Skip to main content
Log in

Moral Perception as Imaginative Apprehension

  • Published:
The Journal of Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Moral perception is typically understood as moral properties perception, i.e., the perceptual registration of moral properties such as wrongness or dignity. In this article, I defend a view of moral perception as a process that involves imaginative apprehension of reality. It is meant as an adjustment to the dominant view of moral perception as moral properties perception and as an addition to existing Murdochian approaches to moral perception. The view I present here builds on Iris Murdoch’s moral psychology and holds that moral perception is an imaginative exploration of the particularity of concrete objects of moral reality (e.g., persons, situations, and events), rather than a registration of moral properties. I argue that such imaginative apprehension includes direct and reflective uses of imagination and that this process grounds experiential moral knowledge that serves the ultimate role of moral perception: getting a better grip on concrete objects of moral reality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, e.g., Audi 2013; Cowan 2015; Cullison 2010; Hutton 2022; McBrayer 2010; McGrath 2004; Werner 2020a, 2020b.

  2. There is no standard terminology. (a) is also known as ‘moral perception’ or ‘moral perceptualism’ (Werner 2019: 1).

  3. For other examples, see Audi 2013; Cullison 2010; Dancy 2010; Hutton 2022; Watkins and Jolley 2002.

  4. Hutton (2022: 583) suggests that Church (2013) might have come close having argued that “agents perceive moral properties by imagining different ways of proceeding from the current situation, under constraints provided by the moral principles they believe.” His central examples concern individuals that change their moral outlook after having a revelatory experience (e.g., Fred who gives up utilitarianism after being confronted by a fictional portrayal of slavery, an example from Werner 1983: 657–59). Hutton thinks Church’s account can’t explain cases as Fred’s as it concerns moral change that is provoked by experience, not by principle-based inference and concludes that linking imagination and moral perception is a dead end (Hutton 2022: 584). However, the analysis seems limited as it neglects other ways imaginings can have other contents. E.g., the imaginings of future possibilities of moral action that don’t have to be guided by principles (see, e.g., John Dewey’s (1922) concept of ‘dramatic rehearsal’ and ‘imaginings with moral contents’ reaching beyond moral properties (which I will discuss in the following sections).

  5. ‘Something other than oneself’ applies to more than just other human beings; Murdoch (2001: 83) suggested we find “self-forgetful pleasure in the sheer alien pointless independent existence of animals, birds, stones and trees.”

  6. Cordner (2016: 196) reacts against what he calls a “recurrent and revealing” misreading in Murdoch scholarship (he refers to Clarke 2012, Driver 2012, Millgram 2004) that understands Murdochian attention as attention to more details.

  7. Cordner (2016: 208; 213) suggests that Murdochian attention is not only receptiveness in the sense of “waiting-on, serving, answering to”, but that it “involves being present to another in a way that includes ‘letting oneself be seen or recognized’’’ as well. He agrees with Cavell (1969: 279) that “recognizing a person depends upon allowing oneself to be recognized by him” and Velleman (1999: 3) that “love disarms our emotional defenses; it makes us vulnerable to the other.” Murdoch’s (2001: 201) appraisal of the virtue of humility by which she concludes The Sovereignty of Good seems to confirm this interpretation; “The humble man, because he sees himself as nothing, can see other things as they are.”

  8. See Audi 2013 for the most explicit defense of supervenience in this context.

  9. Several other authors have argued that perceptual experience can be penetrated by different sorts of cognitive states, e.g., moods, desires, beliefs, and concepts. See, e.g., Macpherson 2012; Siegel 2010, 2012; Stokes 2012. For accounts that explicitly argue for conceptual mediation of perception, see Brewer 1999, McDowell 1994. Panizza (2020: 283) regards the cognitive penetration argument as a confirmation of Murdoch’s view that perception is “not mediated but enriched by concepts.”

  10. In Murdoch’s moral realism, the Good is a guiding ideal of which we have imperfect knowledge, which can be perfected by turning to concrete things in the world that function as ‘hints’ of the Good (see Panizza 2020: 280).

  11. Nussbaum’s focus is the literature of Henry James (and The Golden Bowl in particular). She only refers once to Murdoch’s Sovereignty of Good without further explanation.

  12. “We have another image of courage at forty from that which we had at twenty” (Murdoch 2001: 28).

  13. An anonymous reviewer expressed the worry that Nussbaum’s comparison of the literary and the moral imagination might turn an ordinary capacity as perception into a literary achievement, which would clash with Murdoch’s examples of the virtuous peasant or mothers of large families by which she seems to support a virtuous, but unexamined life (Murdoch 2001: 2, 51–52). However, I think this distinction between Nussbaum and Murdoch is not correct. Nussbaum’s argument is not that we should aestheticize our lives, but that moral knowledge requires imaginative moral perception. She uses Adam and Maggie’s example because she believes that these experiences written down by Henry James come closer to our actual moral experiences than moral-philosophical works that emphasize abstract concepts and principles. In addition, I do not think Murdoch regards virtuous peasants or mothers of large families as unimaginative individuals, but as individuals that are virtuously engaged with the concrete objects of moral reality that surround them (e.g., the peasant’s crops or animals or the mother’s children). I.e., as individuals who are less susceptible to having their truth-affirming imaginings corrupted by egocentric phantasies.

  14. How many of us have ever seen a cat being ignited?

  15. Diamond’s article was meant as a reply to Nussbaum’s article. She retraces the concept of adventure from Nussbaum’s article and an earlier article on James’ The Golden Bowl (Nussbaum 1983: 44). James (1934: 149) meant that a “human, a personal ‘adventure’ is “a name we conveniently give, after the fact, to any passage, to any situation, that has added the sharp taste of uncertainty to a quickened sense of life. Therefore the thing is, all beautifully, a matter of interpretation and of the particular conditions.”

  16. In the philosophy of perception, several arguments are offered for high-level properties figuring in perception. For defenders of philosophical liberalism, the view that perception includes complex properties as something being a pine tree or causation, see Bayne 2009, Siegel 2006. For criticism see, e.g., Byrne 2001, Carruthers and Veillet 2011.

  17. Cowan (2015) provided a similar argument to defend moral properties perception.

  18. See also Chappell 2009, 2014, 2022.

  19. Mylonaki distinguishes a Murdochian view of moral perception from what she calls object views (what I call accounts of moral properties perception here). Mylonaki (2019: 285) argues that, on a Murdochian view, moral perception is about “cognizing an individual reality (a reality graspable in historical and non universalizable concepts) and not an object (a reality graspable in universal terms).” We share the same idea that moral perception is not about registering a set of well-delineated moral facts but about getting a better grip on what I call concrete objects of moral reality or what she calls an ‘individual reality’. So when I use the term ‘object’, I simply refer to Murdoch’s (2001: 17) phrase of M being capable of “giving careful and just attention to an object that confronts her” (emphasis added). Chappell’s (2017: 284) notion of objectual knowledge should be understood in a similar way, as “knowledge of particular things.”

References

  • Audi, R. 2013. Moral perception. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T. 2009. Perception and the Reach of Phenomenal Content. Philosophical Quarterly 59(236): 385–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, B. 1999. Perception and reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Briscoe, R. E. 2011. Mental imagery and the varieties of amodal perception. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 92(2): 153–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. 2001. Intentionalism defended. Philosophical Review 110(2): 199–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P., and B. Veillet. 2011. The Case against Cognitive phenomenology. In Cognitive phenomenology, eds. T. Bayne, and M. Montague. 35–56. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cavell, S. 1969. The Avoidance of Love. In Cavell. Must We Mean What We Say? 267–353. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Chappell, S. G. 2009. Ethics beyond moral theory. Philosophical Investigations 32(3): 206–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chappell, S. G. 2014. Ethics and experience: life beyond moral theory. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chappell, S. G. 2017. Knowing what to do. Imagination, Virtue and Platonism in Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chappell, S. G. 2022. Epiphanies: an ethics of experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Church, J. 2013. Possibilities of perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, B. 2012. Iris Murdoch and the prospects for critical moral perception. In Iris Murdoch, Philosopher: a collection of essays, ed. J. Broackes. 227–254. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clifton, W. 2013. Murdochian moral perception. Journal of Value Inquiry 47(3): 207–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cordner, C. 2016. Lessons of Murdochian attention. Sophia 55(2): 197–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cowan, R. 2015. Perceptual intuitionism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 90(1): 164–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cullison, A. 2010. Moral perception. European Journal of Philosophy 18(2): 159–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. 2010. Moral Perception. Supplement to the Proceedings of The Aristotelian Society 84(1): 99–117.

  • Dewey, J. 1922/2002. Human Nature and Conduct. New York: Dover Publications.

  • Diamond, C. 1991. The realistic Spirit. Wittgenstein, Philosophy and the mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Driver, J. 2012. For every foot its own shoe: Method and moral theory in the philosophy of Iris Murdoch. In Iris Murdoch, Philosopher, ed. J. Broackes. 293–306. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faraci, D. 2015. A hard look at moral perception. Philosophical Studies 172: 2055–2072.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. 1977. The Nature of Morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, K. 2015. Rescue Boats? I’d Use Gunships to Stop Migrants. The Sun, 17 April, http://www.thesun.co.uk/sol/homepage/suncolumnists/katiehopkins/6414865/Katie-Hopkins-I-would-use-gunships-to-stop-migrants.html

  • Hutton, J. 2022. Moral Experience. Perception or emotion. Ethics 132(3): 570–597.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, H. 1934. The art of the Novel. New York: Scribners.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, H. 1966. The Golden Bowl. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linebaugh, K., and S. Lee. 2022. June 21. ‘We are helpless’: Indian heat wave hurts mango farmers - the journal. - WSJ podcasts. The Wall Street Journal. Retrieved December 28, 2022, from https://www.wsj.com/podcasts/the-journal/we-are-helpless-Indian-heat-wave-hurts-mango-farmers/47b40ffc-64be-47b8-8cf9-de63a9589a40

  • Macpherson, F. 2012. Cognitive penetration of Colour Experience: rethinking the issue in light of an indirect mechanism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 84(1): 24–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McBrayer, J. P. 2010. Moral perception and the causal objection. Ratio 23(3): 291–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. 1994. Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, S. 2004. Moral Knowledge by Perception. Philosophical Perspectives 18: 209–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKeever, S., and M. Ridge. 2006. Principled Ethics: Generalism as a Regulative Ideal. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Millgram, E. 2004. Kantian Crystallization. Ethics 114(3): 511–513.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murdoch, I. 1966. The Darkness of Practical Reason. Encounter: 46–50.

  • Murdoch, I. 1992. Metaphysics as a guide to morals. London: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murdoch, I. 1999a. The Sublime and the Good. In Existentialists and Mystics: Writings on Philosophy and Literature, ed. P. Conradi. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murdoch, I. 1999b. Metaphysics and Ethics. In Existentialists and Mystics: writings on Philosophy and Literature, ed. P. Conradi. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murdoch, I. 2001. The Sovereignty of Good. New York: Routledge.

  • Mylonaki, E. 2019. The individual in pursuit of the individual; a murdochian account of moral perception. Journal of Value Inquiry 53(4): 579–603.

  • Nanay, B. 2010. Perception and imagination: Amodal Perception as Mental Imagery. Philosophical Studies 150: 239–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. 1983. Flawed crystals: James’s the Golden Bowl and Literature as Moral Philosophy. New Literary History 15(1): 25–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. 1985. Finely aware and richly responsible: Moral attention and the Moral Task of Literature. The Journal of Philosophy 82(10): 516–529.

    Google Scholar 

  • Panizza, S. 2020. Moral Perception Beyond Supervenience: Iris Murdoch’s Radical Perspective. The Journal of Value Inquiry 54: 273–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reiland, I. 2021. On Experiencing Moral Properties. Synthese 198(1): 315–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. 2006. Which Properties Are Represented in Perception? In Perceptual Experience, eds. T.S. Gendler and J. Hawthorne, 481–503. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Siegel, S. 2010. The contents of visual experience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, S. 2012. Cognitive Penetrability and Perceptual Justification. Noûs 46(2): 201–222.

  • Stokes, D. 2012. Perceiving and desiring: a New look at the cognitive penetrability of experience. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition 158(2): 477–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Timm, U. 2005. My Brother’s Shadow. A Life and Death in the SS. Transl. A. Bell. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Grunsven, J. 2022. Enactivism and the paradox of moral perception. Topoi 41(2): 287–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, D. 1999. Love as a moral emotion. Ethics 109: 338–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Väyrynen, P. 2018. Doubts about moral perception. In Evaluative perception, eds. A. Berqvist, and R. Cowan. 109–128. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, M., and K. D. Jolley. 2002. Pollyanna Realism: Moral Perception and Moral Properties. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 80(1): 75–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weil, S. 1947/2002. Gravity and Grace. Transl. E. Crawford and M. von der Ruhr. London/New York: Routledge Classics.

  • Weil, S. 1950/1992. Waiting for God. Transl. E. Crawford. New York: Harper Perennial.

  • Werner, P. J. 2020a. Moral perception. Philosophy Compass 15(1): 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Werner, P. J. 2020b. Which Moral Properties are Eligible for Perceptual Awareness? Journal of Moral Philosophy 17(3): 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Werner, R. 1983. Ethical realism. Ethics 93(4): 653–679.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

Funded by FWO PhD Fellowship Fundamental Research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yanni Ratajczyk.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

This research contains no conflicts of interest, it involved no human participants or animals.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ratajczyk, Y. Moral Perception as Imaginative Apprehension. J Ethics (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-023-09462-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-023-09462-5

Keywords

Navigation