auditory rating task in which 11–12-year-olds were confronted with licensed and unlicensed uses of the four PSIs. The experiment is reported in the following section.

Method

Participants

36 adults and 40 11–12-year-olds participated in the study. The adult participants (26 female, mean age = 22, age range: 18–26) were students at Osnabrück University participating for course credits. The participating children (23 female, 22 11-year-olds, 18 12-year-olds) were sixth grade secondary school students. They were reimbursed for their participation with a 10 Euro gift certificate to a local book shop. The parents of the participating children reported no developmental delays, neurological disorders, or language disorders in their child. All participants were monolingual German native speakers with normal or corrected-to-normal vision and normal hearing. The experiment was approved by the ethics committee of Osnabrück University.

Materials

We created 32 items in eight conditions such that all items contained one licensed and one unlicensed use of each of the four PSIs. As NPI licenser, respectively PPI anti-licenser, we used a negative quantifier (kein, ‘no’) in the object position scoping above the PSI. Alternatively, for the licensed PPI conditions, respectively unlicensed NPI conditions, we used a definite determiner (der, ‘the’) in the same position (see an example in (12)). We also created 16 grammatical filler sentences that did not contain a PSI: eight sentences with a relative clause, and eight sentences containing two clauses linked by a concessive discourse connective. The complete list of filler and target items is included in the Appendix.

(12)

a.

*Lukas

hat

dem

Arzt

in

dem

Krankenhaus

so

recht

vertraut.

  

Lukas

has

the

doctor

in

the

hospital

so

reallyNPI

trusted

  

‘Lukas has reallyNPI trusted the doctor in the hospital.’

 

b.

Lukas

hat

keinem

Arzt

in

dem

Krankenhaus

so

recht

vertraut.

  

Lukas

has

no

doctor

in

the

hospital

so

reallyNPI

trusted

  

‘Lukas hasn’t reallyNPI trusted the doctor in the hospital.’

 

c.

*Lukas

hat

dem

Arzt

in

dem

Krankenhaus

jemals

vertraut.

 
  

Lukas

has

the

doctor

in

the

hospital

everNPI

trusted

 
  

‘Lukas has everNPI trusted the doctor in the hospital.’

 

d.

Lukas

hat

keinem

Arzt

in

dem

Krankenhaus

jemals

vertraut.

 
  

Lukas

has

no

doctor

in

the

hospital

everNPI

trusted

 
  

‘Lukas hasn’t everNPI trusted the doctor in the hospital.’

 

e.

Lukas

hat

dem

Arzt

in

dem

Krankenhaus

absolut

vertraut.

 
  

Lukas

has

the

doctor

in

the

hospital

absolutelyPPI

trusted

 
  

‘Lukas has absolutelyPPI trusted the doctor in the hospital.’

 

f.

#Lukas

hat

keinem

Arzt

in

dem

Krankenhaus

absolut

vertraut.

 
  

Lukas

has

no

doctor

in

the

hospital

absolutelyPPI

trusted

 
  

‘Lukas hasn’t absolutelyPPI trusted the doctor in the hospital.’

 

g.

Lukas

hat

dem

Arzt

in

dem

Krankenhaus

durchaus

vertraut.

 
  

Lukas

has

the

doctor

in

the

hospital

quitePPI

trusted

 
  

‘Lukas has quitePPI trusted the doctor in the hospital.’

 

h.

#Lukas

hat

keinem

Arzt

in

dem

Krankenhaus

durchaus

vertraut.

 
  

Lukas

has

no

doctor

in

the

hospital

quitePPI

trusted

 
  

‘Lukas hasn’t quitePPI trusted the doctor in the hospital.’

Filler and target sentences were recorded by a female German native speaker. The audio files were subsequently edited to remove periods of silence at the onset or offset of the recordings and to normalise them to the same volume. Both editing steps were conducted using the audio editing software AudacityFootnote 8 (Audacity Team 2019). To ensure that there are no prosodic cues towards a sentence’s grammaticality in the stimuli, we recorded four additional sentences for each target item, in which the (anti-)licensing quantifier was replaced by a nonsense syllable (e.g., Lukas hat fla Arzt in dem Krankenhaus [so recht / jemals / absolut / durchaus vertraut.], ‘Lukas has fla doctor in the hospital [really / ever / absolutely / quite trusted.]’). The bracketed segment was then spliced into the conditions of (12), such that both the un-/anti-licensed and the licensed condition had the same auditory signal at the critical point in the sentence where the PSI occurs.

Procedure

Adults and children were tested using the same procedure. We used a naturalness rating task with a 7-point Likert scale to assess whether participants are sensitive to the restricted distribution of the tested PSIs. The experiment was programmed and hosted on Ibex Farm (Drummond 2013). Participants wore headphones throughout the experiment. In each trial, they first listened to a sentence. Once the sentence had finished playing, a comprehension question appeared on the screen asking participants to choose the correct completion of a sentence fragment (e.g., for (12): Lukas is…(a) in the hospital (b) at a retirement home). Participants could replay the sentence as often as they wanted. After the comprehension question had been answered, a rating scale appeared in its place asking participants to rate the naturalness of the sentence they had just heard. The scalar endpoints were marked with the labels natural (7) and unnatural (1). We added smiley faces along the scale to illustrate the response scheme. Once participants clicked on a response, the trial ended and the next trial began. Participants saw 32 experimental trials and 16 filler trials presented in a pseudorandom order such that no more than three experimental trials would appear in immediate sequence and two experimental trials with the same PSI would never appear right after each other. The experiment started with two practice trials. The total experimental duration was approximately 15 min.

Data Analysis

We used Bayesian ordinal regression models with a cumulative link function (Bürkner and Vuorre 2019) to analyse the rating data. All analyses were conducted using the brms package, version 2.12 (Bürkner 2017) in R, version 4.0 (R Core Team 2019). Before the main analysis, we assessed participants’ response accuracy on the comprehension questions. For both adults and children, all participants had a response accuracy > 95%. We therefore did not exclude any participants from our analysis. For all models, the effect of context (licensing/non-licensing) was treatment coded (0, 1); the PSI comparisons were entered as custom contrasts such that the model included a comparison between the two PPIs and the two NPIs, a comparison between jemals and so recht (the NPIs), and a comparison between absolut and durchaus (the PPIs), each entered as sum coded contrasts (0.5, −0.5). All models used the maximal random effects structure, including random by-subject and by-item intercepts and slopes for all effects. When necessary to resolve an interaction, the models were rerun using treatment coding for the PSI comparisons. We used uninformative uniform priors on the fixed effects. For each model, 4 chains were run with 4000 sampling iterations each using a warm-up period of 2000 iterations. We report the posterior parameter estimates together with the 95 percent credible intervals and the posterior probability that the parameter value is bigger/smaller than 0. All data and code are available online (see data availability statement).

Results

Adults

Adults’ rating responses are visualised in Fig. 1. Adult participants demonstrate a clear categorical differentiation between licensed and unlicensed PSI uses: For all tested PSIs, the licensed condition was rated more natural than the unlicensed one (P(β < 0) = 1 for all PSIs). Furthermore, we found an interaction between the licensing status and the contrast between NPIs and PPIs (\(\hat{\beta}\) = 0.53, CrI = [0.08, 0.98], P(β > 0) = 0.99)Footnote 9: In licensed conditions, there was no evidence for a difference in the naturalness of the tested NPIs and PPIs (\(\hat{\beta}\) = 0.07, CrI = [-0.20, 0.37], P(β > 0) = 0.69), whereas in unlicensed conditions, the model indicated that PPIs were given higher naturalness ratings than NPIs (\(\hat{\beta}\) = 0.61, CrI = [0.26, 0.95], P(β > 0) = 1). This is in line with theoretical and experimental work (Liu and Iordǎchioaia, 2018; Liu et al. 2019) that argues that NPI violations and PPI violations are qualitatively distinct, such that NPI violations result in irrescuable ungrammaticality, whereas PPIs in negative contexts can often be saved (see also Introduction). Further comparisons between the tested PSIs demonstrated that both the NPI so recht (‘really’) and the PPI absolut (‘absolutely’) received somewhat higher naturalness ratings in non-licensing contexts than their counterparts jemals (‘ever’) (\(\hat{\beta}\) = − 1.33, CrI = [− 1.81, − 0.87], P(β < 0) = 1) and durchaus (‘quite’) (\(\hat{\beta}\) = − 0.88, CrI = [− 1.29, − 0.46], P(β < 0) = 1). Overall, the difference in the rating for licensed and unlicensed conditions was smaller for absolut (‘absolutely’) than for any of the other tested expressions (P(β < 0) = 1 for all comparisons), which is largely because anti-licensed absolut was not clearly rejected.

Fig. 1
figure 1

Boxplot of adults’ naturalness ratings for the eight conditions of the experiment. The thick black line shows the median rating per condition, the upper and lower hinges of the box correspond to the first and third quartile. Whiskers extend to the smallest/largest value that is no further than 1.5-times the interquartile range away from the hinges of the box. Individual dots represent each participant’s median rating across the repeated measures

11–12-Year-Olds

The children’s responses are visualised in Fig. 2. Overall, children’s naturalness ratings showed the expected directionality, such that unlicensed PSI uses were rated less natural than licensed ones (P(β < 0) = 1 for all PSIs). 11–12-year-olds do, therefore, demonstrate an awareness of the distributional restriction of these expressions. In licensing contexts, there was weak evidence for higher naturalness ratings for the (affirmative) PPI conditions compared to the (negative) NPI conditions (\(\hat{\beta}\) = 0.41, CrI = [− 0.09, 0.91], P(β > 0) = 0.95), which may reflect a preference for non-negated utterances in general, or integration costs of licensed NPIs—an effect that was absent in adults. Contrary to the adult participant sample, we only found weak evidence for an interaction between the licensing status and the contrast between NPIs and PPIs (\(\hat{\beta}\) = 0.44, CrI = [− 0.22, 1.10], P(β > 0) = 0.90). Instead, the model indicated differences that were specific to the comparison between jemals, on the one hand, and absolut, durchaus, and so recht, on the other. Direct comparisons between these expressions indicated that 11–12-year-olds showed a higher acceptance of unlicensed uses of absolut, durchaus, and so recht, than of jemals (P(β < 0) = 1 for all comparisons).

Fig. 2
figure 2

Boxplot of 11–12-year-olds’ naturalness ratings for the eight conditions of the experiment. The thick black line shows the median rating per condition, the upper and lower hinges of the box correspond to the first and third quartile. Whiskers extend to the smallest/largest value that is no further than 1.5-times the interquartile range away from the hinges of the box. Individual dots represent each participant’s median rating across the repeated measures

Comparison Between Groups

In order to address the question whether 11–12-year-olds differ from adults in their comprehension of PSIs, we built a model on the combined data sets. We used the same model parameters as outlined above, but additionally included the sample (adults/children) as factor interacting with the factors context and PSI. We added this factor as sum coded contrast (0.5, −0.5). The model indicated an interaction between context and group (\(\hat{\beta}\) = − 0.94, CrI = [− 1.38, − 0.49], P(β < 0) = 1), such that, across all four PSIs, children made a smaller, less categorical, difference in their naturalness ratings for licensing and non-licensing contexts than adults (see also Table 3). Within the licensing contexts, children rated the sentences as less natural overall than adults (\(\hat{\beta}\) = 0.61, CrI = [0.25, 0.95], P(β > 0) = 1). Additionally, we found weak evidence that children generally gave higher ratings for PSIs in non-licensing contexts than adults (\(\hat{\beta}\) = -0.33, CrI = [− 0.72, 0.06], P(β < 0) = 0.95). With regard to group differences for particular PSIs, we did not find strong evidence for any such effects in the licensed PSI conditions (P(β < 0) < 0.90 or all comparisons). That is, for the grammatical target sentences, there were no PSI-specific differences between the two groups. In non-licensing contexts, on the other hand, there was evidence for group differences in the comparison between the two NPIs (\(\hat{\beta}\) = 0.57, CrI = [+0.00, 1.15], P(β > 0) = 0.98) and in the comparison between the two PPIs (\(\hat{\beta}\) = 0.64, CrI = [0.08, 1.18], P(β > 0) = 0.99): Both adults and children rejected unlicensed jemals (\(\hat{\beta}\) = − 0.04, CrI = [− 0.50, 0.42], P(β > 0) = 0.43), but children showed a higher acceptance for unlicensed so recht than adults (\(\hat{\beta}\) = 0.52, CrI = [0.05, 0.99], P(β > 0) = 0.99). With regard to the PPIs, children showed a higher acceptance for anti-licensed durchaus than adults (\(\hat{\beta}\) = 0.72, CrI = [0.28, 1.17], P(β > 0) = 1), while both groups accepted anti-licensed absolut to a similar—unexpectedly high—degree (\(\hat{\beta}\) = 0.11, CrI = [− 0.33, 0.56], P(β > 0) = 0.68).

Table 3 Adults’ and 11–12-year-olds’ mean naturalness ratings on a 1–7 Likert scale for the eight conditions of the experiment. Standard deviation in parentheses

Discussion

Using an auditory naturalness rating task, the current study investigated 11–12-year-olds’ comprehension of four German PSIs. It yielded three main results: First, we found that 11–12-year-old children trend towards adult-like comprehension of PSIs in the directionality of their responses to all four PSIs. For the NPI jemals, children’s responses did not differ from those of adults, indicating that they know its distributional restriction. For the NPI so recht and the PPI durchaus, on the other hand, children did not categorically reject un-/anti-licensed uses. Finally, we found that neither group consistently rejected anti-licensed uses of the PPI absolut. Altogether, our results thus indicate that the acquisition of PSIs takes place across a much broader period of childhood than accredited by previous studies (Lin et al. 2015, 2018; Musolini 1998; O’Leary and Crain 1994; Tieu 2013; Tieu and Lidz 2016; Xiang et al. 2006).

We have investigated a relatively old age group of 11–12-year-old children. The motivation for targeting children at this age was that crucial maturational milestones in the neurocognitive development of the language network are reported to have been reached by then (see above). Indeed, since we found that one of the investigated PSIs, jemals, was understood in an adult-like manner, it seems that the foundation for the comprehension of the distributional restrictions of PSIs is in place by this age and that 11–12-year-olds were able to identify and reject unlicensed uses in the sentence rating task. The remaining differences between the tested PSIs, however, require further scrutiny. In the following, we will discuss distributional differences and the special status of attenuating PSIs as potential causes for the observed differences, and will put into question the PPI-hood of absolut.

Distributional Differences Between the Tested NPIs

In the corpus data above, we reported that the NPIs so recht and jemals are similarly frequent in child-directed speech, but vary with regard to their distribution over different licensing environments. We hypothesised that this may well affect the acquisition process, such that a greater variety of licensers in the input could facilitate the abstraction of the rule governing the distribution of the NPI: The different licensing contexts provide converging pieces of evidence for a common linguistic property—downward entailment, nonveridicality, or alike—underlying them all. The results from our rating study lend some support to this idea: Children’s comprehension of jemals, which occurred with a broader range of licensers in the corpus, was at an adult-like level, whereas the results for so recht, which occurred exclusively under sentential negation, indicated that 11–12-year-olds had not yet learned that it cannot occur in affirmative contexts. Future investigations will have to tell whether this contrast generalises to other languages or NPIs.

A second hypothesis that followed from the corpus data was that so recht is a prime candidate for a conservative widening strategy, i.e., an acquisition process wherein the dominance of particular licensers (here, sentential negation) favours an initial analysis of the NPI as being lexically dependent on said licenser. In the present case, this would lead to an analysis where the acceptability of so recht is dependent on its co-occurrence with nicht (‘not’). In later acquisition stages, this analysis would then be revised to reflect the general linguistic property licensing so recht. Crucially, however, at no stage in the process does this account predict that completely unlicensed uses of so recht would be considered acceptable by the language learner.Footnote 10 The results from our study, wherein unlicensed so recht was rated much more natural by children than by adults, thus do not match with the conservative widening account. In our view, the account’s assumption that children’s initial analysis reflects a dependency relation, rather than a mere lexical collocation, between NPI and licenser may be too strong, particularly regarding its prediction that NPIs in other licensing environments should be altogether rejected by children at this stage. Instead, we will need a theory of NPI acquisition that can contend with (i) an asymmetry in production and comprehension, such that both the rarity of unlicensed NPI uses in production and the tolerance for unlicensed uses in comprehension are accounted for, and that (ii) can deal with distributional differences in NPIs, including both NPIs with a small set of relatively homogeneous licensers and NPIs with variable licensers, such as discussed on the example of jemals above.

On Attenuating PSIs

The NPI so recht and the PPI durchaus, which were accepted in non-licensing contexts to a higher degree by 11–12-year-olds, both have an attenuating function. According to Israel (1996, 2011), attenuating PSIs render an assertion less informative than a contextually available alternative. With so recht in (13), for instance, the negation of the high degree modifier renders the assertion vague about the extent to which the speaker actually (dis-)liked the book. In (14), too, the assertion with durchaus carries the implicature that there are in fact aspects of the book that the speaker did not like. This is further evidenced by the oddness of discourse continuation (14a) compared to (14b).

An open question is whether attenuating PSIs are potentially delayed in their acquisition compared to other PSIs. If so, this would constitute an alternative, input-independent, explanation for the contrast between so recht and jemals in the results for 11–12-year-olds. On the surface, the lexical operators that license attenuating PSIs are the same as for other PSIs. A lexical association between licensing operator and PSI should thus be equally easy to form. What may be more challenging to acquire, however, is the generalised property underlying their distribution, namely that they are restricted to contexts where the PSI makes the assertion weaker. The pragmatic power of intentionally producing a less informative sentence lies in all that is not said. It can be pragmatically desirable to avoid the stronger assertion if a speaker does not want to commit to it for lack of evidence (i.e., they do not know whether the stronger assertion holds), but also out of more “strategic” concerns in interpersonal communication, e.g., to be more polite (15) (Brown and Levinson 1987; regarding politeness and PSIs: Israel 2011:109ff). On the other hand, given a supporting discourse context, the attenuated assertion can sometimes also be understood as understatement, such that the speaker actually means to communicate the stronger statement but asserts the weaker one for pragmatic effect, often to be humorous (16). The complex social-pragmatic functions of attenuated assertions with PSIs may render them more difficult to acquire, particularly at early stages of children’s development when they are still known to struggle with pragmatic processes, including the drawing of implicatures (Huang and Snedeker 2009; Noveck 2001; but cf. Katsos and Bishop 2011), the comprehension of irony such as in ironic understatements (Demorest et al. 1983; Recchia et al. 2010), and the knowledge of the markers and the purpose of politeness in language (Nippold et al. 1982; Yoon 2019). We thus consider it an important avenue for further research to more closely investigate the differences between emphatic and attenuating PSIs.

(15)

(After a teacher explained something to class:)

 

Ich

habe

das

noch

nicht

(so

recht)

vertanden,

könnten

Sie

das

wiederholen?

 

I

have

this

still

not

so

really

understood

could

you

this

repeat

 

‘I didn’t (quite) understand this yet, could you repeat it?’

(16)

(About someone who just utterly failed at a task:)

    
 

Na,

das

hat

ja

nicht

so

recht

geklappt.

    
 

Well

this

has

yes

not

so

really

worked

    
 

‘Well, that didn’t work out so well.’

    

The High Tolerance for the Anti-licensed PPI Absolut

With regard to the tested PPIs, our results show that 11–12-year-olds are more accepting of anti-licensed uses of durchaus than adults, suggesting that its distributional restriction has not been fully acquired yet. Similarly, we also found a high acceptance of anti-licensed uses of absolut. Crucially however, the latter effect was also present in adults. That adults would assign such high naturalness ratings for anti-licensed absolut puts into question whether its classification as PPI in CoDII (Trawiński and Soehn 2008) is correct. In fact, we found several instances of absolut in the scope of negation on the web (17, 18). In all of these cases, the sentences are understood to indicate that a property holds in principle, but does not hold completely (nicht absolut, ‘not absolutely’). The same interpretation is available for our stimulus material. To illustrate, consider one of our items, (12f), repeated with a supporting context in (19). We thus conclude that absolut is not a PPI.

Conclusion

Our study on the comprehension of German PSIs has found a range of differences between 11–12-year-old children and adults that indicate that the acquisition of some polarity-sensitive expressions, like jemals, may be completed by age 12, while the acquisition of others, like so recht and durchaus, is still ongoing. The sources of this acquisitional delay, which we have argued to be potentially attributable to differences in the language input or to differences in the status of PSIs as attenuating or emphatic, require further research. Although our study is limited in scope and therefore had to leave many questions about the acquisition of PSIs unanswered, the mere fact that this process extends at least into late childhood and possibly adolescence hopefully inspires a new line of work. Fruitful avenues that could provide more insight into this challenging phenomenon may lie in the extension of the studied age groups, particularly in filling the gap between the 5-year-olds studied before and the 11–12-year-olds studied here, but also in the application of novel experimental paradigms and methodologies available for older children (e.g., EEG, eye-tracking, sentence completion, but also assessments of pragmatic reasoning skills and of regular language input in the form of reading).